LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS
Jeffrey W. Bowlby
Applied Research Branch Human Resources Development Canada
John F Dovidio
Dep...
38 downloads
1346 Views
18MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS
Jeffrey W. Bowlby
Applied Research Branch Human Resources Development Canada
John F Dovidio
Department of Psychology Colgate University
Patrick J. Flinn
Alston and Bird LLP Atlanta, Georgia
Margaret Foddy
School of Psychological Science La Trobe University
Samuel L . Gaertner
Department of Psychology University of Delaware
Karen A . Hegtvedt
Department of Sociology Emory University
Gladys Kafati
Department of Psychology Colgate University
Neil]. MacKinnon
Department of Sociology and Anthropology University of Guelph
Phoebe Riches
School of Psychological Science La Trobe University
Cecilia L . Ridgeway
Department of Sociology Stanford University
Judith G. Smetana
Department of Clinical and Social Sciences in Psychology University of Rochester
Vii
vu i
LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS
Frans N . Stokman
ICS University of Groningen
John F. Stolte
Department of Sociology Northern Illinois University
Jonathan H. Turner
Department of Sociology University of California, Riverside
Marcel A .L .M . van Assen
ICS University of Groningen
Jelle van der Knoop
DECIDE University of Groningen
Reinier C.H. van Oosten
DECIDE University of Groningen
Henry A . Walker
Department of Sociology University of Arizona
Elaine Wethington
Departments of Human Development and of Sociology Cornell University
Morris Zelditch
Department of Sociology Stanford University
PREFACE
EDITORIAL POLICY Advances in Group Processes publishes theoretical analyses, reviews, and theorybased empirical chapters on group phenomena . The series adopts a broad conception of "group processes ." This includes work on groups ranging from the very small to the very large, and on classic and contemporary topics such as status, power, exchange, justice, influence, decision making, intergroup relations, and social networks . Contributors have included scholars from diverse fields including sociology, psychology, political science, philosophy, mathematics, and organizational behavior . The series provides an outlet for papers that may be longer, more theoretical, and/or more integrative than those published by standard journals . We place a premium on the development of testable theories and theory-driven research . Chapters in the following categories are especially apropos :
•
•
Conventional and unconventional theoretical work, from broad metatheoretical and conceptual analyses to refinements of existing theories and hypotheses . One goal of the series is to advance the field of group processes by promoting theoretical work . Papers that review and integrate programs of research . The current structure of the field often leads to the piecemeal publication of different parts of ix
x
PREFACE
•
a program of research . This series offers those engaged in programmatic research on a given topic an opportunity to integrate their published and unpublished work into a single paper, Review articles that transcend the author's own work are also of considerable interest . Papers that develop and apply social psychological theories and research to macro-sociological processes . One premise underlying this series is that links between macro- and micro-sociological processes warrant more systematic and testable theorizing . The series encourages development of the macro-sociological implications embedded in social psychological work on groups .
In addition the editors are open to submissions that depart from these guidelines .
CONTENTS OF VOLUME 17 This volume of Advances in Group Processes covers a broad section of theory and research . The first two chapters address stereotyping and discrimination . Both contributions emphasize the importance of intergroup relations in the production of seemingly intrapersonal phenomena. In their chapter "Group Identity and Intergroup Relations : The Common In-group Identity Model," Dovidio, Gaertner, and Kafati illustrate how the same social categorization processes that ordinarily lead to prejudice and discrimination, can also be used to reduce them . Their theoretical and empirical analyses suggest that cooperative intergroup contact can significantly alter the cognitive interpretations responsible for prejudice, stereotyping, and behavioral discrimination . The next chapter utilizes a distinct, yet somewhat complementary, theoretical perspective . In "The Affective Dynamics of Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations," MacKinnon and Bowlby show how affect control theory can be used to analyze the connections among stereotypes, intergroup attitudes, and discrimination . Three studies are shown to be consistent with hypotheses derived from the affect control model . Taken together, these two chapters do an especially nice job of extending and integrating research on prejudice and stereotyping . The next two papers deal with important theoretical issues concerning status in task groups . In "The Formation of Status Beliefs : Improving Status Construction Theory," Ridgeway explicates the basic logic of status construction theory . Upon reviewing the theory and evidence for status construction processes, Ridgeway offers a "belief formation" assumption to more formally explain how social interaction fosters consensual status beliefs . Next, Foddy and Riches extend a theory of status cues by specifying how task and categorical markers of status combine to alter social interaction . They argue that task-related cues (such as verbal fluency) can overwhelm the effect categorical membership cues (such as ethnic accent) when the two are opposed. The reason is that the former are more directly
Preface
xi
related to the task outcome . Two studies involving Anglo-Australian and Greek-Australian speakers were found to support the main hypotheses . Three papers tackle various aspects of power in bargaining and exchange . In "Strategic Decision Making," Stokman and collaborators describe a simulation-based methodology for analyzing decisions wherein stakeholders have differing priorities, values, and power capabilities . This technique uses empirical data gathered by subject area specialists to predict the decision process and outcome . Not only do these models generate highly accurate predictions, they also provide a strategic tool for analyzing the decision-making process and potential points of compromise . The next chapter represents an important follow-up to a theoretical paper that appeared in the first volume of Advances in Group Processes more than a decade ago. In "The Normative Regulation of Power," Zelditch and Walker analyze and examine theoretical propositions based on their elaboration of the Dornbush-Scott theory of authority . They report data from nine experiments which scrutinize various implications of the theory . An important finding is that internal self-restraint is a tenuous basis for the normative regulation of power-external constraints play a major role . This trio of papers is rounded out by Stolte's chapter titled `Beyond the Concept of Value in Power-Dependence Theory : Expanding a Model of the `Whole Actor ."' Here, Stolte takes on the important task of clarifying and extending Emerson's unfinished theory of value . His theoretical analysis yields important insights into the kinds of decisions that are based on rational deliberation, versus those guided by feelings and emotions . This analysis also raises important questions about the relationship between value and environmental uncertainty . Readers interested in rational choice theory and/or emotional processes should find Stolte's chapter especially provocative . The next chapter deals with conflict in familial relations . In "Cultural Contexts and Developmental Processes in Adolescent-Parent Relationships" Smetana describes a program of research directed at understanding adolescent-parent conflict within a broader normative context . It is argued that adolescents and parents experience conflict due to divergent perceptions and interpretations of important issues . In turn, these conflicts play an important role in modifying the overall family structure and furthering adolescent development . Data from European American, African American, and Chinese families are compared and contrasted to illustrate the similarities and differences in conflict across cultures . Two chapters deal with the spread or transmission of social phenomena . Wethington's chapter "Contagion of Stress" addresses how social stressors are spread from one area of life to another . Wethington catalogues the major types of stress contagion and reviews the primary theoretical perspectives that are used to understand them . She then discusses in unusually fine detail how these approaches may be improved, arguing for refined measurement procedures, a combination of qualitative and quantitative data, and longitudinal studies of the contagion process . Next, Hegtvedt and Flinn break fresh ground by pushing justice theory in new directions in their chapter titled "Intergenerational Justice and the Environment :
xii
PREFACE
Determining the Fair Use of Mono Basin Water ." They first theoretically assess how fair distributions come to be viewed as unfair, and detail how actors attempt to resolve competing justice claims . These ideas are then applied to the trans-generational distribution of natural resources . An insightful case study involving California water-rights litigation is offered to illustrate the principles involved . Finally, Jonathan H . Turner offers a broad-ranging conceptual framework for analyzing the relations between micro-, meso-, and macro-level forces . Turner claims that "embedded encounters" are shaped by the larger categorical and corporate units in which they occur. He then develops a number of testable propositions and shows how these might be useful for an array of sociological theorizing . The prospects and strategies for building multilevel theory are discussed . Shane R . Thye Edward J . Lawler Michael W . Macy Henry A . Walker Volume Co-Editors
GROUP IDENTITY AND INTERGROUP RELATIONS THE COMMON IN-GROUP IDENTITY MODEL
John F . Dovidio, Samuel L . Gaertner, and Gladys Kafati
ABSTRACT Discrimination is an intergroup as well as an interpersonal phenomenon and is related to fundamental processes associated with social categorization and the development of in-group favoritism . We propose in the Common In-Group Identity Model that by understanding the factors that underlie the development of these intergroup biases, these forces can be redirected to improve intergroup relations . In particular, if members of different groups are induced to recategorize themselves as a superordinate group rather than as two separate groups, intergroup prejudice, stereotyping, and discrimination will be reduced through the extension of pro-in-group bias to former out-group members . Moreover, recategorization in the form of a dual identity, in which superordinate and subgroup identities are both salient, can achieve the benefits of a strong superordinate identity without requiring groups to forsake valued ethnic and racial identities . Data reported from laboratory studies, field experiments, and surveys involving a range of different types of groups offer converging evidence in support of the model .
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 1-35 . Copyright m 2000 by JAI Press Inc. All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 1
2
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
Overt expressions of prejudice have declined significantly over the past 35 years (Dovidio and Gaertner 1986, 1998 ; Schuman, Steeh, Bobo, and Krysan 1997) . To the extent that prejudice causes intergroup biases (Dovidio . Brigham, Johnson, and Gaertner 1996), corresponding reductions in discrimination would be expected to occur . However, discrimination is shaped by more than personal prejudice (e .g ., LaPiere 1934) . Discrimination is an intergroup as well as an interpersonal phenomenon . Thus, more comprehensive perspectives and strategies for combating discrimination need to consider the nature of the relations between groups as well as between persons . The present chapter therefore examines the role of intergroup processes in both generating and also potentially in improving intergroup relations . In particular, we propose that intergroup contact can reduce social biases by changing the way people view the relations between groups .
THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVES ON RACE RELATIONS Psychological and sociological approaches to race relations have traditionally reflected different perspectives . Psychological theories have commonly emphasized the role of the individual, in terms of personality and attitude, in social biases and discrimination (see Duckitt 1992 ; Jones 1997) . Traditional psychological theories, such as the work on the authoritarian personality (Adorno, Frenkel-Brunswik, Levinson, and Sanford 1950), have considered the role of dysfunctional processes on the overt expression of social biases . In addition, contemporary approaches, such as aversive racism and symbolic racism perspectives, have considered the contributions of normal processes (e .g., socialization and social cognition) in the expression of subtle, and often unconscious, biases (Dovidio and Gaertner 1996, 1998 ; Gaertner and Dovidio 1986a ; Kovel 1970 ; Sears 1988) . Sociological theories, in contrast, have frequently emphasized the role of large-scale social and structural dynamics in intergroup relations in general, and in race relations in particular (Blauner 1972 ; Bonacich 1972 ; Wilson 1978) . These theories have considered the dynamics of race relations largely in economic and class-based terms-and often to the exclusion of individual influences (see Bobo 1999) . Despite the existence of such divergent views, both sociological and psychological approaches have converged to recognize the importance of understanding group functions and collective identies on race relations (see Bobo 1999) . Blumer (1958a, 1958b, 1965a, 1965b), for instance, offered a sociologically based approach in which group competition and threat are fundamental processes in the development and maintenance of social biases . Blumer (1958a) wrote : "Race prejudice is a defensive reaction to such challenging of the sense of group position . . . . As such, race prejudice is a protective device . It functions, however shortsightedly, to preserve the integrity and position of the dominant group" (p . 5) . From a psychological orientation, Sherif, Harvey, White, Hood, and Sherif (1961)
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
3
similarly proposed in their classic Robbers Cave study that the functional relations between groups is the critical factor determining intergroup attitudes . According to this position, which is related to realistic conflict theory (Bobo 1988 ; Bobo and Hutchings 1996), competition between groups produces prejudice and discrimination, whereas intergroup interdependence and cooperative interaction that result in successful outcomes reduce intergroup bias . Discrimination can serve less tangible collective functions as well as concrete instrumental objectives . Blumer (1958a) acknowledged that the processes for establishing group position may involve goals such as gaining economic advantage, but they may also be associated with the acquisition of intangible resources such as prestige . Theoretical developments in social psychology, stimulated by Social Identity Theory (Tajfel and Turner 1979), further highlight the role of group categorization, independent of actual realistic group conflict, on motivations to achieve favorable group identities ("positive distinctiveness") and consequently on the arousal of intergroup bias and discrimination . Personal prejudice and stereotypes, realistic group threat, and symbolic threats reflect different hypothesized causes of discrimination, but they can operate jointly to motivate discriminatory behavior . Bobo and his colleagues (see Bobo 1999) have demonstrated that group threat and personal prejudice can contribute independently to discrimination against other groups . W . Stephan and his colleagues (Stephan and Stephan 2000 ; Stephan, Ybarra, Martinez, Schwartzwald, and Tur-Kaspa 1998) have also found that personal negative stereotypes, realistic group threat, and symbolic group threat all predict discrimination against other groups (e .g ., immigrants), and each accounts for a unique portion of the effect . The independence of these effects points to different underlying mechanisms . In this chapter we examine how group representations and identities influence the nature of race relations .
INTERPERSONAL AND INTERGROUP PROCESSES The operation of group-level processes is hypothesized to be dynamically distinct from the influence of individual-level processes . Different modes of functioning are involved, and these modes critically influence how people perceive others and experience their own sense of identity . In terms of perceptions of others, for example, Brewer (1988 ; see also Fiske and Neuberg's 1990 Continuum Model) has proposed a "dual process model of impression formation ." The primary distinction in this model is between two types of processing : person based and category based . Person-based processing is bottom-up . It is data-driven, involving the piecemeal acquisition of information that begins "at the most concrete level and stops at the lowest level of abstraction required by the prevailing processing objectives" Brewer 1988, p . 6) . Category-based processing, in contrast, proceeds from global to specific ; it is top-down . In top-down processing, how the external
4
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
reality is perceived and experienced is influenced by category-based, subjective impressions . According to Brewer, category-based processing is more likely to occur than person-based processing, because social information is typically organized around social categories . With respect to one's sense of identity, Social Identity Theory (Tajfel and Turner 1979) and Self-Categorization Theory (Turner 1985) view the distinction between personal identity and social identity as a critical one . When personal identity is salient, a person's individual needs, standards, beliefs, and motives primarily determine behavior. In contrast, when social identity is salient, "people come to perceive themselves as more interchangeable exemplars of a social category than as unique personalities defined by their individual differences from others" (Turner, Hogg, Oakes, Reicher and Wetherell 1987, p . 50) . Under these conditions, collective needs, goals, and standards are primary . Illustrating the dynamics of this distinction, Verkuyten and Hagendoom (1998) found that when individual identity was primed, individual differences in authoritarianism were the major predictor of the prejudice of Dutch students toward Turkish migrants . In contrast, when social identity (i .e ., national identity) was made salient, in-group stereotypes and standards primarily predicted prejudiced attitudes . Thus, whether personal or collective identity is more salient critically shapes how a person perceives, interprets, evaluates, and responds to situations and to others (Kawakami and Dion 1993, 1995) . In general, the social categorization of others and oneself plays a significant role in prejudice and discrimination . We propose, in the Common Ingroup Identity Model, that appropriately engineered social categorization during group contact can play an important role in the reduction of social biases.
SOCIAL CATEGORIZATION AND BIAS Models of category-based processing (Brewer 1988 ; see also Fiske and Neuberg 1990) assume that "the mere presentation of a stimulus person activates certain classification processes that occur automatically and without conscious intent . . . . The process is one of 'placing' the individual social object along well-established stimulus dimensions such as age, gender, and skin color" (Brewer 1988, pp . 5-6) . We have further hypothesized that "a primitive type of categorization may also have a high probability of spontaneously occurring, perhaps in parallel process . This is the categorization of individuals as members of one's ingroup or not" (Dovidio and Gaertner 1993, p . 170) . Because of the centrality of the self in social perception (Higgins and Bargh 1987 ; Kihlstrom et al . 1988), we propose that social categorization involves most fundamentally a distinction between the group containing the self, the in-group, and other groups, the out-groupsbetween the "we's" and the "they' s" (see also Tajfel and Turner 1979 ; Turner et al . 1987) . This distinction has a profound influence on evaluations, cognitions, and behavior .
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
5
Upon social categorization of individuals into in-groups and out-groups, people favor in-group members directly in terms of evaluations and resource allocations (Tajfel, Billig, Bundy, and Flament 1971), as well as indirectly in valuing the products of their work (Ferguson and Kelley 1964) . Also, in-group membership increases the psychological bond and feelings of "oneness" that facilitates the arousal of promotive tension or empathy in response to their needs or problems (Hornstein 1976) . In part as a consequence, prosocial behavior is offered more readily to in-group than to out-group members (Dovidio et al . 1997 ; Piliavin, Dovidio, Gaertner, and Clark 1981) . In addition people are more likely to be cooperative and exercise more personal restraint when using endangered common resources when these are shared with in-group members than with others (Kramer and Brewer 1984) . In terms of information processing, people retain information in a more detailed fashion for in-group members than for out-group members (Park and Rothbart 1980), have better memory for information about ways in-group members are similar and out-group members are dissimilar to the self (Wilder 1981), and remember more positive information about in-group than out-group members (Howard and Rothbart 1982) . Moreover, people are more generous and forgiving in their explanations for the behaviors of in-group relative to out-group members . Positive behaviors and successful outcomes are more likely to be attributed to internal, stable characteristics (the personality) of in-group than out-group, whereas members negative outcomes are more likely to be ascribed to the personalities of out-group members than of in-group members (Hewstone 1990) . Relatedly, observed behaviors of in-group and out-group members are encoded in memory at different levels of abstraction (Maass, Salvi, Arcuri and Semin 1989) . Undesirable actions of outgroup members are encoded at more abstract levels that presume intentionality and dispositional origin (e .g ., she is hostile) than identical behaviors of in-group members (e .g ., she slapped the girl) . Desirable actions of out-group members, however, are encoded at more concrete levels (e .g ., she walked across the street holding the old man's hand) relative to the same behaviors of in-group members (e .g ., she is helpful) . Because abstract schemas are resistant to modification, these biases lead to a persistence of more positive cognitions and evaluations about ingroup than out-group members . Thus, in-group/out-group categorization not only initiates bias, but it also helps to maintain biases . Given the centrality and spontaneity of the social categorization of people into in-group and out-group members, how can bias be reduced? One of the most influential strategies involves creating and structuring intergroup contact .
INTERGROUP CONTACT AND THE REDUCTION OF BIAS Over the past half-century, Allport's (1954) revised Contact Hypothesis has been a guiding framework for strategies designed to reduce intergroup bias and conflict
6
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
(Pettigrew 1998) . This hypothesis proposes that simple contact between groups is not automatically sufficient to improve intergroup relations . Rather, for contact between groups to reduce bias successfully certain prerequisite features must be present. These characteristics of contact include equal status between the groups, cooperative (rather than competitive) intergroup interaction, opportunities for personal acquaintance between the members, especially with those whose personal characteristics do not support stereotypic expectations, and supportive norms by authorities within and outside of the contact situation . Although it is difficult to establish all of these conditions in intergroup contact situations, this formula is effective when these conditions are met (Cook 1984 ; Johnson, Johnson, and Maruyama 1983 ; Pettigrew 1998) . Recent approaches have extended research on the Contact Hypothesis by attempting to understand the potential common processes and mechanisms that these diverse factors engage to reduce bias (Brewer and Miller 1984) . For example, when intergroup contact is favorable and has successful consequences, psychological processes that restore cognitive balance or reduce dissonance produce more favorable attitudes toward members of the other group and toward the group as a whole to be consistent with the positive nature of the interaction . Also, the rewarding properties of achieving success may become associated with members of other groups, thereby increasing attraction (Gaertner et al . 1999) . Intergroup contact can also influence how interactants conceive of the groups and how the members are socially categorized . Cooperative learning and jigsaw classroom interventions (Aronson and Patnoe 1997), which are designed to increase interdependence between members of different groups and to enhance appreciation for the resources they bring to the task, may reduce bias in part by altering how interactants conceive of the group boundaries and memberships .
CONTACT, CATEGORIZATION, AND IDENTITY As we have argued earlier (Gaertner, Dovidio, Anastasio, Bachman, and Rust 1993), the factors specified by the Contact Hypothesis may reduce bias through the process of reducing the salience of the intergroup boundaries or redefining group boundaries . The former process refers to decategorization, whereas the latter process involves recategorization . Decategorization and Personalization
From the perspective of decategorization strategies, intergroup interaction under the conditions specified by the Contact Hypothesis can individuate members and reduce the salience of intergroup boundaries . Interventions that reveal variability in the opinions of out-group members or have out-group members
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
7
respond as individuals rather than as a group renders each member more distinctive and thus weakens the prior categorization scheme (Wilder 1986) . Increasing the perception that both in-group and out-group members are "separate individuals" rather than part of a "we-they" categorization scheme further reduces bias by undermining the effects of pro-in-group biases in evaluations, cognitions, and behavior. Another decategorization strategy of repeatedly criss-crossing category memberships by forming new subgroups each composed of members from former subgroups changes the pattern of who is "in" and who is "out" can also weaken the effects of prior categorization (Urban and Miller 1998) . Brewer and Miller (1984) offered a potentially unifying theoretical framework that posits that the features specified by the Contact Hypothesis (e .g ., equal status, cooperative interaction, self-revealing interaction, and supportive norms) share the capacity to decategorize group boundaries and to promote more differentiated and personalized conceptions, particularly of out-group members . Brewer and Miller propose that personalization, involving the exchange of personal information, can complement and enhance the impact of decategorization . With a more differentiated representation of outgroup members, there is the recognition that there are different types of out-group members, thereby weakening the effects of categorization and its subsequent effects on intergroup bias . During this personalization process, interactants focus on information about an out-group member that is relevant to the self (as an individual rather than self as a group member) . Repeated personalized interactions with a variety of out-group members can, over time, undermine the value of the category stereotype as a source of information about members of that group . The effects of personalization may therefore generalize to new situations as well as to other out-group members who are not present during the intergroup contact situation (Bettencourt, Brewer, Croak, and Miller 1992 ; Marcus-Newhall, Holtz, and Brewer 1993 ; Miller, Brewer, and Edwards 1985) . Thus, intergroup contact can reduce bias in both an immediate and generalizable fashion (see also, Pettigrew 1997) . In addition to decategorization, we propose that the features specified by the Contact Hypothesis also reduce bias through recategorization that increases rather than decreases the level of category inclusiveness (Gaertner et al . 1993, 1994, 1996) . That is, these contact conditions facilitate a reduction in bias, in part, because they share the capacity to transform members' representations of the memberships from separate groups to more inclusive social entity . However, we do not necessarily consider the decategorization and recategorization frameworks to be completely mutually exclusive theoretically ; we believe them to be capable of working in parallel and complementary ways . Given the complexity of intergroup attitudes, it is plausible that these features of contact operate through several related as well as different pathways .
8
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI Recategorization
Recategorization, as represented by our own work on the Common In-group Identity Model, involves interventions to change people's conceptions of the memberships from different groups to one, more inclusive group (Gaertner et al . 1993) . The model is rooted in the social categorization perspective of intergroup behavior and recognizes the central role of social categorization in reducing as well as in creating intergroup bias (Tajfel and Turner 1979) . Specifically, if members of different groups are induced to conceive of themselves more as a single, superordinate group rather than as two separate groups, attitudes toward former
Conditions of Contact
Representational Mediators
Consequences
Intergroup Interdependence (e.g., joint outcomes)
One Group Recategorization ("We")
Evaluative Consequences (e.g., prejudice)
Group Differentiation (e.g., similarity) Environmental Context (e.g, egalitarian norms) Pre-Contact Experience (e.g., affective priming)
Two Subgroups
in One Group Recategorization ("Us+Them =We") Two Groups Categorization ("We/They") Separate Individuals Decategorization ("Me/You") /
Cognitive Effects (e.g., stereotyping)
Behavioral Effects (e.g., helping)
Figure 1 . Within the Common In-group Identity Model, elements of an intergroup contact situation (e .g, intergroup interdependence) influence cognitive representations of the groups as one superordinate group (recategorization), as two subgroups in one group (recategorization involving a dual identity), as two groups (categorization), or as separate individuals (decategorization) . Recategorization and decategorization, in turn, can both reduce cognitive (e .g., beliefs), affective (e .g ., feelings of empathy), and behavioral (e .g ., helping) biases, but in different ways .
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
9
out-group members will become more positive through processes involving pro-in-group bias . As noted earlier, categorization of a person as an in-group member rather than as an out-group member has been demonstrated to produce more positive evaluations and to influence systematically how people process information in ways that reinforce these favorable attitudes . For instance, changing the basis of categorization from race to an alternative dimension can alter who is a "we" and who is a "they," thus undermining racial biases . Thus, cooperative relationships between group, such as those established in Sherif and colleague's (1961) Robbers Cave study, can reduce bias not only by ameliorating realistic group threat but also by establishing a more inclusive, superordinate group identity (Gaertner et al . 2000) . The Common In-group Identity Model is presented schematically in Figure 1 . On the left, situational factors and interventions, such as intergroup interdependence (which produces cooperative behavior) and group similarities or differences, are hypothesized to influence cognitive representations of the memberships (center) as one group (recategorization), two subgroups in one group or on the same team (recategorization with a dual identity), as two groups (categorization), or as separate individuals (decategorization) . Within the model, intergroup cognition involved in social categorization is the critical mediator of subsequent intergroup attitudes and behavior . The model recognizes that recategorization and decategorization strategies can both reduce prejudice, but in different ways . Recategorization, either in terms of a one group or dual identity representation, reduces bias by extending the benefits of in-group favoritism to former out-group members . Attitudes and behavior toward these former outgroup members thus become more favorable, approaching those toward in-group members . Decategorization, in contrast, reduces favoritism toward original ingroup members as they become perceived as separate individuals rather than as members of one's own group .
INTERGROUP CONTACT AND THE COMMON IN-GROUP IDENTITY MODEL As illustrated in Figure 1, we hypothesize that interventions in intergroup contact situations designed to produce a recategorization of people from members of different groups to members of a common group can have a significant impact on intergroup attitudes (prejudice), stereotypes, and behavior . We summarize empirical evidence consistent with the basic propositions of the model . Intergroup Attitudes Cooperative interaction, which results from intergroup interdependence and superordinate goals, is one of the most powerful and robust aspects of intergroup
10
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
contact for reducing bias (Sherif and Sherif 1969) . From our perspective, cooperative interaction may enhance positive evaluations of out-group members, at least in part, by transforming interactants' representations of the memberships from two groups to one group . To test this hypothesis directly, we conducted a laboratory experiment that brought two three-person laboratory groups together under conditions designed to vary independently the members' representations of the aggregate as one group or two groups and the presence or absence of intergroup cooperative interaction (Gaertner, Mann, Dovidio, Murrell, and Pomare 1990) . To develop separate group identities and allegiances, participants first worked on a problem-solving task in three-person groups, unaware of the existence of the other group . We then arranged contact between the groups on another problemsolving task (involving survival in the wilderness) in which structural aspects of the situation were designed to emphasize separate or common group identity (e .g ., segregated or integrated seating ; original group names or a new group name for all six participants) . In addition, we manipulated whether the outcome (and potential reward) for their solution to would be evaluated independently for the two three-person groups or jointly for the six-person group . After the interaction, participants evaluated original in-group and out-group members . The "groupness" and the independent/joint outcome manipulations both reduced intergroup bias . Moreover, even when the groups had independent outcomes, participants induced to feel like one group relative to those whose separate group identities were reinforced reported that the aggregate did feel more like one group . They also had lower degrees of intergroup bias in their evaluations of ingroup and out-group members . Consistent with our hypothesis about how interdependent outcomes reduces bias among participants induced to feel like two groups, the information that the joint solution developed by the six-person group would be evaluated increased the extent to which the participants felt like they belonged to one group. Feelings of belonging to one group, in turn, mediated reduced levels of bias in evaluative ratings . Also supportive of the Common Ingroup Identity Model (see also Brewer 1979), reduced bias associated with introducing interdependent outcomes was due to enhanced favorable evaluations of out-group members . More direct support for the hypothesized mediating role of cognitive representations was revealed by the multiple regression mediation approach, a form of path analysis . The results are presented in Figure 2 . The coefficients associated with the paths are standardized beta weights . This analysis indicated that the influence of interdependent relative to independent outcomes on more positive evaluations of out-group members was substantially reduced (i .e ., from a beta of .62 to one of .09 ; see Figure 2) when the mediating effects of group representations and perceptions of cooperation and competition were considered . Furthermore, consistent with our model, among these potential mediators, only the one-group representation related independently to evaluations of out-group members . That is, intergroup interdependence improved attitudes toward the out-
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
11
Individuals
.03
-.59 -.74 i \
Interdependent/ Independent Outcomes
Different Groups
One Group
26
/
~~
. •~-r''r,
Attitudes Toward Outgroup
.80
Cooperation t
I .62 Note :
.09
Thick arrows indicate statistically significant paths (p < .05)
Figure 2.
The mediating role of cognitive representations in the effects of cooperation on the reduction of intergroup bias .
group, and thereby reduced intergroup bias, primarily indirectly by producing more inclusive, one-group representations . The advantage of this experimental design is that interdependence preceded changes in participants' representations of the aggregate from two groups to one group and also changes in intergroup bias . In addition, because we manipulated the representations of the aggregate in the absence of interdependence, the development of a one-group representation preceded changes in intergroup bias . Thus, we can be confident about the directions of causality in this study . In other experiments we have manipulated structural aspects of intergroup contact situations, such as segregated or integrated seating, and found that these manipulations directly influenced group representations and, ultimately, intergroup bias (Gaertner and Dovidio 1986b ; Gaertner, Mann, Murrell, and Dovidio 1989) . Taken together, these studies provide convergent evidence for a clear sequence of events and identification of causal relations . In a second series of studies we utilized survey techniques under more naturalistic circumstances . The advantage of these studies is that they may provide more externally valid evidence related to enduring and meaningful groups, often with histories of conflict . One of these studies involved a survey of black, Chinese, Hispanic, Japanese, Korean, Vietnamese, and Caucasian students attending a multi-ethnic high school in the northeastern United States (see Gaertner et al . 1994, 1996) . The primary theoretical question we pursued in this study was
12
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
whether students' perceptions of the student body as one group, different groups "playing on the same team," or separate groups would mediate the proposed relation between their perceptions of the favorableness of the conditions of contact (e .g ., cooperative interaction, equal status ; see Green, Adams, and Turner 1988) and their degrees of intergroup bias . Contact Hypothesis items measuring participants' perceptions of equal status between the groups included items such as, "Teachers at this school are fair to all groups of students ." Group representations were assessed with items such as, "Despite the different groups at school, there is frequently a sense that we are just one group ." One index of intergroup bias included items designed to assess feelings (good, uneasy, bad, respectful) toward one's own ethnic group relative to each of the other ethnic groups . Another index involved rating each ethnic/racial group on a modified "feelings thermometer" (see Abelson, Kinder, Peters, and Fiske 1982 ; Esses, Haddock, and Zanna 1993) . The findings were consistent with the processes we hypothesized in the Common In-group Identity Model . More favorable perceptions of the conditions of intergroup contact predicted stronger representations of the student body as one group and as different groups on the same team, but weaker representations as separate groups . Cognitive representations, in turn, predicted bias . The more the student body was perceived to be one group or different groups on the same team, the lower the bias in affective reactions . The more the student body was perceived as different groups, the greater the bias in favorability . We conducted two additional survey studies of intergroup relations in different contexts-banking mergers (Bachman 1993) and blended families from remarriage (Banker and Gaertner 1998) . In these studies Contact Hypothesis items were adapted, for example, to measure participants' perceptions of equal status between the groups in each context (e .g., "Employees from [the participants' company] and [the other organization] are seen as equal members of the merged organization" for banking mergers ; "My stepparent treats me, my siblings and step-siblings equally" for blended families) . The findings of these studies offered converging support for the hypothesis that the features specified by the Contact Hypothesis improve evaluations of out-group members and decrease intergroup bias by changing members' representations of the groups . In particular, perceptions of more favorable conditions of intergroup contact predicted more inclusive, one-group representations . These representations, in turn, mediated more positive interorganizational and interfamily attitudes . Stereotypes In addition to our evidence that a common superordinate identity increases positive evaluations of people who would otherwise be regarded as out-group members, other researchers (Maass, Ceccarelli, and Rudin 1996 ; Study 2) have demonstrated its capacity to reduce subtle linguistic biases the serve to perpetuate stereotypes (Maass, Ceccarelli, and Rudin 1996 ; Study 2) . Maass and colleagues
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
13
gave northern and southern Italians living in Switzerland messages that emphasized the differentiation between northern and southern Italians (in a two-groups condition), or between Italians and the Swiss (in a superordinate "Italian" condition) . These participants were then shown cartoons depicting northern and southern Italians performing positive and negative behaviors . Participants were then asked to choose one of four response alternatives corresponding to the four levels of abstraction (see Semin and Fiedler 1988) . When the distinction between northern and southern Italians was emphasized, the results replicated the linguistic bias effect . Higher levels of abstraction were used to describe positive behaviors of in-group members (e .g ., she is helpful) than for out-group members (e .g ., she walked with the old lady) . Also, higher levels of abstraction were used to describe undesirable behavior of out-group members than for in-group members . This linguistic bias was not evident in the superordinate identity condition . Thus, a superordinate identity fundamentally changed the way behavioral information about in-group and out-group members was processed and importantly, in a way that reduced this subtle bias in information processing . In addition, research by Karpinski and Von Hippel (1996) revealed that this linguistic bias mediates the extent to which people maintain stereotypic expectancies in the face of disconfirming information . Thus, the development of a common in-group identity can not only reduce general intergroup prejudice but also, by reducing intergroup linguistic bias, can help to change intergroup stereotypes . Intergroup Behaviors
In addition to producing more positive intergroup attitudes and reducing prejudice, the development of a common in-group identity can facilitate more positive intergroup behaviors and thus reduce discrimination . Although the connection between positive intergroup attitudes and behaviors seems intuitive, the extension from evaluative bias to intergroup behavior is not a trivial one . As we noted at the beginning of this chapter, discrimination is shaped by more than prejudice . Indeed, the empirical relationship between evaluative bias and is not particularly strong . In a review of the literature regarding the relationship between racial prejudice and racial discrimination by whites, Dovidio and colleagues (1996) found that the correlation was significant but relatively modest in magnitude (r = .32) . In addition, Struch and Schwartz (1989) demonstrated that intergroup bias and intergroup aggression were virtually unrelated (r = .07) and had different antecedents . The variables that predicted intergroup aggression strongly, such as perceived conflict and trait inhumanity, predicted intergroup bias only weakly, if at all. Struch and Schwartz (1989) concluded, "These results make clear the danger of generalizing from research on in-group favoritism to intergroup aggression" (p . 371) . Thus, in another set of studies we focused the consequences of promoting a common in-group identity for positive behavioral interactions between groups .
14
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
Although, as Struch and Schwartz's (1989) work demonstrates, intergroup bias and intergroup behavior may have different antecedents, the development of a common in-group identity is likely to influence both evaluations and positive forms of intergroup interaction . With respect to helping, theoretically several factors could contribute to the effects of recategorization on intergroup helping . Recategorization could operate indirectly through several interpersonal processes . Recategorization of a person as an in-group member increases perceptions of shared beliefs (e .g ., Brown 1984; Wilder 1984) . The perception of greater interpersonal similarity, in turn, typically facilitates helping (see Dovidio 1984) . In addition, recategorization may facilitate empathic arousal, whereby a person's motivational system becomes coordinated to the needs of another (Hornstein 1976 ; Piliavin et al . 1981), which may motivate helpful and sometimes altruistic actions (see Batson 1991) . Intergroup processes, as well as interpersonal processes, can promote helping . Hornstein and his colleagues (Flippen, Hornstein, Siegal, and Weitzman 1996 ; Hornstein 1976 ; Hornstein, Masor, Sole, and Heilman 1971) have demonstrated that recognition of common group membership increases helping beyond the mere effects of interpersonal similarity or attraction . Hornstein and his colleagues (Hornstein 1976 ; Sole, Marton, and Hornstein 1975) proposed that factors such as similarity or common fate may give rise to a sense of "we-ness"-a sense of belonging to a common group . This sense of we-ness, in turn, leads to more positive behaviors such as helping, particularly under conditions of threat (Dovidio and Morris 1975 ; Flippen et al . 1996) . Sole and colleagues (1975) suggested that developing this sense of we-ness facilitated helping toward others independent of interpersonal attraction . It is possible that the development of a common in-group identity (the sense of "we-ness") could also facilitate other forms of positive social interaction, such as the exchange of more self-disclosing information among members of the recategorized superordinate group . Recategorization fundamentally involves a more inclusive redefinition of the in-group boundary, and self-disclosure is intimately involved in the regulation of interpersonal boundaries . According to Derlega, Metts, Petronio, and Margulis (1993), "It is useful to consider adjustments in self-disclosure outputs and inputs as similar to the opening and closing of 'boundaries"' (p . 67) . Self-disclosure and interpersonal closeness are reciprocally related. Self-disclosure communicates a desire for intimacy and promotes closeness (Altman and Taylor 1973) ; in turn, as the closeness of the relationship between interactants increases, self-disclosure increases (Dindia and Allen 1992) and can produce even greater involvement with the other person (Davis 1976 ; Derlega and Chaikin 1976 ; Shaffer, Pegalis, and Bazzini 1996). Thus, creating a common in-group identity may produce a bond of closeness that facilitates greater self-disclosure (Derlega et al . 1993), as well as greater trust, trustworthiness, and cooperativeness (Kramer and Brewer 1984) . We therefore hypothesized that recategorization from two groups to one superordinate group would increase both
Group Identity and Intergroup
Relations
15
helping and self-disclosure between members of former out-groups (see Dovidio et al . 1997) . Following the basic paradigm of Gaertner and colleagues (1990) for manipulating group representations (described earlier), members of two three-person laboratory groups were brought together under conditions (e .g ., integrated or segregated seating, same or different t-shirts) designed to induce them to conceive of themselves as one group or to reinforce their separate group identities . Then, some participants were given an opportunity to help or to engage in a self-disclosing interaction with an in-group or an out-group member . For helping, participants listened individually to an audio-recording of another student (described as either an over or under-estimator, from a previous session) describe how illness had prevented her from completing an important survey of student life for a committee on which she served . Subsequently, participants received a note ostensibly from this person that contained an appeal to help her by placing posters recruiting volunteers to participate in the survey in various locations across campus . The other participants were engaged in a self-disclosure task in which they were asked to discuss the topic, "What do I fear most?" During this task, subjects interacted with either an in-group or out-group member who participated earlier in their session . The results for the helping and self-disclosure measures converged to support predictions from our model . In each case, the bias favoring in-group members, which was present in the two-groups condition, was eliminated for those induced to regard the aggregate as one group . We found further evidence of the benefits of emphasizing a common in-group identity on interracial helping in a field experiment (Ward, Rust, Nier, Gaertner, and Carpenter 1995) . In this study, which was conducted at the University of Delaware football stadium prior to a game between the University of Delaware and Westchester State University, black and white male and female students approached white fans from both universities just before the fans entered the stadium . These fans were asked if they would be willing to be interviewed about their food preferences . Our student interviewers wore either a University of Delaware or Westchester State University hat . By selecting fans who similarly wore clothing that identified their university affiliation, we systematically varied whether fans and our interviewers had common or different university identities in a context in which we expected university identities to be particularly salient . Consistent with the results of our laboratory experiment, white fans' helping behavior toward a black confederate was significantly influenced by making the common university identity salient . The black confederates were helped with the interviewer more when they visibly shared the common group identity than when they did not (60% versus 38%) . The white confederates were helped equivalently across the two conditions (43% versus 40%) . These fans were obviously not color-blind : Only black interviewers who shared common university affiliation with the fans-and who presumably voluntarily assimilated to the fans' salient group identity-were given especially high levels of assistance .
16
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
These effects of recategorization on both helping and self-disclosure have practical, as well as theoretical, implications . They suggest that recategorization manipulations can help to create interactions among group members in the contact situation that can activate other processes, which can subsequently promote more positive intergroup behaviors and attitudes . In particular, both self-disclosure and helping typically produce reciprocity . More intimate self-disclosure by one person normally encourages more intimate disclosure by the other (Archer and Berg 1978 ; Derlega et al . 1993) . As we discussed earlier, the work of Miller, Brewer, and their colleagues (e .g ., Brewer and Miller 1984 ; Miller et al . 1985) has demonstrated that personalized and self-disclosing interaction can be a significant factor in itself in reducing intergroup bias . Considerable cross-cultural evidence also indicates the powerful influence of the norm of reciprocity on helping (Schroeder, Penner, Dovidio, and Piliavin 1995) . According to this norm, people should help those who have helped them, and they should not help those who have denied them help for no legitimate reason (Gouldner 1960) . Thus, the development of a common in-group identity can motivate interpersonal behaviors between members of initially different groups that can initiate reciprocal actions and concessions (see Deutsch 1993 ; Osgood 1962) that will not only reduce immediate tensions but can produce more harmonious intergroup relations beyond the contact situation . Although finely differentiated impressions of out-group members may not be an automatic consequence of forming a common in-group identity, these more elaborated, differentiated, and personalized impressions can quickly develop because the newly formed positivity bias is likely to encourage more open communication (Gaertner et al . 1993) . The development of a common in-group identity creates a motivational foundation for constructive intergroup relations which can act as a catalyst for positive reciprocal interpersonal actions . Thus, the recategorization strategy proposed in our model and decategorization strategies, such as individuating (Wilder 1984) and personalizing (Brewer and Miller 1984) interactions, can potentially operate complementarily and sequentially to improve intergroup relations in lasting and meaningful ways . More positive interpersonal and intergroup relations, which predict more inclusive group representations, may not only relate to more positive attitudes toward others but also more favorable feelings about and commitment to one's organization or institution. Both individually and socially, this commitment can have important consequences . For instance, attrition rate is a serious issue for students of color on college campuses (Steele 1997) with between 50 and 60 percent of black and Hispanic college students dropping out of college before receiving their degree (Carter and Wilson 1997 ; Stangor and Sechrist 1998) . Institutional commitment is an important predictor, over and above academic performance, of retention (Bennett and Okinaka 1990) . To explore the applicability of the Common In-group Identity Model to this issue, we reanalyzed data from a racial climate survey of black and white college students attending a midwestern state
.. c 4)
C)
ono C) 0 U
c ro V c~f
m L O v--
ro
c O
4J
c
17
18
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L. GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
university (Snider and Dovidio 1996) . This survey included items assessing satisfaction with the social environment (with other students, faculty, administrators, and the local community), with experience of discrimination (inside and outside the classroom), and with academic factors (high school preparation and current college grade-point average) . Because the survey was designed for other purposes, the group representations identified by the Common In-group Identity Model were not directly included . One item did relate to feeling to a common ingroup identity-"feeling part of the university community ." This item, however, does not distinguish between a one-group representation or a same-team representation (see Figure 1) ; that is, people could feel part of the university community as one, single common group or they could maintain their group's own identity while feeling collectively part of the "same team" (i .e ., the community overall) . Nevertheless, because both of these perspectives represent recategorization within our model, we used this item to reflect the development of a common group identity . The measure of institutional commitment for our analyses was a composite index of intention to complete the degree at the university and willingness to recommend the university to others . Overall, black students were significantly less satisfied with each of the four aspects of the social environment than were white students . Blacks also reported substantially higher rates of discrimination experienced both inside and outside the classroom . In addition, black students felt significantly less a part of the university community and were substantially less committed to the university than were whites . Of relevance to our model, however, was the pattern of mediation . As illustrated in Figure 3, feeling part of the university community was the primary mediator of commitment . When it was considered in the regression equation it significantly predicted commitment while the effects of race and all of the other variables except satisfaction with the administration and with teaching were nonsignificant . The strength of the path from race to institutional commitment, which was initially significant (beta = - .20) was substantially weakened and nonsignificant (beta = - .01) when the measure of feeling part of the university was considered in the equation . When the responses were analyzed separately by race, feeling part of the community was the most influential predictor for both blacks (beta = .52, p < .001) and whites (beta = .42, p < .001) . The only other significant predictor of institutional commitment was satisfaction with the administration for both black (beta = .25, p < .05) and white (beta = .25, p < .01) students . Thus, the development of a common in-group identity may predict not only the nature of the relationship among individuals but also between individuals and the group, which can have important consequences for both . We found a similar pattern of results in a re-analysis of data of white, Latino, and black psychologists employed in academic departments (see Niemann and Dovidio 1998) . A measure of feeling part of the department was created from two related items in the survey : (1) "I have to prove myself to be fully accepted as a
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
19
member of my department" (reverse scored), and (2) "I feel free to be myself at work ." The outcome of interest, related to commitment, was job satisfaction (see Niemann and Dovidio 1998) . The responses of whites were compared to those of blacks and Latinos (which did not significantly differ from each other) . Analogous to the findings for students, black and Latino psychologists felt less part of their department and were less satisfied in their position than were white psychologists . Again, consistent with our model, the effect of race/ethnicity on job satisfaction was significantly mediated by feeling part of the department . In general, consistent with the Common In-group Identity Model, we have found evidence that a range of aspects involved in intergroup contact, which have been identified by the Contact Hypothesis as key elements, decrease intergroup bias in part through changing cognitive representations of the groups . Moreover, we have shown that developing a common in-group identity can produce more favorable attitudes, reduce stereotyping, and facilitate greater pro-social and personal interactions with people originally identified as out-group members, and enhance group commitment . Nevertheless, for both practical and theoretical reasons there may be limits to the benefits of interventions designed to emphasize solely a one-group representation .
RECATEGORIZATION AND A DUAL IDENTITY Hewstone (1996) has argued, pragmatically, that interventions designed to create a common in-group identity (such as equal status contact) may not be sufficiently potent to "overcome powerful ethnic and racial categorizations on more than a temporary basis" (p . 351) . Moreover, theoretically, based on the assumptions of Social Identity Theory (Tajfel and Turner 1979 ; Turner 1981), introducing equal status interventions in intergroup contact situations may produce threat to the integrity of members' separate group identities and needs for group distinctiveness . Consequently, to re-establish positive and distinctive group identities, members of such equal status, interacting groups may maintain relatively high levels of intergroup bias (Brown and Wade 1987) or even show increased levels of bias (Deschamps and Brown 1983) . Hornsey and Hogg (2000), for instance, found that a condition that emphasized students' common university membership produced even higher levels of bias between humanities and math-science students than did a condition that emphasized their separate group identities . Thus, under some conditions, equal status intergroup interactions may not produce more inclusive group representations nor successfully reduce bias-and may, in fact, exacerbate bias . Under other conditions, however, equal status contact can reduce bias . Hewstone and Brown's (1986 ; see also Hewstone 1996) Mutual Intergroup Differentiation Model suggests that equal status interaction reduces intergroup bias when original group identities are salient and are not threatened by contact, such as
20
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
when the groups have differentiated areas of expertise . Hewstone and Brown (1986) proposed that for contact between members of different groups to reduce bias successfully, "first, that contact should be 'intergroup' not 'interpersonal' ; and second, that an appropriate model of intergroup contact should be based on 'mutual intergroup differentiation"' (Hewstone 1996, p . 333) in which the groups are distinguished by the experience and expertise that they bring to the situation . When the groups are not differentiated in their roles or experience, positive social identity may be threatened (Tajfel and Turner 1979), and bias may be exacerbated rather than reduced (Jetten, Spears, and Manstead 1997) . Furthermore, according to the Mutual Intergroup Differentiation Model, bias will most effectively be reduced when the groups are encouraged "to recognize mutual superiorities and inferiorities, and to accord equal values to dimensions favoring each group" (Hewstone 1996, p . 334 ; see also Tajfel 1969 ; Turner 1981, 1985 ; van Knippenberg 1984) . Differentiation and a Common In-group Identity
The predictions derived from the Mutual Intergroup Differentiation Model are not necessarily incompatible with those based on the Common In-group Identity Model . Recategorization into a single, undifferentiated group (a one-group representation) is only one form considered in our model (see Figure 1) . We further propose that the development of a common in-group identity does not necessarily require each group to forsake its less inclusive group identity completely . As Ferdman (1995) notes, every individual belongs to multiple groups . For example, Rodriguez-Scheel (1980) found that Chicanos in Detroit chose nonethnic categories, such as religion, occupation, and family, as often as ethnic labels to describe themselves . Thus, recategorization can also take the form of a dual identity, in which superordinate and subgroup identities are both salient . This type of recategorization is represented by a "different groups working together on the same team" representation . Establishing a common superordinate identity while simultaneously maintaining the salience of subgroup identities (i .e., developing a dual identity as two subgroups within one group) may be particularly effective because it permits the benefits of a common in-group identity to operate without arousing countervailing motivations to achieve positive distinctiveness . We report two studies investigating this hypothesis . In one study (Dovidio, Gaertner, and Validzic 1998) groups of three students were given feedback indicating that, based on their performance on an earlier task, their group was higher, lower, or equal in status than another group with which they were about to cooperate . This status manipulation was crossed factorially with whether the groups were assigned identical or different task perspectives in preparation for their cooperative interaction . The discussions involved the Winter Survival Problem (Johnson and Johnson 1975) and when the groups had different task perspectives, the members of one group were told to assume that
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
21
they would hike to safety whereas the members of the other group were asked to assume that they would stay put to await search parties . As predicted, the analyses revealed that when the groups were of equal status and task perspectives were different, intergroup bias was lower and the representation of the aggregate feeling like one group was higher than in each of the other three conditions (i .e., equal status-same task, unequal status-different task, and equal status-same task) . In addition, the one-group representation mediated the relation between the experimental manipulations of status and task perspective on intergroup bias . These findings are consistent with the proposed value of equal status, primarily, as Hewstone and Brown (1986) propose, when the distinctiveness between groups is maintained . In another study (Mottola 1996) relative group status among actual employees of many different companies was varied by asking participants to imagine that their current organization was about to merge with another . In one condition, their present company was described as higher in status than the other in terms of generating greater sales and greater profits . In another condition, their company was lower in status on both dimensions . In a third condition, both companies were described as having equal status in terms of both sales and profit . In a fourth condition, their company was described as higher in status on one dimension (e .g ., profit), but the other company was higher on the other dimension . Consistent with Hewstone and Brown's (1986) ideas about the benefits of maintaining the mutual distinctiveness of groups working together, participants in the fourth condition in which one company had higher profit and the other higher sales anticipated that they would more strongly identify with the merged organization than did participants in each of the other three conditions (which did not differ from one another) . Thus, when each group can maintain positive distinctiveness, we can anticipate greater acceptance of a superordinate identity from the members of both groups . This would be particularly important in organizational settings when subgroups must be formed and only the convergent pattern is realistically possible . Furthermore, when the basis of group differentiation facilitates the merged group's effectiveness, the development of a common group identity could be enhanced . For example, as in this study, when each subgroup contributes a different but necessary component to the merged organization's effectiveness, group differentiation could enhance the acceptance of organizational identification . Beyond generating more positive intergroup attitudes, the degree of organizational unity experienced can have implications for the effectiveness and productivity of a merged organization . For example, we have found that the extent to which members of two groups perceived of themselves as one superordinate group correlated with the actual effectiveness of their task solution (r = .28, p < .02) . This relationship is also consistent with the meta-analytic conclusions of Mullen and Copper (1994) who found that group cohesiveness significantly predicts group productivity (r = .25) . Moreover, Mullen and Copper suggest that the relationship between cohesiveness and productivity may be bidirectional and thus iterative : cohesiveness may enhance productivity, and successful accomplish-
22
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
ment, in turn, further increases cohesiveness . Indeed, the relationship between successful performance and subsequent productivity is even stronger (r = .51) than the relationship between initial cohesiveness and productivity . Thus, the development of a common ingroup identity can help form a basis for more harmonious intergroup relations to develop through mutual success and achievement, which reinforces the common bond and identity between the groups . As depicted by the "subgroups within one group" (i .e ., a dual identity) representation in our model (see Figure 1), we believe that it is possible for members to conceive of two groups (for example, parents and children) as distinct units within the context of a superordinate (i .e ., family) identity . The development of dual identities, in which groups are allowed or encouraged to maintain their previous group identities while at the same time having salient superordinate identities, is an alternative form of recategorization to the one-group representation . A representation of "different groups on the same team" permits mutual intergroup differentiation while recognizing a common, superordinate group membership . Moreover, this type of recategorization may be particularly effective when people have strong allegiances to their original groups . When group identities and the associated cultural values are central to members' functioning or when they are associated with high status or highly visible cues to group membership, it would be undesirable or impossible for people to relinquish these group identities or, as perceivers, to be "color-blind ." Indeed, demands to forsake these group identities or to adopt a color-blind ideology would likely arouse strong reactance and result in especially poor intergroup relations (see Schofield 1986) . If, however, people continued to regard themselves as members of different groups but all playing on the same team or as part of the same superordinate entity, intergroup relations between these "subgroups" would be more positive than if members only considered themselves as "separate groups" (see Brewer and Schneider 1990) . In this respect, the benefits of a dual identity may be particularly relevant to interracial and interethnic group contexts . Majority and Minority Group Perespectives
Racial and ethnic identities are fundamental aspects of individuals' self-concepts and esteem and thus are unlikely to be readily abandoned . Thus, attempts to produce a single superordinate identity at the expense of one's racial or ethnic group identity may ultimately be detrimental to intergroup relations . In contrast, the development of a dual identity, in terms of a bicultural or multicultural identity, may not only improve intergroup relations but may also contribute to the social adjustment, psychological adaptation, and overall well-being of minority group members (LaFromboise, Coleman, and Gerton 1993) . There is evidence intergroup benefits of a strong superordinate identity can be achieved for both majority and minority group members when the strength of the subordinate identity is equivalently high. For example, in a survey study of white
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
23
adults, Smith and Tyler (1996, Study 1) measured the strength of respondents' superordinate identity as "American" and also the strength of their identification as "white ." Regardless of whether they strongly identified with being white, those respondents with a strong American identity were more likely to base their support for affirmative action policies that would benefit blacks and other minorities on relational concerns regarding the fairness of Congressional representatives than on whether these policies would increase or decrease their own well-being . However, for the group who identified themselves more strongly with being white than being American, their position on affirmative action was determined more strongly by concerns regarding the instrumental value of these policies for themselves . This pattern of findings suggests that a strong superordinate identity (such as being American) allows individuals to support policies that would benefit members of other racial subgroups without giving primary consideration to their own instrumental needs . Among people of color, even when racial or ethnic identity is strong, perceptions of a superordinate connection enhance interracial trust and acceptance of authority within an organization . Huo, Smith, Tyler, and Lind (1996) surveyed white, black, Latino, and Asian employees of a public-sector organization . Identification with the organization (superordinate identity) and racial/ethnic identity (subgroup identity) were independently assessed . Regardless of the strength of racial/ethnic identity, respondents who had a strong organizational identity perceived that they were treated fairly within the organization, and consequently they had favorable attitudes toward authority . Huo and colleagues (1996) conclude that having a strong identification with a superordinate group can redirect people from focusing on their personal outcomes to concerns about "achieving the greater good and maintaining social stability" (pp . 44-45), while also maintaining important racial and ethnic identities . We found converging evidence in our multi-ethnic high school survey study (Gaertner et al . 1996), which we introduced earlier . In particular, we compared students who identified themselves on the survey using a dual identity (e .g ., indicating they were Korean and American) with those who used only a single, subgroup identity (e .g ., Korean) . Supportive of the role of a dual identity, students who described themselves as both American and as a member of their racial or ethnic group had less bias toward other groups in the school than did those who described themselves only in terms of their subgroup identity . Also, the minority students who actually identified themselves using a dual identity reported lower levels of intergroup bias relative to those who only used their ethnic or racial group identity . Not only do whites and people of color bring different values, identities, and experiences to intergroup contact situations, these different perspectives can shape perceptions of and reactions to the nature of the contact . Blumer (1958a) proposed that group status is a fundamental factor in the type of threat that different groups experience . Recent surveys, for example, reveal that blacks show a
24
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
higher level of distrust and greater pessimism about intergroup relations than do whites (Dovidio and Gaertner 1998 ; Hochschild 1995) . Majority group members tend to perceive intergroup interactions as more harmonious and productive than do minority group members (Gaertner et al . 1996 ; Islam and Hewstone 1993 ; see also the college student survey discussed earlier), but they also tend to perceive subordinate and minority groups as encroaching on their rights and prerogatives (Bobo 1999) . In addition, majority and minority group members have different preferences for the ultimate outcomes of intergroup contact. Whereas minority group members often tend to want to retain their cultural identity, majority group members favor the assimilation of minority groups into one single culture (a traditional "melting pot" orientation)-the dominant culture (Horenczyk 1996) . Berry (1984; Berry, Poortinga, Segall, and Dasen 1992) presents four forms of cultural relations in pluralistic societies that represent the intersection of "yes-no" responses to two relevant questions : (1) Are cultural identity and customs of value to be retained? (2) Are positive relations with the larger society of value, and to be sought? These combinations reflect four adaptation strategies for intergroup relations : (1) integration, when cultural identities are retained and positive relations with the larger society are sought ; (2) separatism, when cultural identities are retained but positive relations with the larger society are not sought ; (3) assimilation, when cultural identities are abandoned and positive relations with the larger society are desired ; and (4) marginalization, when cultural identities are abandoned and are not replaced by positive identification with the larger society . Although this framework has been applied primarily to the ways in which immigrants acclimate to a new society (van Oudenhoven, Prins, and Buunk 1998), we propose that it can be adapted to apply to intergroup relations between majority and minority groups more generally . Substituting the separate strengths of the subgroup and subordinate group identities for the answers to Berry's (1984) two questions, the combinations map onto the four main representations considered in the Common In-group Identity Model : (1) same team (subgroup and superordinate group identities are high, like integration) ; (2) different groups (subgroup identity is high and superordinate identity is low, like separatism) ; (3) one group (subgroup identity is low and superordinate group identity is high, like assimilation ; and (4) separate individuals (subgroup and superordinate group identities are low, like marginalization) . Research in the area of immigration suggests that immigrant groups and majority groups have different preferences for these different types of group relations . Van Oudenhoven and colleagues (1998) found in the Netherlands that Dutch majority group members preferred an assimilation of minority groups (in which minority group identity was abandoned and replaced by identification with the dominant Dutch culture), whereas Turkish and Moroccan immigrants most strongly endorsed integration (in which they would retain their own cultural identity while also valuing the dominant Dutch culture) . These preferences also apply to the preferences of whites and of people of color about racial and ethnic group
Group Identity and Intergroup
Relations
25
relations in the United States . We have found that whites most prefer assimilation, whereas racial and ethnic minorities favor pluralistic integration (Kafati 1999) . Moreover, these preferred types of intergroup relations for majority and minority groups, a one-group representation for whites and same-team representation for people of color, may differentially mediate the consequences of intergroup contact for the different groups . To explore this possibility, we examined how different types of cognitive representations might mediate the relationship between more positive perceptions of intergroup contact and higher levels of institutional commitment among white students and students of color (Kafati 1999) . As in the Snider and Dovidio (1996) survey study of college students considered earlier in this chapter, commitment was chosen as the main outcome variable because attrition rates by race/ethnicity are a widespread concern on college campuses . Perceptions of favorable intergroup contact were measured in the same way as in our multi-ethnic high school study (Gaertner et al . 1996) and included ratings on the dimensions of equal status, supportive norms, personal interaction, and cooperative interaction . Commitment included items about students' intentions to complete their education at the institution and their willingness to recommend the institution to others, as well as questions about the academic and social climate . Whereas in the Snider and Dovidio (1995) survey, only a single item, feeling part of the university community, assessed recategorized representations, this study examined all four cognitive representations identified by the Common In-group Identity Model and hypothesized to represent different models of intergroup relations : perceptions of being (1) one group (assimilation), (2) separate groups (separatism), (3) separate individuals (decategorization/marginalization), and (4) different groups on the same team (integration/multiculturalism) . In addition, participants' identification with their racial or ethnic group was assessed . We hypothesized that the positive relation between perceptions of more favorable intergroup contact and institutional commitment would be mediated by different representations of the groups . Whereas we expected that the relation for whites would be mediated by one-group representations, reflecting an assimilation perspective, we anticipated that the relation for people of color would be mediated by same-team representations, a multicultural perspective that recognizes both one's racial or ethnic group identity and a superordinate identity-a dual identity . The results confirmed the hypothesis . For whites, more positive perceptions of intergroup contact related to stronger perceptions of students consisting of one group, different groups on the same team, and separate individuals, as well as weaker perceptions of different groups . However, when considered simultaneously, only the one-group representation was significantly related to commitment (see Figure 4, top panel) . Supportive of the hypothesized mediation, the relationship between perceptions of more favorable conditions of intergroup contact and greater institutional commitment, which was initially significant (beta = .36), was greatly reduced by the inclusion of one-group representations in the
26
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
White Students Individuals
Different Groups
Conditions of Contact
One Group
.04
.36
Students ofColor Individuals
Different Groups
Conditions of Contact
Same Team
34
.37 One Group
.24
Figure 4 .
.04
Intergroup Relations and Satisfaction at College for White Students and for Students of Color
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
27
equation (beta = .04) . This pattern of results is also consistent with the finding in our field experiment, described earlier in this chapter, that white football fans responded particularly favorably to blacks who apparently adopted their university affiliation as a superordinate identity . Conditions of contact also significantly predicted each of the representations for students of color . In contrast to the pattern for whites, though, the same-team representation-but not the one-group representation-predicted commitment (see Figure 4, bottom panel) . In general, these effects were stronger for people higher in racial ethnic identification, both for whites and people of color . These findings have practical as well as theoretical implications . Although correlational data should be interpreted cautiously, it appears that, for both whites and people of color, favorable intergroup contact may contribute to their commitment to their institution . However, strategies and interventions designed to enhance satisfaction need to recognize that whites and people of color may have different ideals and motivations . Because white values and culture have been the traditionally dominant ones in the United States, American whites may see an assimilation model, in which members of other cultural groups are absorbed into the "mainstream," as the most comfortable and effective strategy . For people of color, this model, which denies the value of their culture and traditions, may not only be perceived as less desirable but also as threatening to their personal and social identity-particularly for people who strongly identify with their group . Thus, efforts to create a single superordinate identity, although well-intentioned, may threaten one's social identity, which in turn can intensify intergroup bias and conflict .
CONCLUSION Discrimination and bias are group-level as well as individual-level phenomena . Categorizing people as members of one's own group (the in-group) and other groups (out-groups) automatically initiates biases that produce and maintain more positive attitudes, stereotypes, and actions toward in-group than out-group members . We propose that by understanding the processes that underlie the development of these intergroup biases, these forces can be redirected to reduce prejudice and discrimination. In particular, the Common In-group Identity Model involves interventions to change people's conceptions of the memberships from different groups to one, more inclusive group . If members of different groups are induced to conceive of themselves more as a single, superordinate group rather than as two separate groups, attitudes toward former out-group members will become more positive through processes involving pro-in-group bias . In general, data from laboratory studies, field experiments, and surveys involving a range of different types of groups offer converging evidence in support of the model .
28
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
The development of a common in-group identity does not necessarily require each group to forsake its less inclusive group identity completely . Recategorization can also take the form of a dual identity (such as by a "different groups working together on the same team" representation), in which superordinate and subgroup identities are both salient, and the benefits of a strong superordinate identity can be achieved for both majority and minority group members when the strength of the subordinate identity is high . Moreover, because of the salience and importance of racial and ethnic identities among minority group members relative to majority group members, there tend to be differences in these groups' preferences for recategorization strategies and intergroup relations . We have found, for example, that whites most prefer assimilation (reflecting a one-group identity), whereas racial and ethnic minorities favor pluralistic integration (involving a dual-identity or same-team representation) . Furthermore, these preferred types of intergroup relations for majority and minority groups differentially mediate the consequences of intergroup contact . Whereas a one-group representation is of primary importance for whites, a same-team representation is the critical factor for people of color . Taken together, these findings indicate that, although racial and ethnic prejudice and discrimination have long traditions, these biases can potentially be addressed by harnessing the fundamental psychological processes that would typically promote bias and redirecting them to improve intergroup relations . We acknowledge that interventions based on these principles need to be considered carefully . It is important to be cognizant of how interventions might affect social categorization and to be sensitive to the differential effects for majority and minority groups . Nevertheless, understanding the multilevel nature of prejudice and discrimination is an essential step for finding solutions-which may need to be similarly multifaceted .
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS The research described and the preparation of this chapter were supported by NIMH Grant MH 48721 . We are also grateful to the editors and the reviewers for their helpful comments on an earlier version of this chapter .
REFERENCES Abelson, R . P ., D . R. Kinder, M. D . Peters, and S . T . Fiske . 1982 . "Affective and Semantic Components in Political Person Perception ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 42: 619-630 . Adorno, T . W ., E . Frenkel-Brunswik, D. J . Levinson, and R . N. Sanford . 1950. The Authoritarian Personality . New York : Harper. Allport, G . W . 1954 . The Nature of Prejudice . Cambridge, MA : Addison-Wesley.
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
29
Altman, I ., and D . A . Taylor . 1973 . Social Penetration : The Development of Interpersonal Relationships . New York : Holt, Rinehart, and Winston . Archer, R . L., and J . H . Berg . 1978 . "Disclosure Reciprocity and its Limits : A Reactance Analysis ." Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 14 : 527-540 . Aronson, E ., and S . Patnoe . 1997 . The Jigsaw Classroom. New York : Longman . Bachman, B . A . 1993. "An Intergroup Model of Organizational Mergers ." Unpublished PhD Dissertation, University of Delaware, Newark, DE . Banker, B . S ., and S . L . Gaertner . 1998 . "Achieving Stepfamily Harmony : An Intergroup Relations Approach ." Journal of Family Psychology 12 : 310-325 . Batson, C . D . 1991 . The Altruism Question : Toward a Social-psychological Answer. Hillsdale, NJ : Erlbaum . Bennett, C., and A . M . Okinaka. 1990. "Factors Related to Persistence among Asian, Black, Hispanic and White Undergraduates at a Predominantly White University : Comparisons Between First and Fourth Year Cohorts ." The Urban Review 22 : 33- 60 . Berry, J . W . 1984 . "Cultural Relations in Plural Societies ." Pp. 11-27 in Groups in contact: The Psychology of Desegregation, edited by N . Miller and M . B . Brewer . Orlando, FL: Academic Press. Berry, J . W ., Y . H. Poortinga, M . H. Segall, and P. R . Dasen. 1992 . Cross-cultural Psychology : Research and Applications . Cambridge : Cambridge University Press . Bettencourt, B . A ., M . B . Brewer, M . R. Croak, and N. Miller. 1992. "Cooperation and the Reduction of Intergroup Bias: the Roles of Reward Structure and Social Orientation ." Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 28 : 301-319 . Blauner, R . 1972. Race Oppression in America . New York : Harper and Row . Blumer, H . 1958a . "Race Prejudice as a Sense of Group Position ." Pacific Sociological Review 1 : 3-7 . Blumer, H . 1958b . "Recent Research on Race Relations in the United States of America ." International Social Science Bulletin 10 : 403-477 . Blumer, H. 1965a . "Industrialization and Race Relations ." Pp . 228-229 in Industrialization and race relations : A symposium, edited by G . Hunter . New York: Oxford University Press . Blumer, H . 1965b . "The Future of the Color Line ." Pp . 322-336 in The South in continuity and change, edited by J. C . McKinney and E . T . Thompson. Durham, NC : Seeman. Bobo, L . 1988 . "Group Conflict, Prejudice, and the Paradox of Contemporary Racial Attitudes ." Pp . 85-114 in Eliminating Racism : Profiles in Controversy, edited by P . A. Katz and D . A . Taylor . New York: Plenum . Bobo, L . 1999 . "Prejudice as Group Position: Micro-foundations of a Sociological Approach to Racism and Race Relations." Journal of Social Issues 55(3) . Bobo, L ., and V. L . Huchings . 1996 . "Perceptions of Racial Group Competition : Extending Blumer's Theory of Group Position to a Multiracial Context ." American Sociological Review 61 : 951-972 . Bonacich, E . 1972 . "A Theory of Ethnic Antagonism ." American Sociological Review 77 : 547-559 . Brewer, M . B . 1979 . "Ingroup Bias in the Minimal Intergroup Situation : A Cognitive Motivational Analysis ." Psychological Bulletin 86 : 307-324 . Brewer, M . B. 1988 ." A Dual Process Model of Impression Formation." Pp. 1-36 in Advances in Social Cognition : Vol. I: A Dual Process Model of Impression Formation, edited by T . S . Srull and R . S . Wyer . Hillsdale, NJ : Erlbaum . Brewer, M . B ., and N . Miller . 1984 . "Beyond the Contact Hypothesis : Theoretical Perspectives on Desegregation ." Pp . 281-302 in Groups in Contact : The Psychology of Desegregation, edited by N. Miller and M . B . Brewer. Orlando, FL: Academic Press . Brewer, M. B ., and S . Schneider. 1990 . "Social Identity and Social Dilemmas : A Double-edged Sword ." Pp . 169-184 in Social Identity Theory : Constructive and Critical Advances, edited by D . Abrams and M . Hogg . London : Harvester Wheatsheaf.
30
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
Brown, R. J. 1984. "The Effects of Intergroup Similarity and Cooperative vs . Competitive Orientation on Intergroup Discrimination ." British Journal of Social Psychology 21 : 21-33 . Brown, R. J ., and G. Wade . 1987 . "Superordinate Goals and Intergroup Behavior : The Effect of Role Ambiguity and Status on Intergroup Attitudes and Task Performance ." European Journal of Social Psychology 17 : 131-142 . Carter, D . J., and R . Wilson . 1997 . Minorities in Higher Education. Washington, DC : American Council on Education . Cook, S . W . 1984. "Cooperative Interaction in Multiethnic Contexts ." Pp . 291-302 in Groups in Contact: The Psychology of Desegregation, edited by N . Miller and M. B . Brewer. Orlando, FL: Academic Press . Davis, J . D . 1976 . "Self-disclosure in an Acquaintance Exercise : Responsibility for Level of Intimacy ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 33 : 787-792 . Derlega, V . J ., and A . L . Chaikin . 1976 . "Norms Affecting Self-disclosure in Men and Women ." Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 44 : 376-380. Derlega, V . J., S . Metts, S . Petronio, and S . T. Margulis . 1993 . Self-disclosure. Newbury Park, CA : Sage . Deschamps, J. C ., and R . Brown . 1983 . "Superordinate Goals and Intergroup Conflict ." British Journal of Social Psychology 22 : 189-195 . Deutsch, M . 1973 . The Resolution of Social Conflict . New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Dindia, K ., and M . Allen . 1992 . "Sex Differences in Self-disclosure: A Meta-analysis ." Psychological Bulletin 112 : 106-124 . Dovidio, J . F. 1984 . "Helping Behavior and Altruism : An Empirical and Conceptual Overview ." Pp. 361-427 in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol . 17, edited by L. Berkowitz . New York: Academic Press . Dovidio, J. F ., J . Brigham, B . T . Johnson, and S . L . Gaertner. 1996 . "Stereotyping, Prejudice and Discrimination." Pp. 276-319 in Foundations of Stereotypes and Stereotyping, edited by N . Macrae, C. Stangor and M. Hewstone. New York: Guilford. Dovidio, J . F., and S . L. Gaertner. 1986 . "Prejudice, Discrimination, and Racism : Historical Trends and Contemporary Approaches ." Pp . 1-34 in Prejudice, Discrimination and Racism, edited by J. F . Dovidio, and S. L. Gaertner . Orlando, FL: Academic Press . Dovidio, J. F., and S . L . Gaertner . 1993 . "Stereotypes and Evaluative Intergroup Bias ." Pp . 167-193 in Affect, Cognition, and Stereotyping: Interactive Processes in Intergroup Perception, edited by D . M . Mackie and D . L . Hamilton. Orlando, FL: Academic Press . Dovidio, J . F ., and S . L . Gaertner . 1996. "Affirmative Action, Unintentional Racial Biases, and Intergroup Relations ." Journal of Social Issues 52(4) : 51-76. Dovidio, J. F., and S . L. Gaertner. 1998 . "On the Nature of Contemporary Prejudice : The Causes, Consequences, and Challenges of Aversive Racism ." Pp. 3-32 in Confronting Racism : The Problem and the Response, edited by J . Eberhardt and S . T . Fiske. Newbury Park, CA : Sage . Dovidio, J . F., S . L. Gaertner, and A. Validzic . 1998 . "Intergroup Bias : Status, Differentiation, and a Common In-group Identity ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 75 : 109-120. Dovidio, J . F ., S . L. Gaertner, A . Validzic, K. Matoka, B . Johnson, and S . Frazier . 1997 . "Extending the Benefits of Re-categorization : Evaluations, Self-disclosure and Helping ." Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 33 : 401-420 . Dovidio, J . F., and W. N. Morris. 1975 . "The Effects of Stress and Commonality of Fate on Helping Behavior ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 31 : 145-149. Duckitt, J . 1992 . "Psychology and Prejudice : A Historical Analysis and Integrative Framework." American Psychologist 47 : 1182-1193 . Esses, V ., G . Haddock, and M . Zanna. 1993 . "Values, Stereotypes, and Emotions as Determinants of Intergroup Attitudes ." Pp . 137-166 in Affect, Cognition and Stereotyping : Interactive Processes in Group Perception, edited by D . Mackie and D . Hamilton . San Diego, CA: Academic Press .
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
31
Ferdman, B . M . 1995 . "Cultural Identity and Diversity in Organizations : Bridging the Gap Between Group Differences and Individual Uniqueness." Pp . 37-61 in Diversity in Organizations: New Perspectives for a Changing Workplace, edited by M . M . Chemers, S . Oskamp, and M . A. Costanzo . Thousand Oks, CA : Sage . Ferguson, C. K ., and H . H. Kelley . 1964 ." Significant Factors in Over-evaluation of Own Groups' Products." Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 69 : 223-228 . Fiske, S . T ., and S . L . Neuberg . 1990. "A Continuum Model of Impression Formation : From Category Based to Individuating Processes as a Function of Information, Motivation, and Attention ." Pp. 1-74 in Advances in experimental social psychology, Vol . 23, edited by M . P . Zanna . San Diego, CA : Academic Press . Flippen, A . R ., H . A. Hornstein, W. E . Siegal, and E . A . Weitzman. 1996. "A Comparison of Similarity and Interdependence as Triggers for Ingroup Formation ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 22 : 882-893 . Gaertner, S . L ., and J. F . Dovidio. 1986a . "The Aversive Form of Racism ." Pp . 61-89 in Prejudice, Discrimination, and Racism, edited by J . F. Dovidio and S . L . Gaertner. Orlando, FL : Academic Press. Gaertner, S . L ., and J . F. Dovidio . 1986b . "Prejudice, Discrimination, and Racism : Problems, Progress and Promise ." Pp . 315-332 in Prejudice, Discrimination, and Racism, edited by J . F. Dovidio and S . L . Gaertner . Orlando, FL : Academic Press . Gaertner, S . L ., J. F . Dovidio, P. A. Anastasio, B . A . Bachman, and M . C . Rust . 1993 . "The Common Ingroup Identity Model : Recategorization and the Reduction of Intergroup Bias ." Pp. 1-26 in European Review of Social Psychology, Vol . 4, edited by W . Stroebe and M . Hewstone . New York: John Wiley and Sons . Gaertner, S . L ., J . F . Dovidio, B . Banker, M . Houlette, K. Johnson, and E. McGlynn . 2000. "Reducing Intergroup Conflict: From Superordinate Goals to Decategorization, Recategorization, and Mutual Differentiation . Group Dynamics 4 : 98-114 . Gaertner, S . L ., J . F . Dovidio, M . C . Rust, J . Nier, B . Banker, C . M. Ward, G. R . Mottola, and M . Roulette . 1999 . "Reducing Intergroup Bias : Elements of Intergroup Cooperation ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 76 : 388-402 . Gaertner, S . L., J. A . Mann, J . F . Dovidio, A . J . Murrell, and M . Pomare. 1990 . "How Does Cooperation Reduce Intergroup Bias?" Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59 : 692-704 . Gaertner, S . L ., J . Mann, A . Murrell, and J . F. Dovidio . 1989 . "Reducing Intergroup Bias : The Benefits of Recategorization ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 57 : 239-249 . Gaertner, S . L ., M . C . Rust, J. F. Dovidio, B . A. Bachman, and P. A . Anastasio . 1994. "The Contact Hypothesis : The Role of a Common Ingroup Identity on Reducing Intergroup Bias ." Small Groups Research 25(2): 224-249 . Gaertner, S . L ., M . C . Rust, J. F. Dovidio, B . A. Bachman, and P. A. Anastasio . 1996 . "The Contact Hypothesis : the Role of a Common Ingroup Identity on Reducing Intergroup Bias among Majority and Minority Group Members ." Pp . 230-360 in What's Social about Social Cognition?, edited by J. L . Nye and A. M . Brower. Newbury Park, CA : Sage . Gouldner, A . 1960. "The Norm of Reciprocity : A Preliminary Statement ." American Sociological Review 25 : 161-178 . Green, C . W., A . M . Adams, and C . W. Turner . 1988 . "Development and Validation of the School Interracial Climate Scale ." American Journal of Community Psychology 16: 241-259. Hewstone, M . 1990 . "The 'Ultimate Attribution Error'? A Review of the Literature on Intergroup Attributions ." European Journal of Social Psychology 20 : 311-335 Hewstone, M . 1996 . "Contact and Categorization : Social Psychological Interventions to Change Intergroup Relations." Pp . 323-368 in Foundations of Stereotypes and Stereotyping, edited by N. Macrae, M . Hewstone, and C . Stangor. New York: Guilford .
32
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L. GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
Hewstone, M ., and R. J . Brown . 1986 . "Contact Is Not Enough : An Intergroup Perspective on the 'Contact Hypothesis' ." Pp . 1-44 in Contact and Conflict in Intergroup Encounters, edited by M . Hewstone and R . Brown . Oxford : Basil Blackwell . Higgins, E. T ., and J . A . Bargh . 1987 . "Social Cognition and Social Perception ." Annual Review of Psychology 38 : 369-425 . Hochschild, J . L . 1995 . Facing up to the American Dream : Race, Class, and the Soul of the Nation . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press . Horenczyk, G . 1966 . "Migrant Identities in Conflict : Acculturation Attitudes and Perceived Acculturation Ideologies ." Pp. 241-250 in Changing European identities : Social Psychological Analyses of Social Change, edited by G . Breakwell and E . Lyons . Oxford : Butterworth-Heinemann . Hornstein, H . A. 1976 . Cruelty and Kindness: A New Look at Aggression And Altruism . Englewood Cliffs, NJ : Prentice Hall . Hornstein, H . A ., H . N. Masor, K . Sole, M . Heilman. 1971 . "Effects of Sentiment and Completion of a Helping Act on Observer Helping : A Case for Socially-Mediated Ziergarnik Effects ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 17 : 107-112 . Hornsey, M. J., and M . A . Hogg . 2000 . "Sub-group Relations : Two Experiments Comparing Subgroup Differentiation and Common Ingroup Identity Models of Prejudice Reduction ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin (in press) . Howard, J . M ., and M. Rothbart. 1980. "Social Categorization for In-group and Out-group Behavior ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 38 : 301-310 . Huo, Y. J ., H. J . Smith, T . R . Tyler, and A. E . Lind. 1996 . "Superordinate Identification, Subgroup Identification, and Justice Concerns : Is Separatism the Problem. Is Assimilation the Answer?" Psychological Science 7 : 40- 45 . Islam, M. R., and M. Hewstone . 1993. "Dimensions of Contact as Predictors of Intergroup Anxiety, Perceived Outgroup Variability and Outgroup Attitude : An Integrative Model ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 19 : 700-7 10. Jetten, J ., R . Spears, and A . S . R . Manstead . 1997 . "Distinctiveness Threat and Prototypicality : Combined Effects on Intergroup Discrimination and Collective Self-esteem ." European Journal of Social Psychology 27 : 635-658. Johnson, D. W., and F . P . Johnson. 1975 . Joining Together: Group Theory and Group Skills . Englewood Cliffs, NJ : Prentice-Hall . Johnson, D. W ., F . P. Johnson, and G . Maruyama . 1983 . "Interdependence and Interpersonal Attraction among Heterogeneous and Homogeneous Individuals : A Theoretical Formulation and a Meta-analysis of the Research ." Review of Educational Research 52 : 5-54. Jones, J . M . 1997 . Prejudice and Racism (2nd ed .). New York: McGraw-Hill . Kafati, G . 1999. "Assessing the Intergroup Climate at Colgate University ." Unpublished manuscript, Department of Psychology, Colgate University, Hamilton, NY . Karpinski, A ., and W. Von Hippel. 1996 . "The Role of the Linguistic Intergroup Bias in Expectancy Maintenance ." Social Cognition 14 : 141-163 . Kawakami, K ., and K . L . Dion . 1993 . "The Impact of Salient Self-identities on Relative Deprivation and Action Intentions ." European Journal of Social Psychology 23 : 525-540. Kawakami, K ., and K . L . Dion. 1995 . "Social Identity and Affect as Determinants of Collective Action." Theory and Psychology 5 : 551-577. Kihlstrom, J . F., N . Cantor, J . S . Albright, B . R. Chew, S . B . Klein, and P. M . Niedenthal . 1988 . "Information Processing and the Study of the Self." Pp. 145-180 in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 21, edited by L . Berkowitz. Orlando, FL: Academic Press . Kovel, J . 1970 . White Racism: A Psychohistory . New York: Pantheon . Kramer, R. M ., and M. B . Brewer. 1984. "Effects of Group Identity on Resource Utilization in a Simulated Commons Dilemma ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 46 : 1044-1057 . LaFromboise, T., H . L . K. Coleman, and J. Gerton. 1993 . "Psychological Impact of Biculturalism: Evidence and Theory ." Psychological Bulletin 114 : 395-412 .
Group Identity and Intergroup
Relations
33
LaPiere, R. T . 1934. "Attitudes vs . Actions ." Social Forces 13 : 230-237 . Maas, A ., R . Ceccarelli, and S . Rudin . 1996 . "Linguistic Intergroup Bias : Evidence for In-group-protective Motivation ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71 : 512-526. Maass, A., D . Salvi, L . Arcuri, and G . R. Semin . 1989 . "Language Use in Intergroup Contexts : The Linguistic Intergroup Bias ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 57 : 981-993 . Marcus-Newhall, A ., N. Miller, R . Holtz, and M . B . Brewer . 1993 . "Cross-cutting Category Membership with Role Assignment : A Means of Reducing Intergroup Bias ." British Journal of Social Psychology 322 : 125-146. Miller, N ., M . B . Brewer, and K . Edwards . 1985 . "Cooperative Interaction in Desegregated Settings : A Laboratory Analog ." Journal of Social Issues 41(3) : 63-75 . Mottola, G . 1996. "The Effects of Relative Group Status on Expectations of Merger Success ." PhD Dissertation, University of Delaware . Newark, DE . Mullen, B ., and C . Copper. 1994. "The Relation Between Group Cohesiveness and Performance : An Integration ." Psychological Bulletin 115 : 210-227 . Niemann, Y. F ., and J . F . Dovidio . 1998 . "Relationship of Solo Status, Academic Rank, and Perceived Distinctiveness to Job Satisfaction of Racial/ethnic Minorities . " Journal of Applied Psychology 83 : 55-71 . Osgood, C . E . 1962 . An Alternative to War or Surrender . Urbana, IL : University of Illinois Press. Park, B ., and M . Rothbart . 1982 . "Perception of Out-group Homogeneity and Levels of Social Categorization : Memory for the Subordinate Attributes of In-group and Out-group Members ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 42 : 1051-1068 . Pettigrew, T. F . 1997 . "Generalized Intergroup Contact Effects on Prejudice ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 23 : 173-185 . Pettigrew, T. F . 1998 . "Intergroup Contact Theory." Annual Review of Psychology 49: 65-85 . Piliavin, J . A ., J . F . Dovidio, S . L . Gaertner, and R . D . Clark, III. 1981 . Emergency Intervention . New York : Academic Press . Rodriguez-Scheel, J . 1980 . "An Investigation of the Components of Social Identity for a Detroit Sample. " Unpublished manuscript, Occidental College, Psychology Department, Los Angeles, CA . Schofield, J . W. 1986. "Causes and Consequences of the Colorblind Perspective ." Pp . 231-253 in Prejudice, Discrimination and Racism, edited by J . F. Dovidio and S . L. Gaertner . Orlando, FL: Academic Press . Schroeder, D . A ., L . A . Penner, J . F . Dovidio, and J . A. Piliavin . 1995 . Psychology of Helping and Altruism: Problems and Puzzles. New York : McGraw-Hill . Schuman, H., C. Steeh, L . Bobo, and M . Krysan . 1997 . Racial Attitudes in America: Trends and Interpretations (2nd ed .) . Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press. Sears, D . O . 1988 . "Symbolic Racism ." Pp . 53-84 in Eliminating racism : Profiles in controversy, edited by P. A . Katz and D . A . Taylor . New York : Plenum Press . Semin, G. R ., and K. Fiedler. 1988. "The Cognitive Functions of Linguistic Categories in Describing Persons : Social Cognition and Language ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 54 : 558-568 . Shaffer, D . R ., L . J . Pegalis, and D . G . Bazzini . 1996 . "When Boy Meets Girl (Revisited) : Gender, Gender-Role Orientation, and Prospect of Future Interaction on Self-Disclosure Among Sameand Opposite-Sex Acquaintances ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 22 : 495-506. Sherif, M ., O. J . Harvey ; B . J . White, W . R . Hood, and C . W. Sherif. 1961 . Intergroup Conflict and Cooperation. The Robbers Cave Experiment. Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Book Exchange . Sherif, M ., and C . W . Sherif. 1969. Social Psychology. New York : Harper and Row . Smith, H . J ., and T . R. Tyler. 1996. "Justice and Power : When Will Justice Concerns Encourage the Advantaged to Support Policies Which Redistribute Economic Resources and the Disadvantaged to Willingly Obey the Law?" European Journal of Social Psychology 26: 171-200.
34
JOHN F . DOVIDIO, SAMUEL L . GAERTNER, and GLADYS KAFATI
Snider, K ., and J . F. Dovidio . 1996 . A Survey of the Racial Climate at Indiana State University . Institutional Research and Testing, Indiana State University, Terra Haute, IN . Sole, K., J . Marton, and H . A . Hornstein. 1975 . "Opinion Similarity and Helping : Three Field Experiments Investigating the Bases of Promotive Tension ." Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 11 : 1-13 . Stangor, C ., and G . B . Sechrist . 1998 . "Conceptualizing the Determinants of Academic Choice and Task Performance Across Social Groups ." Pp . 105-124 in Prejudice: the Target's Perspective, edited by J . K. Swim and C . Stangor . San Diego, CA : Academic Press . Steele, C . M . 1997 . "A Threat in the Air: How Stereotypes Shape Intellectual Identity and Performance." American Psychologist 52: 613-629. Stephan, W . G ., and C . W . Stephan . 2000. "An Integrated Threat Theory of Prejudice ." in Reducing Prejudice: Claremont Symposium on Applied Psychology, edited by S . Oskamp . Hillsdale, NJ : Erlbaum . Stephan, W . G ., O . Ybarra, C . Martinez, J. Shwarzwald, and Tur-Kaspa. 1998 . "Prejudice Toward Immigrants in Spain and Israel : an Integrated Threat Analysis Theory ." Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 29 : 559-576 . Struch, N ., and S . H. Schwartz . 1989 . "Intergroup Aggression : Its Predictors and Distinctness from Ingroup Bias ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 56: 364-373 . Tajfel, H. 1969. "Cognitive Aspects of Prejudice ." Journal of Social Issues 25(4) : 79-97 . Tajfel, H ., M . G . Billig, R . F . Bundy, and C . Flament . 1971 . "Social Categorisation and Intergroup Behavior ." European Journal of Social Psychology 1 : 149-177. Tajfel, H ., and J . C . Turner . 1979 . "An Integrative Theory of Intergroup Conflict ." Pp . 33-48 in The Social Psychology of Intergroup Relations, edited by W. G. Austin and S . Worchel. Monterey, CA : Brooks/Cole . Turner, J . C . 1981 . "The Experimental Social Psychology of Intergroup Behavior ." Pp . 66-101 in Intergroup Behavior, edited by J . C . Turner and H . Giles . Chicago, IL : University of Chicago Press. Turner, J. C . 1985 . "Social Categorization and the Self-concept : a Social Cognitive Theory of Group Behavior ." Pp . 77-122 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol . 2, edited by E . J . Lawler. Greenwich, CT : JAI Press . Turner, J. C ., M. A . Hogg, P . J . Oakes, S . D . Reicher, and M. S . Wetherell . 1987 . Rediscovering the Social Group : A Self-categorization Theory . Oxford, UK : Basil Blackwell . Urban, L. M., and N . Miller . 1998 . "A Theoretical Analysis of Crossed Categorization Effects : A Meta-analysis ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 74 : 894-908 . van Knippenberg, A. 1984. "Intergroup Differences in Group Perceptions." Pp . 560-578 in The Social Dimension : European Developments in Social Psychology, Vol . 2, edited by H . Tajfel . Cambridge, UK : Cambridge University Press. van Oudenhoven, J . P., K. S . Prins, and B . Buunk. 1998 . "Attitudes of Minority and Majority Members Towards Adaptation of Immigrants ." European Journal of Social Psychology 28 : 995-1013 . Verkuyten, M ., and L. Hagendoorn. 1998 . "Prejudice and Self-categorization : The Variable Role of Authoritarianism and In-group Stereotypes ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 24: 99-110. Ward, C. M ., J . Nier, M . C . Rust, S . L . Gaertner, and T . Carpenter. 1995 . "A Game They Came to Watch : A Study of Compliance and Team Membership ." Poster presented at the Annual Eastern Psychological Association Convention, Boston, MA . Wilder, D. A . 1981 . "Perceiving Persons as a Group : Categorization and Intergroup Relations ." Pp . 213-257 in Cognitive Processes in Stereotyping and Intergroup Behavior, edited by D . L . Hamilton. Hillsdale, NJ : Erlbaum . Wilder, D . A. 1984. "Predictions of Belief Homogeneity and Similarity Following Social Categorization ." British Journal of Social Psychology 23 : 323-333 .
Group Identity and Intergroup Relations
35
Wilder, D . A. 1986. "Social Categorization : Implications for Creation and Reduction of Intergroup Bias ." Pp . 291-355 in Advances in experimental social psychology, Vol . 19, edited by L . Berkowitz . Orlando, FL : Academic Press . Wilson, W . J . 1978. The Declining Significance of Race . Chicago : University of Chicago Press .
THE AFFECTIVE DYNAMICS OF STEREOTYPING AND INTERGROUP RELATIONS
Neil J . MacKinnon and Jeffrey W . Bowlby
ABSTRACT Most of the research on stereotyping and intergroup relations in social psychology has been conducted within the social cognition paradigm of psychological social psychology . In this paper we identify three deficits of the social cognition approach to stereotyping and intergroup relations that have hindered its developing a satisfactory explanatory model : first, an overemphasis on cognition and a concomitant neglect of affect ; second, the confounding of affect and cognition by recent attempts to redress this imbalance ; and, third, the tendency to treat the relations among cognitive, affective, and behavioral aspects of intergroup relations as a one-way causal process, rather than as a system of reciprocal effects and cybernetic control . We show how affect control theory, with its twofold emphasis on affect and control, and its clear distinction between cognition and affect, provides a comprehensive, explanatory model for analyzing stereotyping and intergroup relations . To illustrate this claim, we report three studies based on intergroup attitudes for Canadian regional identities . The first applies the in-group bias/ethnocentrism and out-group
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 37-76 . Copyright © 2000 by JAI Press Inc . All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 37
38
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY homogeneity hypotheses from social cognition research on intergroup perceptions to affect control theory data on intergroup attitudes . The second employs the attribution equations of affect control theory to demonstrate how stereotypic traits can be generated from intergroup attitudes for social identities . The third applies the impression formation equations of the theory to analyze the affective outcomes of intergroup relations between Canadians with different regional identities . Our findings reveal qualified support for the application of the in-group bias and out-group homogeneity hypotheses to affect control theory data on intergroup attitudes . In addition, the generation of stereotypic traits from intergroup attitudes for regional identities, and the analysis of affective outcomes of intergroup relations, yield plausible results . Following a discussion of the limitations of our research, we show how social cognition theory and affect control theory are complementary approaches to the study of stereotyping and intergroup relations .
Originally coined by the journalist, Walter Lippman (1922), to refer to the simple, fixed, and often erroneous conceptions people have about members of social groups, stereotype remains a vibrant concept in social psychology 65 years after Katz and Braly (1933, 1935) applied it to the perception of racial groups . While sociologists and sociological social psychologists have often invoked the concept as an assumed antecedent of prejudice and discrimination, they have generally left theoretical and empirical work on stereotyping itself to psychological social psychologists (for a recent exception, see Ford and Tonander 1998) . Most of this work has been conducted within the social cognition paradigm, inspired by Tafjel's (1969, 1970) discovery that prejudice and discrimination can result from the mere categorization of individuals in laboratory settings . In the three decades following Tafjel's pioneering work, social cognition research on stereotyping has produced a massive literature (for concise summaries, see Hamilton and Mackie 1993a; Stangor, Sullivan, and Ford 1991 ; for reviews, see Hamilton, Sherman, and Ruvolo 1990 ; Messick and Mackie 1989 ; for an overview of social cognition theory from a sociological perspective, see Howard 1995). Impressive as this research has been in delineating the content and ascription of stereotypes and identifying some of the underlying cognitive mechanisms and conditions of stereotyping, it has failed to produce an adequate explanatory model of intergroup processes relating stereotypes to intergroup attitudes and behavior . For instance, one textbook laments a decade after Tafjel's (1969, 1970) pioneering work that "theories explaining the psychological process of stereotyping have not been developed or tested as have theories pertaining to the content of stereotypes . . . [and] the selection of target groups" (Albrecht, Thomas, and Chadwick 1980, p . 255) . And 10 years after this sobering assessment, Stangor, Sullivan, and Ford (1991, p. 360) conclude that "despite the voluminous research concerning patterns of social stereotype ascription, there has surprisingly been very little empirical research concerning the relationship between stereotyping and prejudice or between stereotyping and discrimination ."
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
39
Perhaps the past three decades can best be described as a period of normal science (Kuhn 1962), focusing on the implications of Tafjel's (1969, 1970) exemplary research on social categorization . Late into the 1990s research continues to address such conventional issues as differences in perceptions between groups engaged in mutual stereotyping (e .g ., Allen 1996 ; Judd and Park 1995), the perceived variability of in-groups versus out-groups (the out-group homogeneity effect) (e .g ., Judd and Park 1995 ; Lee and Ottati 1995), the favorability of in-groups versus out-groups (the in-group bias or ethnocentrism effect) (e .g., Allen 1996 ; Judd and Park 1995), and the accuracy of intergroup perceptions (e .g ., Ryan 1996) . The failure of social cognition theory to develop a satisfactory, explanatory model of intergroup processes stems in large part from its one-sided emphasis on cognition and its concomitant neglect of affect, along with the confounding of cognition and affect by recent attempts to redress this imbalance . As elaborated below, we attribute this confounding of cognition and affect to two related factors : first, a conceptualization of intergroup attitudes as summary cognitive judgments of group favorability, consisting of cognitive, affective, and behavioral components ; and, second, the use of predictive models to determine the relative contributions of these components to intergroup attitudes . For example, Esses, Haddock, and Zanna (1993) and Stangor and colleagues (1991) regressed intergroup attitudes (a single-item measure of group favorability) on personal and/or consensual stereotypes (the traits ascribed to members of social groups) and group-elicited emotions (the feelings evoked by members of social groups) . Both studies found that, net of group-elicited emotions, stereotypes play a negligible role in predicting intergroup attitudes . What are we to conclude from these implausible findings? To begin with, they are hardly surprising . The fact that both the attitude criterion and the emotions predictors are affective phenomena disadvantages stereotypic traits as predictors of intergroup attitudes . Contrary to the view that intergroup attitudes can be reduced to cognitive judgments of group favorability, we maintain that affect is involved in all such judgments . As argued below, affect is essential to attitude and cannot be excluded by definition without destroying the construct as conventionally understood. Moreover, if interpreted literally, these findings suggest that stereotypes are unimportant in explaining intergroup attitudes . Strictly speaking, however, predictive models do not explain anything, certainly not the causal relationships of stereotype-based cognitions and group-elicited emotions to intergroup attitudes, nor their causal connections to intergroup behavior itself . Besides its traditional neglect of affect, and the confounding of cognition and affect by recent attempts to rectify this deficiency, the failure of social cognition theory to develop an adequate explanatory model of intergroup processes can be attributed to a third factor : the tendency to view the relations among the cognitive, affective, and behavioral components of intergroup processes as a one-way causal process, rather than an integrative system of cybernetic feedback and control . This
40
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
is exemplified by the either-or selection of cognition-affect-behavior or affect-cognition-behavior models in the intergroup processes literature . More recent theoretical formulations, however, promise to correct this deficit . In the words of two prominent social cognition researchers, "viewing the intergroup encounter as involving constantly interacting cognitive and affective processes reveals the arbitrariness of any distinction between emotion-to cognition and cognition-to-emotion models of behavior . Instead, it becomes evident that intergroup behavior reflects the joint influence of both kinds of processes" (Hamilton and Mackie 1993b, p . 373) . This paper illustrates the application of affect control theory (Heise 1979; Smith-Lovin and Heise 1988 ; MacKinnon and Heise 1993 ; MacKinnon 1994) to intergroup processes . We begin by expanding the discussion of stereotypes, intergroup attitudes, and intergroup behavior with which we introduced this paper . Then, following a concise statement of affect control theory, we show how its conceptualization of attitude and its twofold emphasis on affect and control address the issues raised in the preceding discussion, and how the theory provides an explanatory model of intergroup processes based on reciprocal relations among stereotypes, intergroup attitudes, and intergroup behavior . Against the background of these conceptual and theoretical discussions, we illustrate the application of affect control theory to intergroup relations with attitudinal data on Canadian regional identities . These data were collected in 1995 from comparable samples of Alberta and Ontario university students, representing two regions of the country characterized by a history of interregional disparity and resentment. The research reported here comprises three distinct studies . Study 1 compares the intergroup attitudes of Alberta and Ontario samples for Canadian regional identities, exploring the classic in-group bias/ethnocentrism hypothesis and the out-group homogeneity hypothesis derived from social cognition research on stereotyping . Study 2 employs the attribution equations of affect control theory to generate stereotypic traits from intergroup attitudes for regional identities . Study 3 applies the theory's impression formation equations to explore the affective outcomes of intergroup relations between Albertans and Ontarions . In the general discussion of these three studies we address the limitations of our research and the additional issues it raises, including the use of mathematical models to study intergroup relations . We conclude this paper by showing how social cognition theory and affect control theory are complementary approaches to analyzing intergroup processes . This discussion includes a brief comparison of affect control theory with social identity theory (Tafjel 1974, 1978, 1982 ; Tajfel and Turner 1979 ; Turner 1982 ; Hogg 1992,1993 ; Hogg and Abrams 1988 ; Hogg, Terry, and White 1995), a later development in social cognition theory that advances a more adequate, explanatory model of intergroup relations than can be found in conventional social cognition research on stereotyping .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
41
STEREOTYPES, INTERGROUP ATTITUDES, AND INTERGROUP BEHAVIOR As commonly understood, stereotypes are rigid, oversimplified, and inaccurate generalizations of the traits and behavior of members of social groups . These "category-based expectations" (Jones and Gillis 1976) engender "snap judgments" (Schneider et al . 1979)-simple, unreflective, and immediate cognitive appraisals about members of a particular group . People tend to engage in more reflective and complex cognitive processing only when the appearance or behavior of group members violates category-based expectations . Thus, stereotypes are more than group concepts in the Katz and Braly (1933, 1935) tradition ; they are cognitive structures that organize and direct the processing of social information ; and, like all cognitive structures, they enable people to deal with the complexity of their social environment efficiently . In this sense, stereotypes function as prototypes (Cantor and Mischel 1979), mental representations or images of typical members of a group that serve as fuzzy categories in cognitive processing. Or, at a more general and complex level, stereotypes can be viewed as generic schemas, abstract cognitive structures that organize experience at both the perceptual and cognitive-interpretative levels of psychological processing (Mandler 1984, pp . 55-60) . More specifically, because stereotypes conespond to social identities based upon membership in or ascription to social groups, they can be treated as identity schemas (MacKinnon 1994 ; Stryker and Serpe 1994) . Although the term, role schemas, is more commonly employed in the social cognition literature, we prefer the term, identity schemas to emphasize that role behavior is predicated upon the identification with social positions, a basic assumption of both identity theory (Stryker 1968, 1980 ; McCall and Simmons 1978) and social identity theory (see references above) . Terminological preferences aside, identity or role schemas refer to "organized knowledge about the expected behaviors of occupants of particular social positions" (Howard 1995, p . 93), those pertaining, not only to instrumental activities (e .g ., familial, occupational), but also to social groups (e .g ., ethnic, racial) . From this perspective, "role [identity] schemas can be considered the [cognitive] basis of stereotyping and intergroup prejudice and discrimination" (p . 93) . In contrast to the general consensus in the intergroup relations literature on the meaning and function of stereotypes, there is considerable disagreement on the definition and role of intergroup attitudes . This reflects the dissension in attitude theory and research in general (Hill 1981) . According to conventional definition, an attitude consists of "positive or negative affect toward or evaluation of some object" (Schuman 1995, p. 68, following Thurstone 1928, 1967 ; cf. Edwards 1957 and Fishbein and Ajzen 1975) . Proponents of this definition distinguish clearly between attitude-"essentially a subjective judgment . . . of like or dislike . . . good or bad . . .favorable or unfavorable" and belief-"a probability judgment that links
42
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
some object or concept to some attribute" (Fishbein 1978, p . 378) . While the strength of an attitude is measured by the extremity, intensity, or felt importance of an affectively based evaluative judgment (Schuman 1995), the strength of a belief "is defined by the person's subjective probability that the object-attribute relationship exists (or is true)" (Fishbein 1978, p . 378) ." In short, affectively based evaluations are the essence of attitudes ; cognitive judgments, the essence of beliefs . The causal connection between the two constructs is captured by Fishbein and Ajzen's (1975) model of attitudes, which proposes that beliefs evoke attitudes, which, in turn, engender behavioral intention and response . We return to the distinction between attitudes and beliefs, or affect and cognition, in our discussion of affect control theory . Although some authors consider the identification of attitude with affect or evaluation as the conventional meaning of the construct among social psychologists (e .g ., Schuman 1995), others assert that the most popular definition of attitude today is a multicomponent one (e .g ., Delamater 1992 ; Hamilton and Mackie 1993b ; Zanna and Rempel 1988) based on Rosenberg and Hovland's (1960) definition of attitude as a relatively stable organization of cognitive, affective, and behavioral components . According to this definition, an attitude encompasses, not only what we feel about an object, but also what we think about it, and how we are inclined to behave toward it . Applying this definition to intergroup attitudes, stereotypes constitute the cognitive component ; ethnocentrism and prejudice, the affective component ; and discrimination in social relations, the behavioral component . Zanna and Rempel (1988) propose a substantial revision of Hovland and Rosenberg's definition, redefining attitude "as the categorization of a stimulus object along an evaluative dimension based upon, or generated from, three general classes of information : (1) cognitive information, (2) affective/emotional information, and/or (3) information concerning past behaviors or behavioral intentions" (p . 319) . There are three important characteristics of this definition of attitude that distinguish it from the multicomponent definition popularized by Hovland and Rosenberg (1960) . First, it considers attitudes as simple summary evaluations of an object or event along a single dimension such as good-bad or favorable-unfavorable. Second, because such summary evaluations are viewed strictly as "items of knowledge" (Zanna and Rempel 1988, p . 330), attitudes are reduced to cognitive judgments . In Zanna and Rempel's view, "evaluation and affect or emotion are not the same concept . . .emotions may be a component, or even the sole basis, of an evaluation, but the two need not occur together" (p . 320) . Third, as independently variable "sources" or "antecedents" of attitudes, cognition, affect, and behavior are not simply separate components of attitudes or different modes of response to attitude-objects or events, "they constitute very different ways in which the attitude is formed and subsequently experienced" (p . 320) .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
43
The studies of Esses and colleagues (1993) and Stangor and colleagues (1991), discussed in the introduction to this paper, take Zanna and Rempel's (1988) definition of attitude as their starting point . Regressing single-item measures of group favorability on group-elicited emotions and stereotypic traits, both studies found that the latter are of negligible import in predicting intergroup attitudes . In our earlier discussion we attributed this counterintuitive finding to the fact that traits are disadvantaged as predictors of intergroup attitudes because both the attitude criterion and the emotions predictors are affective in nature . To their credit, Stangor and colleagues acknowledge that the use of a criterion measure that may be "particularly sensitive to the affective component of prejudice . . . might have provided an unfair advantage for the emotion variables" (1991, p . 371) . Moreover, both groups of researchers interpret their findings cautiously, disclaiming any intention "to minimize the role of stereotypes in intergroup relations" (Stangor et al . 1991, pp . 376-377) or "to suggest that it is not important to understand the cognitive component of prejudice" (Esses et al . 1993, p . 158 n15) . Despite these disclaimers, the fact that both studies found that stereotyped-based cognitions play little if any role in predicting intergroup attitudes begs the question, "how then do stereotypes feed into this process?" (Hamilton and Mackie 1993b, p . 375) . This question cannot be resolved by predictive models, such as those estimated by the Esses and Stangor studies, because such single-equation models consider only the direct effects of predictors . Identification of indirect effects requires the estimation of a multiple equation causal model (a path analysis model) in conjunction with an analysis of effects (Pedhazur 1997) . To their credit, Esses and colleagues acknowledge that their research "has not examined the causal connections between intergroup attitudes and their affective, cognitive, and behavioral components" (1993, p . 160) . Contemplating the possibility that "stereotypes play a more indirect role in determining intergroup attitudes," they speculate that "the characteristics. . . we attribute to members of a group may influence how we feel about these people and thus our evaluation of the group" (p . 152) . This suggests that a model containing the following specifications should have been estimated : (1) Stereotypic Traits --- P 21 ---4(2) Group-Elicited Emotions --- P 32 ---I(3) Intergroup Attitudes (1) Stereotypic Traits p31 *(3) Intergroup Attitudes The total effect of stereotypic traits on intergroup attitudes consists of its direct effect (p31 ) plus its indirect effect via group-elicited emotions (p21P32) . The total effect of group-elicited emotions on intergroup attitudes, on the other hand, is coextensive with its direct effect (p32) . To assess the relative effects of stereotypic traits and group-elicited emotions on intergroup attitudes, one must compare the total effects (direct plus indirect) of each independent variable . In contrast, an
44
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
assessment of relative effects employing a predictive rather than a causal model is restricted to a comparison of direct effects, leading to the seemingly anomalous findings of Esses and colleagues (1993) and Stangor and colleagues (1991) . In summary, studies of intergroup processes employing Zanna and Rempel's (1988) definition of attitude as a purely cognitive evaluation based on cognitive, affective, and behavioral components, in conjunction with the use of predictive models to determine the relative contributions of these components to intergroup attitudes, create a number of problems . First, the Zanna-Rempel definition is predicated upon the assumption that attitudes can be reduced to cognitive judgments pasteurized of affect . However, as Schuman (1995, p . 85n1) has observed, "it is difficult to imagine an evaluation of interest to sociologists [and, presumably, many psychologists as well] that is totally devoid of affect ." Moreover, Stangor and colleagues (1991) implicitly question this assumption by acknowledging the possible sensitivity of their attitude measure to the emotions predictor ; and Zanna and Rempel (1988) themselves acknowledge the difficulty of creating affectively free evaluations in experimental settings . Second, because predictive models do not address the causal relations among predictors, they mask any indirect effects these predictors may have on the criterion . This appears to be the case for the stereotypes predictor in the Esses and Stangor studies . Third, predictive models do not do justice to Zanna and Rempel's (1988) definition of attitude, which emphasizes that cognition, affect, and behavior are not simply constituent components, but rather "sources" or "antecedents," of attitudes . While Zanna and Rempel (1988) suggest the use of predictive models to determine the extent to which the relative effects of these three sources of attitudes change over time, they advocate causal experimental research to study their relative effects on attitude formation and change . Finally, neither the Zanna-Rempel (1988) model of attitude nor its application to intergroup attitudes by the Stangor and Esses studies incorporates the distinction between generalized or global affect and the specific emotions . As we shall see in the following section, this distinction is a critical one in affect control theory.
AFFECT CONTROL THEORY Affect control theory formalizes Mead's (1934) model of mind as an internal process of cybernetic feedback and control, and his conceptualization of social interaction as an ongoing process of mutually adjusted response among interactants (MacKinnon 1994) . Moreover, the theory accepts Mead's premise that language creates shared objects of consciousness through social categorization, and that these social cognitions are the basis of intersubjectivity and coordination in social interaction . Contrary to Mead's view that the affective associations of social cognitions are individual or idiosyncratic rather than social, affect control theory views these sentiments as more or less shared by members of the same culture or
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
45
subculture . These cultural sentiments, rather than the social cognitions that evoke them, are the raw materials for affect control theory ; and, in contrast to Mead's cognitive social psychology, affective rather than cognitive processing is its focus . Because "affective associations to social categorization generally are recognized as `attitudes"' (Heise 1979, p . 179n1), affect control theory draws heavily upon attitude theory and research for insights into affective processing . Operationally, the theory measures cultural sentiments by capitalizing on the established EPA (evaluation, potency, activity) structure of the semantic differential (Osgood, Suci, and Tannenbaum 1957 ; Osgood, May, and Miron 1975), which Osgood has interpreted as capturing the connotative aspect of meaning, "the `feeling tones' of concepts as part of their total meaning" (1969, p . 195) . Evaluation and potency, respectively, have been identified with the sociological dimensions of status and power (Kemper and Collins 1990) ; and, depending upon context, activity has been associated with the emotional energies of social interactants (Collins 1990), the expressiveness of identity-based roles (Heise 1988, p . 6), or the agency of participants in social interaction . We describe the specific scales employed by affect control theory to measure evaluation, potency, and activity in the method section of this paper . The EPA structure of connotative, affective meaning enables one to get a quantitative handle on the indeterminable content and dimensional complexity of denotative, cognitive meaning (Heise 1979, 1988 ; MacKinnon and Langford 1994) . Because they serve as generalized attitude scales (Osgood et al . 1957, pp . 195-198), EPA ratings also allow one to measure all kinds of social phenomenasocial identities, interpersonal behaviors, social settings, social characteristics, personality traits, and emotions-on a single, common metric . Moreover, EPA rating scales provide a mathematically coherent metric (Heise 1979, p . 50), enabling one to transform one type of phenomenon into another within the same semantic space . This is accomplished in affect control theory by applying the various mathematical models of the theory . For example, given the EPA profiles for the situated identities of social interactants, one set of equations generates their culturally expected behaviors . Another set of equations simulates the reidentification processes (labeling and trait attributions) that take place when the actions of participants belie culturally expected behavior . A third set of equations generates the emotions produced by interactional events, and so on . At the heart of these various models lie the principles of affective reaction and affect control. The first principle proposes that people react affectively to interactional events, experiencing transient feelings for the actor, behavior, and object person in each event . The second principle proposes that people construct and interpret events to confirm cultural sentiments for these event components . The discrepancy between established cultural sentiments and the transient feelings produced by events is called affective deflection in affect control theory . Restating the affect control principle in these terms, people construct and interpret interactional events to minimize affective deflection . Thus, besides advancing a model of
46
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W. BOWLBY
mind based on language, affect control theory incorporates Mead's conceptualization of mind as a cybernetic control system . In contrast to Mead, however, the theory applies the principle of control to affective (attitudinal) rather than cognitive (information) processing . The overall operation of the affect control model can be summarized in six steps (adapted with revisions from Heise 1979, p . 3) . (For a formal propositional statement and verbal exposition of the theory, see MacKinnon 1994 ; for a more technical, mathematical account, see Heise 1988 .) 1.
2.
3.
4.
5. 6.
Each person present in a situation (as actor, object person, or observer) engages in cognitive work to define the situation at hand, employing social categories (identities) to identify people present. Because social identities are associated with characteristic acts (e .g ., counsel and medicate for doctor ; listen and obey for patient), additional cognitive work enables one to narrow down the potential actions of each person . At the same time, the social categories identified by all this cognitive activity evoke cultural sentiments for the imputed identities and likely behaviors of people present . Events that are judged to be comprehensible within the cognitive framework established by the definition of the situation and additional cognitive work are tentatively selected for recognition . Events that come closest to confirming cultural sentiments for their constituent identities and behaviors are more likely to be selected for final recognition than those that do not . The recognition of events generates transient impressions or feelings about participants that may confirm or disconfirm cultural sentiments for their imputed identities and perceived behaviors . Discrepancies between transient feelings and established cultural sentiments (i .e ., affective deflection) engender the conceptualization of new events that would bring transient feelings back into line with cultural sentiments . If self is the actor in such conceptualized events, a behavioral intention or disposition is the outcome of this process ; if another participant is the actor, an expectation for that person's behavior . The realization of a behavioral intention or expectation through action creates a new event, looping the process back to (2) . If cultural sentiments for the identities of participants cannot be confirmed through restorative action (5), the process loops back to (1) instead, and a person engages in a redefinition of the situation on the basis of the most recent event . This higher-order feedback helps to stabilize the system . In view of the greater observability and/or finality of behavior, a redefinition of the situation generally focuses on reidentifying participants (MacKinnon 1994, p . 24) . This is accomplished by imputing new identities (labeling) or modifying the original identities through the attribution of explanatory traits .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
47
This summary outline makes explicit three essential features of affect control theory . First, the theory specifies the relations among cognition, attitudes, and behavior, not as a simple causal chain, but rather as a control system in which people actively engage in maintaining their experience of social reality through corrective action or through reconceptualization of what has taken place . Second, the theory views the relation between cognitive and affective processes as complementary and interdependent phases of human consciousness . That is, the theory supposes that present cognitions evoke affective reaction and control which, in turn, stimulate new cognitions-the conceptualization of restorative events (see Step 4), for instance, or the reconceptualization of those that have been previously recognized (see Step 6) . Third, the theory acknowledges that attitude-behavior dynamics are "subordinate to a definition of the situation-that is, to a person's categorizations of people and objects in a scene" (Heise 1979, p . 2) . The theory does not predict the initial definition of the situation (Step 1), only its modification (see Step 6) . The original definition of the situation is provided by the researcher conducting affect control simulations of social interaction . In short, affect control theory begins with the affective associations or attitudes evoked by social categories, and models the attitude-behavior dynamics that follow . Because social categorization is the focus of social cognition theory, while attitude-behavior dynamics is the focus of affect control theory, this suggests a division of labor and a point of complementarity between the two theories . We return to this point in our general discussion . Absent from the summary outline of affect control theory just provided is the theory's model of emotions . In this regard, affect control theory distinguishes between the global affects of cultural sentiments, transient feelings, and deflection and the specific emotions experienced by participants in social interaction . Derivations from the empirically based attribution equations of the theory reveal that the latter are a consequence of two factors : first, the amount of affective deflection produced by events ; and, second, the extent to which events confirm or disconfirm the situated identities of participants (MacKinnon and Heise 1993 ; MacKinnon 1994 ; Smith-Lovin 1990) . The three studies with which we illustrate the application of affect control theory to stereotyping and intergroup relations can be located in the above outline of the theory . Study 1 employs only the cultural sentiments data (EPA measures of Canadian regional identities) (see Step 1) to test hypotheses about in-group versus out-group attitudes . Study 2 applies the attribution equations (see Step 6) to generate the characteristic traits of regional stereotypes . Study 3 employs the impression formation equations of the theory to generate the transient feelings (Step 3) and affective deflection (Step 4) produced by a set of a priori events, in order to study the affective outcomes of interaction between Canadians with different regional identities . It is important to stress, however, that simulations of intergroup relations can be conducted employing the full affect control model, including the affect control or impression management equations generating
48
NEIL] . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
interpersonal behaviors (Steps 4 and 5), and the equations predicting the specific emotions experienced by participants . While we have conducted many such analyses, considerations of space preclude reporting them here . With this brief statement of affect control theory in hand, we return to our previous discussion of stereotypes and intergroup attitudes to show how the theory addresses the issues raised there. While affect control theory accepts that stereotypes are identity schemas, it does not deal with the content of these cognitive structures directly, in the sense of measuring the traits attributed to members of social groups . In contrast to social cognition research, affect control theory takes the affective associations evoked by social identities (their EPA profiles) as its starting point . At the same time, the plausibility of affect control predictions suggests that EPA measures of social identities code much of the cognitive information embodied in identity schemas, including stereotypic beliefs about the characteristic traits and behavior of group members . For example, Study 2 shows how the stereotypic traits of Canadian regional identities can be recovered from their EPA profiles by applying the attribution equations of the theory . While the divergence between affect control and social cognition theories with respect to the concept of stereotype is more complementary than irreconcilable, it is a different matter when we turn to intergroup attitudes . In contrast to Hovland and Rosenberg's (1960) definition of attitude that includes cognition, affect, and behavior, affect control theory restricts the construct to affective meaning or response . Therefore, in contrast to Zanna and Rempel's (1988) definition of attitude, employed as a conceptual linchpin in the studies of intergroup attitudes by Esses and colleagues (1993) and Stangor and colleagues (1991), the theory does not accept that evaluations can be reduced to cognitive judgments devoid of affect. For affect control theory, affect is an essential property of attitude and cannot be eliminated by definitional fiat without destroying the construct as conventionally understood. Affect control theory recognizes that, ontologically, cognition and affect are inextricable modes of psychological experience, a matter of relative preponderance than mutual exclusiveness . Epistemologically, however, the theory recognizes the distinction between cognition and affect is an analytically useful one"particularly at the extremes of `cold' cognitions (where affective arousal is of low intensity) and `hot' cognitions (where affective arousal is more pronounced) ; or, alternatively, at the extremes of affective experience largely unmediated by cognition and that conjoined with a high level of cognitive awareness and appraisal" (MacKinnon 1994, p . 45) . From this perspective, beliefs are more cognitive than affective ; and attitudes, more affective than cognitive . Moreover, some attitudes are hotter than others-that is, of greater intensity in either direction on the bipolar scales employed to measure them . For example, while a bigot evokes intense negative feelings (-2 .34) on the evaluation scale for Canadian male respondents, and a charity worker, intense positive feelings (2 .48), other identities evoke affective associations that are closer to neutral on the evaluation scale (e .g .,
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
49
.39 for a customer) . (For an extensive discussion of the relation between cognition and affect as debated in the psychological literature, and the implications of this issue for affect control theory, see MacKinnon 1994, pp . 41-50 .) Thus far, we have discussed attitude as the affective response to objects in terms of positive or negative evaluation (good-bad, favorable-unfavorable, and so on) . However, following the EPA structure of affective meaning established by Osgood and associates (Osgood 1969 ; Osgood, May, and Miron 1975), affect control theory extends the domain of attitude to feelings of potency and activity as well . Whether viewed in terms of E or EPA, restricting the construct of attitude to affective response analytically separates intergroup attitudes (ethnocentrism and prejudice) from their presumed antecedents (stereotype-based cognitions) and behavioral consequences (social discrimination) . As acknowledged by Zanna and Rempel, this one-component definition of attitude has the advantage of making the consistency between attitudes and behavior "a theoretical or even empirical question rather than a definitional necessity" (1988, p . 316) . Besides rejecting Zanna and Rempel's reduction of attitudes to cognitive judgments devoid of affect, affect control theory does not share the view of these authors that emotions are a direct source of attitudes . Instead, as discussed above, the theory treats emotions as a product of the more global affective dynamics of identity processes in social interaction . On the other hand, the theory's emphasis on the role of action in attitude-formation and change (Heise 1979, p . 38) is consistent with Zanna and Rempel's identification of past behavior and behavioral intentions as important sources of attitudes . As discussed above, affect control theory views the relation between attitudes and behavior as a reciprocal process of cybernetic feedback and control, rather than as one-way causal process . While this model of attitude resonates with the model proposed by Fishbein and Ajzen (1975), there is an important difference in emphasis . In the Fishbein and Ajzen model, the feedback from behavior to attitude is more incidental than designed . In the affect control model, the discrepancy between fundamental attitudes and the transient attitudes produced by events "generate behaviors designed to create new feelings that confirm fundamental attitudes" (Heise 1979, p . 39) . This model of attitudes sheds some light on the empirically tenuous link between attitudes and behavior that continues to plague attitude theory in general (Hill 1981 ; Schuman 1995) and theories of intergroup processes in particular (Mackie and Hamilton 1993b ; Seeman 1981 ; Zanna and Rempel 1988) . According to the affect control model of attitudes, "behavior is not generated directly from either fundamental or transient attitudes but rather from the discrepancy between the two ." Hence, "an attitude as such does not ordinarily generate any typical behavior" (Heise 1979, pp. 38-39) . In summary, affect control theory provides a powerful model for exploring the relationships among stereotypes, intergroup attitudes, and intergroup relations, an explanatory model of intergroup processes based on attitude-behavior dynamics and affective processing . From the perspective of affect control theory, ste-
50
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
reotypes are identity schemas deriving from membership in or ascription to social groups ; intergroup attitudes are the cultural sentiments evoked by group identities ; and stereotyping itself exemplifies the identification processes that underlie all social interaction . Thus, the theory models stereotyping and intergroup relations in the same way that it models identification processes and social interaction in general . When people act in accord with their group identities, affective deflection is minimal and interaction between members of social groups proceeds in stereotypic fashion . When the actions of group members deviate from stereotype-based expectations, the motivation to minimize affective deflection mobilizes restorative actions to repair the violation of the "expressive order" (Goffman 1967) defined by intergroup attitudes . In the event that the deflection produced by disruptive events cannot be resolved through restorative action, stereotypes themselves may become modified through the attribution of explanatory traits, or discarded altogether through the imputation of entirely new identities .
METHOD The general methodology of affect control research is available from a number of published sources (e .g ., Heise 1978 ; Smith-Lovin and Heise 1988), enabling us to restrict our discussion to details specific to the research reported here . In this section we describe the sample, instrument, and measurement procedures employed in this research . We discuss other aspects of research design, including data analysis procedures, in the specific sections dealing with each of our three studies . Sample Data on cultural sentiments for regional identities were collected as part of a larger study conducted in 1995, employing convenience samples of undergraduate students enrolled in introductory sociology methods courses at an Ontario and an Alberta university . Each of the two samples consisted of approximately 30 males and 30 females born and/or raised in Canada . Instrument Our survey instrument was introduced by a covering page, providing instructions to respondents and asking them to provide information on their gender and the country in which they were born and/or raised . The body of the survey consisted of 11 pages of word stimuli pertaining to social identities and interpersonal behaviors . Each word stimulus was followed by the evaluation, potency, and activity semantic differential scales described in the next section .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
51
Measurement We measured the affective meaning of regional identities and interpersonal acts with the evaluation, potency, and activity scales developed in past affect control research . The evaluation scale is anchored by "bad, awful" to "good, nice" ; the potency scale, by "small, weak, powerless" to "big, strong, powerful" ; and the activity scale, by "slow, old, quiet" to "fast, young, noisy ." Calibrated from -4 to +4, each scale captures a wide range of negative to positive valence, from infinitely "bad, awful" to infinitely "good, nice," for example . Actual values generally fall between ±3, with a ±2 considered a large (positive or negative) value . Following established procedures in affect control research, estimates of cultural sentiments were obtained by aggregating individual scores on EPA scales . As discussed above, affective deflection (the dependent variable in Study 3) is conceptualized as the discrepancy between the fundamental cultural sentiments for social identities and interpersonal behaviors outside the context of any event and the transient impressions or feelings for these components created by their combination in ABO (Actor-Behavior-Object) events . Thus, deflection can be viewed as a kind of global affective response to interpersonal events, employing fundamental cultural sentiments as a point of reference . Operationally, deflection is measured as the sum of the squared discrepancies between fundamental sentiments and transient impressions for the ABO (Actor-Behavior-Object) components of events on the EPA (evaluation, potency, and activity) dimensions of affective meaning : Deflection = E [(A e - Ae' )2+ (Ap - Ap')2 + (A a - Aa ) 2 + (B e - B e' )2 + (BP - Bp' )2 + (B a - Bay )2+ We - Oe ')2 + (op -O p ')2 +(Oa -Oa ) 2 ]
Unprimed terms in this expression denote fundamental cultural sentiments ; primed terms, transient impressions created by events . Subscripts (e, p, a) denote evaluation, potency, and activity . Squaring discrepancies avoids the cumbersome algebra of absolute differences and provides greater weight to larger discrepancies than to trivial ones . The fundamental sentiments in the deflection measure are simply the mean EPA values of identities and behaviors measured on the semantic differential scales described above . The transient impressions or feelings created by events analyzed in Study 3 were generated from the empirically based impression formation equations of affect control theory, employing estimates of parameters from earlier Canadian research (MacKinnon 1985) . Because these equations are far too complex to discuss here, we refer the interested reader to Heise (1988) and Smith-Lovin (1988) for technical detail .
52
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
STUDY 1
The first study explores two classic hypotheses from social cognition research on stereotyping, employing Alberta and Ontario data on cultural sentiments for Canadian regional identities . According to the in-group bias or ethnocentrism hypothesis, people tend to evaluate their own group more favorably than out-groups . According to the out-group homogeneity hypothesis, people tend to perceive members of an out-group as more stereotypic and less diverse than members of that group see themselves (Judd and Park 1995) . This study differs from past research on these hypotheses in two important ways . First, we apply the ethnocentrism and out-group homogeneity hypotheses to intergroup attitudes (cultural sentiments) rather than to intergroup perceptions (attributed traits), the usual focus of social cognition research on these hypotheses (e.g ., Judd and Park 1995) . Second, we explore whether the ethnocentrism effect generalizes from evaluation (the dimension of attitude emphasized by social cognition research) to the potency and activity dimensions of affective response . On the other hand, by studying the attitudes of both Albertans and Ontarions, we maintain the intergroup perspective of more recent work on stereotyping by social cognition researchers (e .g ., Allen 1996 ; Judd and Park 1995) . Findings In-group Bias/Ethnocentrism Hypothesis
Evidence for this hypothesis within each sample is provided by comparing mean attitudes for regional identities down columns in Table 1 . For example, the mean evaluation of male Alberta respondents for an Albertan (2 .01) is higher than its evaluation of all other regional identities-Maritimer (1 .74), Ontarion ( .42), and Quebecer (- .30) . This pattern prevails for female Alberta respondents and for Ontario respondents of both genders, with one minor exception-Ontario respondents evaluate a Maritimer as a bit nicer than an Ontarion . We do not report tests of significance for within-sample comparisons of means because such comparisons probably violate the assumption of statistically independent evaluations (Blalock 1979, p . 141) . The ethnocentrism hypothesis is tested across samples by comparing the mean evaluations of Alberta and Ontario respondents for their respective regional identities, Albertan and Ontarion . Although the two samples are not random, we employ tests of significance here as a heuristic device to discriminate between the trivial and the possibly important . As revealed by across-row comparisons in Table 1, Alberta respondents evaluate an Albertan more highly than Ontario respondents do (2 .01 versus .76 for male respondents ; 1 .84 versus .98 for female respondents) ; and Ontario respondents evaluate an Ontarion more highly than Alberta respondents (1 . 16 versus .42 for male respondents ; 1 .12 versus .66 for
•
•~o
10 P, lD V n N M
•
O
O
r u M
M O M N N 10 00 h
C}
0 R N
O
m L N -D
O 0 n M N N N 0-c
Q
•
E • C/') •
N ;! M n N 0~ 0C
Q
n .- O M Z3 O ~ iD N r
Q
00o~v v C v M C-
• •
00 N to M N ' M M r ' N N
C ro
N
U
O
U N C
0-c O cO cO 7 V ~ V'
C
0
O 2 0C in N N
a>
V
0
ro
11
N N n O ~o co
Q1
-Q
N O N M l0 M 00 r
Q
Q
x x M V ~O 0~ M - r C O
C O
0 W
0
O
W
O y C O
co 0-~ N cO O~ M r O
ro
rq
aN
V N O O n V M N
0-c 10 00 v .O 00 cc co V Q
C
O C N E O N Y N
•
.p Q
'0 0
C V Q
Q~E
C
0
ooa
._E C N Q) Q :2 oa
53
O z
54
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W. BOWLBY
female respondents) . While the latter comparison falls short of statistical significance, the overall pattern of differences supports the in-group bias/ethnocentrism hypothesis for the evaluation dimension of affective meaning . Extending the ethnocentrism hypothesis to the potency dimension of affective meaning, both male and female Ontario respondents view an Ontarion as more powerful than all other regional identities . However, contrary to the hypothesis, male Alberta respondents view an Albertan as less powerful than an Ontarion, and female Alberta respondents view an Albertan as less powerful than either an Ontarion or a Quebecer. Applying the hypothesis to across-sample comparisons, Alberta respondents view an Albertan as more powerful than Ontario respondents do (1 .12 versus .49 for male respondents ; .62 versus .29 for females), albeit the latter difference does not achieve statistical significance . While these across-sample differences support the ethnocentrism hypothesis for Albertan as the in-group target identity, across-sample comparisons for Ontarion as the in-group target identity does not . In fact, Alberta respondents rate an Ontarion as more powerful than Ontario respondents rate themselves (1 .67 versus 1 .16 for males ; 1 .82 versus 1 .15 for females) . Taken together, these findings provide only limited support for extending the ethnocentrism hypothesis to the potency dimension of affective response . Within-sample (down-column) comparisons for the activity dimension of affective response also reveal only limited support for the ethnocentrism hypothesis . Consistent with the hypothesis, Ontario respondents of either gender see themselves as more lively than Albertans, Maritimers, or Quebecers, and male Alberta respondents also view themselves as more lively than Canadians from other regions . However, contrary to the hypothesis, female Alberta respondents see themselves as less lively than either an Ontarion or a Quebecer . Moving to across-sample comparisons, Albertans view themselves as significantly more lively than Ontario respondents do (1 .20 versus .11 for males ; .72 versus - .23 for females) . Although these comparisons support the hypothesis for Albertan as the in-group target identity, those for Ontarion as the in-group target identity are small, statistically insignificant, and inconsistent in direction across gender . The Out-Group Homogeneity Hypothesis
Following the statement of this hypothesis by Judd and Park (1995)-in terms of intergroup perceptions or mutual stereotyping, we explore the hypothesis with across-sample comparisons of intergroup attitudes for Albertan and Ontarion as out-group target identities . We use standard deviations to measure the homogeneity of group attitudes, smaller values indicating greater homogeneity . We do not employ tests of significance for differences of standard deviations across samples, even as a heuristic device, because such (two-sample F) tests are notoriously unrobust in the presence of even slight departures from normality (Moore and McCabe 1993 ; Pearson and Please 1975) . Therefore, differences in standard devi-
v
0 rtl C O
C O
0 O O
~O N
a
U Q
fTS C
O OA
L O y w n C
n 00 C~ Ol 0 O~ N
U Q N .Q Q
aJ
ro G O
co -It ~o ~Y I~ -~ In
v
N C N M M O M
Q
0
cz Cn O c
W N N O O~ O N
cu
c a U
L
N O
C
L
C
O ~ n O
C O
C O N
Q1
v C
C ro
G (li
W
m
ro
O N M I. n V N C
C Q)
N
Q
Q
t
Q m O
O L V O
. n N 0 O O
O ~
C O ro W
G O ro ro W
m Q!
W Ln ~O N ,I: N M O~
Q
O
u a)
M -Q N N N N
Q
U N C ro
c
E .0 .ro
Q
C
ci
c Boa
c 0
55
y
C E .o ro
U
Q~oa
56
NEIL) . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
ations between samples must be interpreted strictly as sample-bound, descriptive data which we employ to explore rather than test the homogeneity hypothesis . As reported in Table 2, Ontario respondents view an Albertan as more homogenous on evaluation than Alberta respondents themselves (1 .14 versus 1 .48 for males ; .87 versus 1 .21 for females . Ontario respondents also view an Albertan as more homogenous on potency than Alberta respondents ( .98 versus 1 .49 for males ; .70 versus 1 .36 for females), and more homogenous on activity as well (1 .00 versus 1 .41 for males; .97 versus 1 .31 for females) . Thus, for the Ontario sample as the in-group and Albertan as the out-group target identity, these findings support the out-group homogeneity hypothesis across all three dimensions of intergroup attitudes . In contrast, our findings reveal a reversal of the out-group homogeneity effect for the Alberta sample as the in-group and Ontarion as the out-group target identity . That is, Alberta respondents view an Ontarion as less homogenous than Ontario respondents themselves on all three dimensions of affective meaning . For evaluation, the relevant comparisons yield 1 .36 for Alberta male respondents versus 1 .04 for Ontario male respondents (1 .26 versus 1 .07 for females) ; for potency, 1 .43 versus 1 .17 (males) and 1 .25 versus 1 .17 (females) ; and for activity, 1 .64 versus 1 .06 (males) and 1 .09 versus .99 (females) . Discussion This study applied the ethnocentrism and out-group homogeneity hypotheses from social cognition research on stereotyping to Alberta and Ontario attitudes for Canadian regional identities . While both within- and across-sample comparisons support the ethnocentrism hypothesis for evaluation, the results are mixed when the hypothesis is extended to the potency and activity dimensions of intergroup attitudes . Within-sample comparisons on potency support the hypothesis for only the Ontario sample . In across-sample comparisons on potency, the ethnocentrism effect was found for Albertan as the in-group target identity, but a reversal of the effect was found for Ontarion as the in-group target identity . With the exception of Alberta females, within-sample comparisons support the ethnocentrism hypothesis for the activity dimension of intergroup attitudes . On the other hand, across-sample comparisons on activity reveal the ethnocentrism effect only for Albertan as the in-group target identity . Our findings support the out-group homogeneity hypothesis for the evaluation, potency, and activity dimensions of intergroup attitudes, but for only the Ontario sample as in-group and Albertan as the out-group identity . In fact, for all three dimensions of intergroup attitudes, we found a reversal of the out-group homogeneity effect for the Alberta sample as in-group and Ontarion as the out-group identity . The group-specific nature of the ethnocentrism and out-group homogeneity effects revealed by this study resonates with the findings of Judd and Park (1995) .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
57
Eliminating rival hypotheses through a sequence of carefully designed studies and sophisticated analyses, these researchers accumulated support for a differential socialization explanation of their finding that African-American university students manifested ethnocentrism and in-group homogeneity effects while white American students did not . Specifically, Judd and Park (1995) argue that young black Americans have been socialized to believe that ethnic group membership is a meaningful social category and social identity, to be emphasized in the ongoing struggle for social equality, while young white Americans have been socialized to avoid making distinctions on the basis of ethnic group membership . While the intensity of interregional relations in Canada pales by comparison to the intensity of racial conflict in the United States, the differential socialization hypothesis proposed by Judd and Park (1995) may help to explain some of our findings-specifically, the greater ethnocentrism effect for the Alberta sample on evaluation and the manifestation of this effect on potency and activity for the Alberta sample only . Historically, Western Canada has been an economically disadvantaged region relative to Central Canada ; and although this disparity has narrowed in recent decades, intergroup attitudes may lag behind economic change . If true, we would expect the intergroup attitudes of young Albertans to manifest greater in-group favorability than those of young Ontarions, the kind of defensive ethnocentrism described by Judd and Park (1995) . While this line of reasoning helps to explain why the ethnocentrism effect is stronger for the Alberta sample, it does not shed light on why a reversal of the out-group homogeneity effect was found for Albertans (historically, the economically disadvantaged in-group) with Ontarion as the out-group target identity ; nor, by the same token, does it explain why the out-group homogeneity effect was manifested only for Ontarions (historically, the economically advantaged group) with Albertan as the out-group target identity . However, while many studies have revealed that in-group members perceive out-group members as more homogeneous and less variable than themselves, other studies reveal that this is far from a universal tendency (see Lee and Ottati 1995 for references) . Moreover, the form in which we have stated and tested the out-group homogeneity hypothesis in this study employs the in-group homogeneity of the target group itself as a basis for comparison. Therefore, the in-group homogeneity of target groups becomes relevant to explaining our findings with respect to the out-group homogeneity hypothesis . In this regard, Lee and Ottati demonstrate experimentally how cognitive and motivational factors affect in-group homogeneity, suggesting that "instead of being static, perceptions of in-group variation appear to fluctuate across time and circumstances" (p . 610) . The issues here are complex and we can only speculate as to why Ontarions exhibit greater in-group homogeneity for their group identity than Albertans do for theirs (see Table 2) . However, since the purpose of this paper is to illustrate the application of affect control theory to stereotyping and intergroup relations, rather than to debate the relative merits of any
58
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W. BOWLBY
particular explanation, we move on to the next study without additional commentary .
STUDY 2 As discussed in our description of affect control theory, the measurement of all kinds of social phenomena on EPA scales enables one to transform the affective meaning of one type of phenomenon into another within the same semantic space . This study illustrates how stereotypic traits can be generated from social identities by employing the attribution equations of the theory . In affect control theory, traits are treated as descriptive attributions of a person with a particular social identity . The procedure of recovering characteristic or stereotypic traits from social identities involves simulating a social event that perfectly confirms a particular social identity, then applying the attribution equations to generate a numerical EPA profile for the kinds of traits that might be attributed to a person with this confirmed identity . With this numerical EPA profile in hand, the cultural data base for identity modifiers is searched for traits that optimally fit this test profile . This procedure is based on the notion that when events perfectly confirm a person's social identity, the traits attributed to that person become a function of the cultural sentiments for that identity (see MacKinnon 1994, p . 128 for a discussion of this rationale applied to characteristic or stereotypic emotions) . For example, when an event (say the delivery of a flawless, enthusiastically received lecture) confirms a professor's identity, observers of this event might consider that professor to be studious, experienced, dignified, tactful, practical, responsible, reasonable, and mature (predictions from Canadian equations and cultural sentiments) . Table 3 reports the characteristic or stereotypic traits generated by the attribution equations of affect control theory for the four regional identities employed in Study 1 . Each list of traits is preceded by the numerical EPA profile generated by the model and trait retrievals are ordered according to their fit to this test profile . For example, the numerical EPA profile (2.8 1 .9 .7) suggests that the characteristic traits attributed to an Albertan by male Alberta respondents would be extremely positive, quite powerful, and slightly lively in nature friendly, loved, employed, confident, competent, talented, and reliable. Those attributed to an Albertan by male Ontario respondents (1 .2 1 .1 .1) are much lower on evaluation and notably less on potency and activity as well-conscientious, modest, tactful, sophisticated, poised, accommodating, and practical . The difference in stereotypic traits attributed to an Albertan by male Alberta and Ontario respondents stem from differences in their cultural sentiments for this social identity . Because male Alberta respondents view themselves as much nicer and more powerful and lively than male Ontarion respondents do (see Table 1), they make self-attributions that are more positive, powerful, and lively .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations Table 3 .
59
Stereotypic Traits of Regional Identities for Alberta and Ontario Samples Males
Regional Identity
Albertan
Ontarion
Maritimer
Quebecer
Alberta
Females Ontario
Alberta
Ontario
(2 .8 1 .9 .7)
(1 .2 1 .1 .1)
(2 .31 .4 .4)
(1 .2 1 .0 - .1)
friendly loved employed confident competent talented reliable
conscientious modest tactful sophisticated poised accomodating practical
easygoing helpful worthy trusting appreciative cooperative intellectual
poised virtuous cautious contented modest sophisticated warm
(1 .5 1 .8 .6)
(2 .01 .7 .7)
(1 .82 .0 .7)
(1 .9 1 .6 .5)
witty wealthy intellectual rich persuasive perceptive successful
original bright efficient self-discipl talented confident wealthy
confident clever self-discipl perceptive rich wealthy independent
intellectual worthy self-discipl clever respectful charming creative
(1 .3 .5 - .6)
(1 .4 .7- .2)
(1 .4 .8- .7)
(1 .3 .7- .4)
wholesome noble humble religious discrete cautious
accomodating earnest modest noble agreeable
wholesome accomodating modest earthy humble reverent sentimental
modest earthy accomodating agreeable humble cautious poised
( .71 .1 .8)
( .7 .9 .7)
(1 .41 .5 .7)
(.7 .9 .6)
modern well-bred provocative demanding talkative suave idealistic
suave lucky modern clean-cut demanding white normal
well-bred charming married witty creative rich earnest
sensuous idealistic masculine sophisticated suave normal candid
The numerical EPA profile for the characteristic traits of an Ontarion is more similar for male respondents from each province, differing only in the higher evaluation of traits (2 .0 versus 1 .5) attributed by Ontario males to themselves . Interestingly, considering the historical status of Ontario as the most prosperous Canadian province, Alberta respondents view an Ontarion as wealthy, rich, and successful . In contrast, the self-attributions of Ontario respondents emphasize talent, intelligence, and efficiency-original, bright, intellectual, clever, efficient, self-disciplined, and talented, depending on the gender of respondent . The EPA profile generated by the attributions equations for a Maritimer is quite similar across both province and gender, denoting traits that are positive, weak,
60
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W. BOWLBY
and unlively in nature-wholesome, noble, modest, humble, accommodating, agreeable, earnest, discrete, cautious, religious, reverent, and sentimental. Again, these traits are consistent with the positive, weak, and unlively cultural sentiments for a Maritimer reported in Study I (see Table 1) . With the exception of Alberta females, the EPA profile for the stereotypic traits of a Quebecer is also quite similar across samples, resulting in trait retrievals that are slightly good, powerful, and lively-modern, suave, well-bred, and the like . In the case of Alberta females, whose EPA profile is much higher on evaluation and a bit higher on potency, retrievals also include such traits as charming, witty, and creative. In view of the resurgence of Quebec nationalism in the last two decades, and the publicly expressed frustration by other Canadians to understand the aspirations of Quebecers, the most interesting trait retrievals are those that describe a Quebecer as provocative, demanding, and idealistic. Again, these trait retrievals reflect the cultural sentiments for the regional identity at hand . As reported in Study 1 (see Table 1), a Quebecer is viewed as slightly negative to slightly positive on evaluation, and as low to slightly positive on potency and activity, depending on the gender and province of the respondent . Discussion
This study demonstrates how the stereotypic traits attributed to Canadians from different regions of the country can be generated from the cultural sentiments for regional identities by applying the attribution equations of affect control theory . Since cultural sentiments for regional identities differ by region, the stereotypic traits attributed to these identities differ across region as well . The differences in trait attributions between Alberta and Ontario samples revealed by our findings are plausible enough, judging by our knowledge of Canadian culture . However, because stereotypic traits were not measured directly in this study, our findings should be considered hypotheses for more conventional research in the social cognition tradition . We return to this point in our general discussion of findings .
STUDY 3 This study explores the affective outcomes of intergroup relations between Albertans and Ontarions from the cultural perspective of each group . Design and Analysis
The units of analysis in this study are interpersonal events . The dependent variable is affective deflection, described in the method section of this paper. We regress the affective deflection produced by events on the nature of the act (its evaluation, potency, and activity), the type of event (Ontarion > Albertan and
v -
v rou v
ra v
o c
Q b o >
£ >
a) N ro
a 22
E
v
v
p A E u y L
y
O_
C
-N
R1 E
c i
3
o
aN
L
L
C
a
o p
v a) v z
v
v v
;9 E ro v -o .-
E- 'ro
0 0E W
0 3 v
O
E u
ao . c '
Y O
O N V' 0 r I
Ln c N W ~ I
W M r
N V rn cc M I r I
v °
v
co °
v
v
O '-
M N
O cC O N
V I
C cO O Cn cC I
•
I + +
+ I +
+ +
w co
W W
61
cd L
v m v
N
v av v = v = ro ro v =m v = ro v = ro yv u ro E ra E ra E ro E ra E a E ro E ro E E a? E- E .v E- E 01 E- E- E-
I I +
ft
•E
L
o v
•pN-n y0 E `~ O rp L v _ a 0 v u O- 2 f_ v O U° 2 v E -O 7 C Y a p C o
• •
c
y v °
v
v u `-o
73
0 c
° Q E '~ ao avo c v ro w ° v vE a °c C a - bO
°v N a w N cn 0 E v ° o > o v v u ° o c ro
a
-'
v a
a s
4 C
v
a
m ° v
a v ._ ro yo v v -a a C - .N a u ai `°
ro
WD bu> >. w 3O ..Q Y v 3 N N D
o o u
m
v4
C v a Cv ce C ro a) 4O L Q W
62
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
Albertan > Ontarion), and interactions between these two sets of predictors . The analysis is replicated across Alberta and Ontario samples to determine the effect of cultural perspective on the affective outcomes of intergroup events . In one analysis we employ the cultural sentiments of the Alberta sample for an Albertan and an Ontarion ; in the other those of the Ontario sample for the two regional identities . In the dummy variable analysis for the Alberta sample, we employ Albertan > Albertan events as the reference category ; in the analysis for the Ontario sample, Ontarion > Ontarion events . This enables one to compare the effect of out-group to in-group interaction within each analysis, To ensure maximum variation in behavior for the events analyzed in this study, we searched our Canadian database for behaviors having EPA profiles closest to the eight possible configurations of low (-) and high (+) EPA values listed in Figure 1 . The empirical EPA profiles for behaviors available in our database that come closest to these ideal EPA profiles are reported in Figure 1, along with representative behaviors . In some cases empirical EPA profiles only approximate ideal EPA configurations because of the unavailability of matching behaviors . For instance, there are no behaviors that are simultaneously high on evaluation and low on potency . As a consequence, empirical EPA profiles are close to neutral on potency for (+ - +) and (+ --) configurations ; and, because behavior is inherently lively, a number of other empirical EPA profiles are close to neutral on activity . Behaviors were selected from those listed in Figure 1 to construct the events analyzed in this study . A cross-classification of these eight types of behaviors by the three types of events described above yields 24 ABO (actor-behavior-object person) events to analyze for each gender, or 48 events in all when pooled across gender . These 48 events were analyzed separately for the Ontario and Alberta samples, yielding parallel equations describing the affective outcomes of intergroup relations from the cultural perspective of each group . Employing ordinary least squares regression, we performed a dummy variable analysis for each sample to estimate the effects of event-type (D1 : Ontarion > Albertan events ; D2 : Albertan > Ontarion events), the evaluation, potency, and activity of the behavior in each event (BE, BP, and BA), and the interactions between event-type and the nature of the act (D1BE, D1BP, D1BA and D2BE, D2BP, D2BA) . As explained above, in-group interaction (Ontarion > Ontarion events in the Ontario equation ; Albertan > Albertan events in the Alberta equation) was defined as the reference category, thus omitted from the equation for each sample . In preliminary analysis, we included a dummy variable for the gender of respondent and tested its main and interaction effects with event-type and behavior evaluation, potency, and activity . Because neither main nor interaction effects were found, gender was deleted from the regression analysis . Thus, the general equation for the dummy variable analysis reported in this study is as follows :
O OO OO OO ON OO OC ~0 O M N O CL O 0 0 0 0 0 0 7 C~M OO N;-o0N OC
E
U > wQ) LoM m > U
'O t M N t0 0~ r t N ~O a1 Ct CO of WN MN ~0t t~OW Oo0 ON'D N NN t '°N -N`° I I ~ OM ro CW7ro`v co IO u)t c in t cc rn N M u1 u1W Co u)t 10 N NM~7n C4 . N r-N Q N N N
C C U > le Q) WC CL NO L
tIn NLnN~o l0 l0 N O1 M 10 M h N r, 10 u1 inC0O tItN ~oM 0.-C~M NN CN ~n I I N
0 O 0 II d Ma
fl II C 0 7 0Q r. II C OO O
c3 .Nco0 0^ M OO CL 0O 0O 0O 0O 0O Mn co 0 r-
C O Q U • N •
GO
N . N 1 Ln M un N 0 ~ON~O O O t M t O IM C-4 IDLn O O N M C~ M M t N ~-- O
W O • Oc ~c M u7 u1 l0 u) n l0 V) Q-'D•O O O O O M t O M t 7
t NCcotr.000 NO t ..O u1 t ~O t MLnM r.M mO NO MO mn nM NN u1 t I r-i I I M • •
c a• -Q v •vv .~~ a _ S
c w o Q m C C N N C c cc) co co 0 C) Q
63
64
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W. BOWLBY
Deflection' = a + b1D1 + b 2 D2 + b 3 BE + b4BP + b 5 BA + b6D1BE + b 7 D1BP + b 8 DIBA + b 9 D2BE + b 10D2BP + b1 1 D2BA For predicting the affective deflection produced by a particular type of event (D 1 : Ontarion > Albertan or D2 : Albertan > Ontario), this equation reduces to the constant (a), the main effect of event-type (either D1 or D2) ; the evaluation, potency, and activity of the behavior (BE, BP, and BA) ; and three terms (either D1BE, D1 BP, D1BA or D2BE, D2BP, D2BA) representing the interaction of event-type with the nature of the act. Findings Overall Equation
As reported in Table 4, the overall equation explains 97 percent of the variance in deflection for the Alberta sample (F = 96 .983 ; p = .000) and an equivalent amount of variance for the Ontario sample (F = 98 .741 ; p = .000) . Behavioral Dynamics
In this section we deal with the main effects of behavior evaluation (BE), potency (BP), and activity (BA), net of event-type (Dl or D2) and interactions between event-type and the nature of the act (D1BE, D1BP . . . D2BA) . For both samples, behavior evaluation, potency, and activity manifest sizable and significant effects on deflection (-2 .567, p = .000 ; .656, p = .000 ; - .406, p = .020, respectively, for the Alberta equation ; -1 .348, p < .001 ; .354, p < .001 ; - .377, p < .001 for the Ontario equation) . The direction of these effects in both equations indicates that nice and lively behaviors between Albertans and Ontarions reduce affective deflection while powerful actions increase it . While the pattern of effects is similar across equations, the effects of behavior evaluation and potency are notably larger in the Alberta equation . The main effects of behavior evaluation, potency, and activity are modified by a number of interactions with event-type-D1BE and D1BP for the Alberta equation, D2BE for both equations, and so on . While one can interpret these interactions in terms of event-type moderating the main effects of behavior, the principal concern of this study is with the effect of event-type (Ontarion > Albertan versus Albertan > Ontarion) on the affective deflection produced by intergroup relations . Therefore, we delay our discussion of interaction effects until the following section, where we interpret them in terms of the nature of the act (BE, BP, and BA) moderating the amount of deflection produced by event-type (D1 and D2) .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
65
Effects of Event-Type on Deflection The main effects of BE, BP, and BA have been discussed in the preceding section . Because the pattern of these effects is similar in the general equations for Alberta and Ontarion samples, we ignore them here in order to simplify our presentation of findings regarding the effects of event-type on affective deflection . Dl : Ontarion > Albertan Events Alberta equation : Deflection' = 5 .571 - 1 .264D1 + 1 .246DIBE - .367DIBP Ontario equation : Deflection' = 3 .454 - .454D1 Recalling that the reference categories for the Alberta and Ontario equations are, respectively, Albertan > Albertan and Ontarion > Ontarion events, the negative coefficient for D1 in both equations indicates that out-group interaction involving Ontarion >Albertan events produces less deflection than in-group interaction . While the main effect of D1 events is about three times larger in the Alberta equation (-1 .264 ; p = .000) than in the Ontario equation (- .454 ; p = .000), it is moderated by behavior evaluation (BE) and potency (BP) in the Alberta equation . The sign of the D1BE effect in the Alberta equation suggests that the nicer the actions of an Albertan toward an Ontarion, the larger the deflection produced by D1 (Ontarion > Albertan) events . Considering the size of this effect (1 .246 ; p = .000), positively evaluated actions by an Ontarion could easily wash out the reduction in deflection (-1 .264) produced by the main effect of D1 events in the Alberta equation . Recalling our discussion of Table 1, both Albertan and Ontarion are positively evaluated identities for Alberta respondents, albeit they evaluate an Albertan as much nicer than an Ontarion . The impression formation equations of affect control theory reveal that unexpectedly good actions produce transient impressions that enhance the fundamental status of both actor and recipient . Therefore, unexpectedly nice actions in Ontarion > Albertan events produce sizeable deflections because such events create transient impressions that exceed the fundamental positive status of both participants . The large positive effect of D1BE in the Alberta equation simply captures this property of the evaluation dynamics of affect control theory . The potency of the act also moderates the main effect of D1 (Ontarion > Albertan) events in the Alberta equation . In this case, the negative coefficient for the D1BP term (- .367 ; p = .10) reveals that powerful actions by an Ontarion enhance the reduction in deflection produced by D1 (Ontarion > Albertan) events . As reported in Table 1, Alberta respondents view Ontarions as more powerful than themselves ; and according to the impression formation equations of affect control theory, powerful actions maintain the fundamental potency of powerful actors and the relative impotency of weaker recipients . Thus, deflection should be reduced
66
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W. BOWLBY
when an Ontarion implements powerful actions in Ontarion > Albertan events . The negative coefficient for D1 BP in the Alberta equation simply reflects this aspect of the potency dynamics of affect control theory . In sum, the amount of affective deflection produced by Ontarion > Albertan events for Alberta respondents depends, not only on their cultural sentiments for the two regional identities, but also on what an Ontarion actually does to an Albertan . By the same token, the absence of interactions between event-type and behavior in the Ontario equation reveals that the amount of deflection produced by Ontarion > Albertan events for Ontario respondents is influenced solely by their cultural sentiments for an Ontarion and an Albertan . D2 : Albertan > Ontarion Events Alberta equation: Deflection' = 5 .571 -1 .752D2 + .933D2BE Ontario equation : Deflection' = 3 .454 - .620D2 + .397D2BE + .339D2BP Recalling, again, that the reference category in each equation represents in-group interaction, the negative coefficient for D2 in both equations reveals that deflection decreases as one moves from in-group to out-group interaction involving Albertan > Ontarion events . The size of this effect in the Alberta equation (-1 .752 ; p = .000) is about three times larger than in the Ontario equation (- .620 ; p < .001) . However, the main effect of D2 events in both equations is moderated by the nature of the act-behavior evaluation (BE) in both equations and, additionally, behavior potency (BP) in the Ontario equation . The large positive effect of D2BE in the Alberta ( .933 ; p = .000) and Ontario ( .397 ; p < .001) equations counteracts the reduction in deflection attributed to the main effect of D2 events in each equation (-1 .752 and - .620, respectively) . This suggests that the nicer the actions of an Albertan, the greater the deflection produced by Alberta > Ontario events for both Alberta and Ontario samples . The main effect of D2 (Albertan > Ontarion) events in the Ontario equation is also moderated by its interaction with the potency of an Albertan's actions (BP) . The positive coefficient for D2BP ( .339 ; p = .017) indicates that increasingly powerful actions by an Albertan toward an Ontarion washes out the deflection-reducing main effect of D2 events (- .620 ; p = 000) . Discussion As reported above in Table 4, the general equation for predicting the global affective outcomes of intergroup relations between Albertans and Ontarions explains a substantial and significant amount of variance in the dependent variable . The large and significant main effects for behavioral terms in this equation reveal that the amount of deflection produced by intergroup events depends on the nature of the act-what interactants actually do to one another, regardless of the
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
67
type of event . However, the interactions between behavior and event-type in the general equation indicate that the effect of behavior on deflection is influenced by who implements the behavior and who is the recipient . The main effects of event-type in the general equation represent the impact of intergroup relations (relative to within-group relations) on the deflection produced by events . In the remainder of this section, we discuss the mechanisms through which event-type influences the affective outcomes of intergroup relations . We conclude our discussion by addressing several seemingly anomalous findings from this study . As defined above, affective deflection is based on the discrepancy between the cultural sentiments for identities and the transient impressions or feelings created by events . The impression formation equations generating transient impressions in affect control theory are asymmetrical . As a consequence, the transient impressions for the actor in ABO events are different from those for the recipient . Because the transient impressions of an Ontarion created by D 1 (Ontarion > Albertan) events are quite different from those produced by D2 (Albertan > Ontarion) events, for instance, the amount of affective deflection produced by those two kinds of events will also be different . This explains the differences between equations for predicting D1 (Ontarion > Albertan) and D2 (Albertan > Ontarion) events within each sample . Differences in equations across samples for predicting the same type of event-D 1 (Ontarion > Albertan) events, for instance-can be attributed to differences between samples in cultural sentiments for the regional identities, Albertan and Ontarion . Recalling our discussion of Table 1, Ontario respondents evaluate an Ontarion higher than an Albertan ; and, depending on their gender, Alberta respondents evaluate an Albertan as three to five times nicer than an Ontarion . The cultural sentiments of Ontario and Alberta samples for regional identities also differ on the potency and activity dimensions of affective meaning . For example, Alberta respondents rate an Ontarion as more powerful than an Albertan . These differences in cultural sentiments across samples result in sample-specific equations for predicting the affective response to the same kind of event . Our analysis of the affective outcomes of intergroup relations has revealed several apparently anomalous findings-for instance, that out-group interaction between Albertans and Ontarions creates less deflection than in-group interaction . This is reflected in the negative effects of D1 (Ontarion > Albertan) and D2 (Albertan > Ontarion) events in both the Alberta and Ontario equations compared to the reference categories in these equations (Albertan > Albertan and Ontarion > Ontarion events, respectively) . This counterintuitive finding results from the fact that we have "forced" a full range of intergroup behaviors in the events analyzed in this study, including extremely bad and powerful actions (see Figure 1) . Because such actions are even more uncharacteristic of social relations within than between groups, deflection declines as we move from in-group to out-group interaction .
68
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W. BOWLBY
Another finding that seems anomalous at first blush concerns the increase in deflection resulting from the interaction between event-type and behavior evaluation-the 131 BE term in the Alberta equation for D1 events and the D2BE term in both Alberta and Ontario equations for D2 events . The DIBE term suggests that deflection increases in Ontario > Alberta events with the goodness of an Ontarion's actions ; and the D2BE term, that deflection increases in Albertan > Ontarion events with the goodness of an Albertan's actions . This remains a strange finding only if one fails to consider that deflection is a squared quantity, hence not resulting exclusively from negatively evaluated actions . While an examination of our data matrix reveals that bad actions create much greater deflection than good ones, positively evaluated actions that exceed those expected by virtue of the fundamental evaluation of an Albertan or Ontarion also produce considerable deflection . This kind of deflection, however, enhances the status of interactants . That is, while extremely nice interpersonal actions between an Albertan and an Ontarion create deflection because they are culturally unexpected, their consequence is to increase rather than diminish the status of each participant . The positive effects of DIBE and D2BE in our equations simply reflect the status-enhancing deflection produced by such events .
GENERAL DISCUSSION This paper has reported three studies to illustrate the application of affect control theory to stereotyping and intergroup relations . The first explored the in-group bias/ethnocentrism hypothesis and the out-group homogeneity hypothesis from social cognition research on stereotyping, employing data on intergroup attitudes (cultural sentiments) rather than intergroup perceptions (ascribed traits) . The second study applied the attribution equations of affect control theory to generate stereotypic traits from the cultural sentiments for regional identities . The third applied the theory's impression formation equations to explore the affective outcomes of intergroup relations . Findings from these three studies have been discussed extensively above . Here we address the more general issues raised by this kind of research . The first issue concerns the external validity or generalizability of our findings . For instance, we did not directly measure the affective reactions of Ontario and Alberta respondents to the events analyzed in Study 3 . Instead, we constructed a measure (affective deflection) based on the discrepancy between the transient feelings produced by events and the culturally established sentiments for the regional identities and actions involved in them . While the cultural sentiments of Alberta and Ontario respondents were directly measured in our research, transient feelings were generated from the impression formation equations of affect control theory estimated from previous Canadian research . This calls into question the external validity of our findings-whether we can generalize from estimates of
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
69
affective deflection based on equations established in previous research to the affective reactions that might actually be experienced by Alberta and Ontario respondents . However, the impression formation equations of affect control theory have been estimated empirically from large-scale, carefully designed research on the affective reaction of people to hundreds of interpersonal events . Moreover, predictions from affect control models based on these empirical equations have been supported by experimental research (Wiggins and Heise 1988 ; Robinson and Smith-Lovin 1992 ; Robinson, Smith-Lovin, and Tsoudis 1994), survey research (Heise and MacKinnon 1988 ; Heise and Calhan 1995), and qualitative research (Smith-Lovin and Douglas 1992 ; Francis 1997) . Therefore, despite the fact that we did not measure the affective reactions of Alberta and Ontario respondents directly, we feel confident in what the findings from Study 3 reveal about the affective outcomes of intergroup relations between Albertans and Ontarions . The same kind of question concerning external validity also applies to our findings from Study 2, which employed the attribution equations of affect control theory to generate the stereotypic traits of regional identities . However, these equations are simple derivations from the empirically based amalgamation equations of the theory, which describe how traits and other modifiers combine with social identities to create impressions of composite identities (Averett and Heise 1988) . Therefore, we also feel confident in what the findings from Study 2 suggest about the stereotypic traits of Canadian regional identities . There remains, however, a second and more mundane kind of external validity to consider, one that applies to all three studies reported in this paper-the extent to which we can generalize findings based upon non-probability, convenience samples of university students to the larger populations of Ontario and Alberta residents . In this case, the question of external validity pertains to the representativeness of our samples, rather than the validity and integrity of our research procedures . Here, we rest our case on the assumption that the kind of cultural data employed in our research-EPA measures of social identities-is uniform enough within cultures to be accessible from convenience samples of university students . From this perspective, sample respondents serve as "informants," providing information on the intergroup attitudes of Alberta and Ontario cultures . This raises the related question as to whether samples of about 30 males and 30 females from each culture are sufficiently large to provide reliable information . Here, we rely on the mathematical model developed and tested by Romney, Weller, and Batchhelder (1986), which estimates that stable results for the aggregation of high concordance cultural data (which we presume ours to be) can be expected from samples of as few as a half dozen informants .
70
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
CONCLUSION In the introduction to this paper we identified three deficits of social cognition research on stereotyping that have hindered its developing an explanatory model of intergroup relations, articulating the causal connections among stereotypes, intergroup attitudes, and intergroup behavior . These deficits include a traditional neglect of affect, a components approach to intergroup attitudes that inspires predictive rather than explanatory models, and the lack of a control perspective incorporating cognitive and affective processes as aspects of a larger system . We also described how affect control theory provides a powerful explanatory model of intergroup relations by not sharing these limitations of social cognition research on stereotyping . At the same time, however, one must acknowledge the strengths of social cognition theory and research that complement the limitations of affect control theory . For instance, affect control theory does not measure stereotypic traits of social groups directly ; instead, the theory generates them from attitudinal data on group identities (Study 2) . Therefore, it is important to validate predictions from affect control theory with direct research on the stereotypic traits actually attributed to social groups . This remains the forte of social cognition research, which has developed sophisticated measures and procedures to study the content, ascription, and accuracy of intergroup perceptions (e .g ., Esses et al . 1993 ; Judd and Park 1995 ; Ryan 1996 ; Stangor et al . 1991) . Moreover, social cognition researchers have expanded the cognitive content of stereotypes to include, not only ascribed traits, but also symbolic beliefs (those pertaining to whether groups uphold or violate cherished values and norms), and have demonstrated the importance of such beliefs in predicting intergroup attitudes (Esses et al . 1993) . In contrast, there is no direct equivalent to the construct of symbolic beliefs in affect control theory . Finally, while the attitudinal data of affect control theory enables one to explore such intergroup phenomena as ethnocentrism and homogeneity effects (Study 1), social cognition research on intergroup perceptions enriches our understanding of these phenomena . In short, social cognition theory's focus on cognition and cognitive processes and affect control theory's focus on affect and affective processes complement one another in the study of intergroup relations . We have located this paper in the context of social cognition theory because the bulk of research on stereotyping and intergroup relations in social psychology has been conducted within this general paradigm . In order to balance our comparison of affect control and social cognition approaches to this area of research, we conclude this paper with a brief discussion of social identity theory (see above references), a more or less separate development within social cognition theory itself . Like affect control theory, social identity theory advances an explanatory model that is lacking in general social cognition research on stereotyping and intergroup relations .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
71
Social identity theory proposes that broad social categories or attributes (gender, ethnic origin, and so on) describing groups to which one belongs, or to which one feels one belongs, are represented in one's mind as social identities . Thus conceived, social identities become important components of self-concept, motivating group comparisons and behavior that favor the in-group and hence the self . As a consequence, in-group and out-group perception become stereotypic and intergroup behavior acquires competitive and discriminatory properties . Social identity theory emphasizes the generative nature of the "sociocognitive mechanisms" (self-categorization and the self-enhancement motive) underlying identity processes, and views the salience and content of social identities as dynamically responsive to situational context (Hogg et al . 1995) . A later extension of social identity theory, self-categorization theory (Turner 1985 ; Turner, Hogg, Oakes, Reicher, and Wetherell 1987) draws heavily from cognitive psychology to elaborate self-categorization and identity processes . Like social identity theory, affect control theory deals with identities based upon broad social categories or attributes . Affect control research has accumulated EPA data for many such identities, and the existence of comparable data for various cultures (American, Canadian, German, Japanese) enables one to analyze intergroup relations from a cross-cultural perspective . As discussed earlier in this paper, the theory also advances a social psychological model of identity processes . Like the model advanced by social identity theory, the affect control model is an inherently dynamic and generative one, according to which the affective meaning of identities shifts with the identities of others in an event, the actions implemented by each interactant, and the setting in which the event takes place . Finally, like social identity theory, affect control theory supposes the operation of a self-enhancement motive in identity processes, locating it in a social psychological theory of motivation based upon the principle of affect control and the incentive of identity-confirmation (MacKinnon 1994, pp . 50-59) . For both theories, the motivation to enhance self-esteem through the confirmation of valued social identities is the well-spring of stereotyping, ethnocentrism, and discrimination in intergroup relations . Despite these similarities, there are important conceptual differences between the two theories that stem from their origins in different traditions . While social identity theory developed from the cognitive tradition of individual psychology, affect control theory traces its roots to the social psychological tradition of Mead and symbolic interactionism . This difference in origin has important repercussions for how each theory views the micro-foundations of group processes and intergroup relations . For social identity/self-categorization theory, the depersonalization of self-the shift in identity from unique individual to group member resulting from the categorization of self in terms of group prototypes-is the fundamental process underlying group and intergroup aspects of behavior such as stereotyping and ethnocentrism . As a consequence, "social identity theory and self-categorization models . . . do not construct group processes from interpersonal
72
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
processes . The process of self-categorization depersonalizes perception, feelings, and actions in terms of the contextually relevant self-defining in-group prototypes" (Hogg et al . 1995, p . 262) . Establishing group processes on cognitive structures (group or otherwise), rather than interpersonal processes, brings social identity theory perilously close to "the jagged rocks of psychological reductionism" (p . 264) . In contrast, affect control theory constructs group processes and intergroup relations from interpersonal events, the units of analysis in symbolic interactionism thought and the ultimate empirical referents of social phenomena (Wallace 1983, p . 167) . Moreover, the theory does not associate group identification with the depersonalization of group members, but rather with the internalization of cultural sentiments for the groups with which individuals identify . Thus, by establishing group processes on interpersonal events and the internalization of culture, affect control theory avoids the psychological reductionism implicit in social identity theory, maintaining its integrity as a genuine social psychological theory . In conclusion, social identity theory, like social cognition theory in general, has focused almost exclusively on cognition and cognitive processes . Despite its emphasis on self-enhancement motivation, social identity theory has generally ignored the role of affect, affective processing, and emotions in identity processes (for one attempt to integrate social identity theory with appraisal and constructionist theories of emotion, see Smith 1993) . This deficit of social identity theory (and social cognition theory in general) creates an opening for affect control theory to make an important contribution to our understanding of group processes and intergroup relations .
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS The research reported in this paper has been supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (Grant #410-94-0087) . We wish to express our gratitude to John Goyder, David Heise, Herman Smith, and two anonymous reviewers for comments on earlier drafts of this paper .
REFERENCES Albrecht, S . L ., D . L . Thomas, and B . A. Chadwick. 1980 . Social Psychology . Englewood Cliffs, NJ : Prentice-Hall . Allen, B . P . 1996. "African American and European Americans' Mutual Attributions : Adjective Generation Technique (AGT) Stereotyping ." Journal of Applied Social Psychology 26 : 884-912. Averett, C., and D . R . Heise . 1988. "Modified Social Identities : Amalgamations, Attributions, and Emotions ." Pp. 103-132 in Analyzing Social Interaction: Advances in Affect Control Theory, edited by L . Smith-Lovin and D. R . Heise . New York : Gordon and Breach (reprint from a special Issue of the Journal of Mathematical Sociology 13) . Blalock, H . M . 1979 . Social Statistics (2nd ed .) . New York : McGraw-Hill .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
73
Cantor, N ., and W .Mischel . 1979 . "Prototypes in Person Perception ." In Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol . 12, edited by L. Berkowitz . New York: Academic Press . Collins, R . 1990 . "Stratification, Emotional Energy, and the Transient Emotions ." Pp . 27-57 in Research Agendas in the Sociology of Emotions, edited by T . D . Kemper. Albany, NY : State University of New York Press . DeLamater, J . D . 1992 . "Attitudes ." Pp . 117-124 in Encyclopedia of Sociology, edited by E . Borgatta. New York: MacMillan . Edwards, A . L. 1957 . Techniques of Attitude Scale Construction . New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts . Esses, V. M ., G . Haddock, and M . P . Zanna. 1993 . "Values, Stereotypes, and Emotions as Determinants of Intergroup Attitudes ." Pp . 137-166 in Affect, Cognition, and Stereotyping : Interactive Processes in Group Perception, edited by D . M . Mackie and D . L. Hamilton. San Diego : Academic Press . Fishbein, M . 1978 . "Attitudes and Behavioral Prediction : An Overview ." Pp. 377-389 in Major Social Issues : A Multidisciplinary View, edited by J .M . Yinger and S .J . Cutler . New York : Free Press . Fishbein, M., and I . Ajzen . 1975 . Belief Attitude, Intention, and Behavior : an Introduction to Theory and Research . Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley . Ford, T. E ., and G . R. Tonander . 1998 . "The Role of Differentiation Between Groups and Social Identity in Stereotype Formation." Social Psychology Quarterly 61 : 372-384. Francis, L . E . 1997 . "Ideology and Interpersonal Emotion Management : Redefining Identity in Two Support Groups ." Social Psychology Quarterly 60 : 153-171 . Goffman, E. 1967. Interaction Ritual : Essays on Face-to-Face Behavior. Chicago : Aldine . Hamilton, D. L., and D . M . Mackie . 1993a. "Cognitive and Affective Processes in Intergroup Perception : The Developing Interface ." Pp . 1-11 in Affect, Cognition, and Stereotyping : Interactive Processes in Group Perception, edited by D . M . Mackie and D . L. Hamilton. San Diego : Academic Press . Hamilton, D . L ., and D . M . Mackie. 1993b . "Affect, Cognition, and Stereotyping : Concluding Comments ." Pp. 371-383 in Affect, Cognition, and Stereotyping : Interactive Processes in Group Perception, edited by D . M. Mackie and D . L . Hamilton . San Diego : Academic Press. Hamilton, D. L., S . J . Sherman, and C . M . Ruvolo. 1990. "Stereotype-Based Expectancies : Effects on Information Processing and Social Behavior ." Journal of Social Issues 46 : 35-60 . Heise, D. R. 1978 . Computer-Assisted Analysis of Social Action : Use of Program INTERACT and Survey UNC75 . Chapel Hill, NC : Institute for Research in Social Science . University of North Carolina. Heise, D . R . 1979 . Understanding Events : Affect and the Construction of Social Action . New York : Cambridge University Press . Heise, D. R . 1988 . "Affect Control Theory : Concepts and Model ." Pp . 1-33 in Analyzing Social Interaction : Advances in Affect Control Theory, edited by L . Smith-Lovin and D . R . Heise . New York : Gordon and Breach (reprint of a special issue of the Journal of Mathematical Sociology 13) . Heise, D . R ., and C . Calhan . "Emotion Norms in Interpersonal Events." Social Psychology Quarterly 58 : 223-240 . Heise, D. R ., and N . J . MacKinnon . 1988. "Affective Bases of Likelihood Judgments ." Pp. 133-151 in Analyzing Social Interaction : Advances in Affect Control Theory, edited by L . Smith-Lovin and D. R. Heise . New York: Gordon and Breach (reprint of a special issue of the Journal of Mathematical Sociology 13) . Hill, R. J . 1981 . "Attitudes and Behavior ." Pp . 347-377 in Social Psychology : Sociological Perspectives, edited by M . Rosenberg and R . H. Turner. New York : Basic Books . Hogg, M . A. 1992. The Social Psychology of Group Cohesiveness : From Atraction to Social Identity . London : Harvester/Wheatsheaf .
74
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
Hogg, M . A . 1993 . "Group Cohesiveness : A Critical Review and Some New Directions ." European Review of Social Psychology 4 : 85-111 . Hogg, M . A ., and D . Abrams . 1988 . Social Identifications : A Social Psychology of Intergroup Relations and Group Processes . London: Routledge. Hogg, M . A ., D. J. Terry, and K . M . White. 1995 . "A Tale of Two Theories : A Critical Comparison of Identity Theory With Social Identity Theory ." Social Psychology Quarterly 58 : 255-269 . Howard, J . A. 1995 . "Social Cognition ." Pp . 90-117 in Sociological Perspectives on Social Psychology, edited by K . S . Cook, G. A . Fine, and J. S . House . Boston : Allyn and Bacon. Jones, E . and D . McGillis . 1976 . "Correspondent Inferences and the Attribution Cube : A Comparative Reappraisal." Pp. 389-420 in New Directions in Attribution Research, Vol . 1, edited by J . Harvey, W . Ickes, and R . Kidd . Hillsdale, NJ : Lawrence Erlbaum Associates . Judd, C. M ., and B . Park. 1995 . "Stereotypes and Ethnocentrism : Diverging Interethnic Perceptions of African American and White American Youth ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 69 :460-481 . Katz, D., and K . Braly. 1933 . "Racial Stereotypes of One Hundred College Students ." Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 28 : 280-290 . Katz, D ., and K. Braly . 1935 . "Racial Prejudice and Racial Stereotypes ." Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 30 : 175-193 . Kemper, T . D ., and R . Collins . 1990 . "Dimensions of Microinteraction ." American Journal of Sociology 96: 32-68 . Kuhn, T . 1962 . The Structure of Scientific Revolutions . Chicago : University of Chicago Press . Lee, Y-T., and V . Ottati . 1995 . "Perceived In-group Homogeneity as a Function of Group Membership Salience and Stereotype Threat ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 21 : 610-619. Lippman, W . 1922 . Public Opinion. New York : Harcourt Brace Jovanovich . Messick, D . M., and D. M . Mackie . 1989 . "Intergroup Relations ." Annual Review of Psychology 40 : 45-81 . MacKinnon, N . J . 1985 . Affective Dynamics and Role Analysis . Final Report, Social Sciences and Humanities Research council of Canada Project 410-81-0089 . Guelph, Ontario : Department of Sociology and Anthropology, University of Guelph . MacKinnon, N . J . 1994. Symbolic Interactionism as Affect Control. Albany, NY : State University of New York Press . MacKinnon, N . J ., and D . R. Heise. 1993 . "Affect Control Theory : Delineation and History ." Pp. 64-103 in Theoretical Research Programs : Studies in the Growth of Theory, edited by J. Berger and M. Zelditch, Jr . Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . MacKinnon, N . J., and T. Langford. 1994 . "The Meaning of Occupational Prestige Scores : A Social Psychological Analysis and Interpretation ." The Sociological Quarterly 35 : 215-245 . Mandler, G . 1984 . Mind and Body : Psychology of Emotion and Stress . New York: Norton . McCall, G. J., and J. L. Simmons. 1978 . Identities and Interactions (2d ed.) . New York : Free Press . Mead, G . H . 1934 . Mind, Self and Society, edited by C. W. Morris . Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Moore, D . S ., and G . P. McCabe. 1993 . Introduction to the Practice of Statistics (2nd ed.) . New York: Freeman . Osgood, C . E. 1969 . "On the Whys and Wherefores of E, P, and A ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 12 : 194-199 . Osgood, C . E., W . H . May, and M . S . Miron . 1975 . Cross-Cultural Universals of Affective Meaning . Urbana, IL : University of Illinois Press . Osgood, C . E ., G. C. Suci, and P. H . Tannenbaum . 1957. The Measurement of Meaning . Urbana : University of Illinois Press . Pearson, E . S ., and N. W. Please . 1975 . "Relation Between the Shape of Population Distribution and the Robustness of Four Simple Test Statistics ." Biometrika 62 : 223-241 .
Stereotyping and Intergroup Relations
75
Pedhazur, E . J. 1997 . Multiple Regression in Behavioral Research (3rd ed .). Fort Worth, TX : Harcourt-Brace . Robinson, D . T., and L . Smith-Lovin . 1992 . "Selective Interaction and Identity ." Social Psychology Quarterly 55 : 13-28 . Robinson, D. T ., L. Smith-Lovin, and O. Tsoudis. 1994 . "Heinous Crime or Unfortunate Accident? The Effects of Remorse on Responses to Mock Criminal Confessions ." Social Forces 73 : 175-190. Romney, A. K., S . C . Weller, and W . H . Batchelder . 1986 . "Culture as Consensus : A Theory of Culture and Informant Accuracy ." American Anthropologist 88 : 313-338 . Rosenberg, M . J., and C . I . Hovland . 1960 . "Cognitive, Affective, and Behavioral Components of Attitudes." Pp . 1-14 in Attitude Organization and Change, edited by C . I . Hovland and M. J. Rosenberg . New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Ryan, C . S . 1996. "Accuracy of Black and White College Students' In-Group and Out-Group Stereotypes ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 22 : 1114-1127 . Schneider, D ., A . Hastort, and P . Ellsworth. 1979 . Person Perception. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Schuman, H . 1995 . "Attitudes, Beliefs, and Behavior ." Pp . 68-89 in Sociological Perspectives on Social Psychology, edited by K. S . Cook, G. A . Fine, and J . S . House . Boston : Allyn and Bacon . Seeman, M . 1981 . "Intergroup Relations." Pp . 378-410 in Social Psychology: Sociological Perspectives, edited by M. Rosenberg and R . H . Turner . New York : Basic Books . Smith, E . R . 1993 . "Social Identity and Social Emotions : Toward New Conceptualizations of Prejudice ." Pp . 297-315 in Affect, Cognition, and Stereotyping : Interactive Precesses in Group Perception, edited by D . M . Mackie and D . L . Hamilton . San Diego : Academic Press . Smith-Lovin, L . 1988 . "Impressions from Events ." Pp . 35-70 in Analyzing Social Interaction : Advances in Affect Control Theory, edited by L . Smith-Lovin and D . R. Heise. New York : Gordon and Breach (reprint of a special issue of the Journal of Mathematical Sociology 13) . Smith-Lovin, L. 1990 . "Emotion as the Confirmation and Disconfirmation of Identity : An Affect Control Model ." Pp . 238-270 in Research Agendas in the Sociology of Emotions, edited by T . D . Kemper . Albany : State University of New York Press . Smith-Lovin, L ., and W. Douglas . 1992 . "An Affect Control Analysis of Two Religious Subcultures ." Pp. 217-248 in Social Perspectives on Emotion, Vol . 1, edited by V . Gecas and D . Franks . Greenwich, CT : JAI Press . Smith-Lovin, L ., and D . R . Heise, eds . 1988 . Analyzing Social Interaction : Advances in Affect Control Theory . New York: Gordon and Breach (reprint of a special issue of the Journal of Mathematical Sociology 13). Stangor, C ., L . A . Sullivan, and T. E . Ford . 1991 . "Affective and Cognitive Determinants of Prejudice." Social Cognition 9: 359-380 . Stryker, S . 1968 . "Identity Salience and Role Performance : The Relevance of Symbolic Interaction Theory for Family Research ." Journal of Marriage and the Family 30 : 558-564 . Stryker, S . 1980. Symbolic Interaction : A Social Structural Version . Menlo Park, CA : Benjamin/Cummings . Stryker, S ., and R . T . Serpe . 1994 . "Identity Salience and Psychological Centrality : Equivalence, Overlapping, or Complementary Concepts?" Social Psychology Quarterly 57 : 16-35 . Tafjel, H . 1969 . "Cognitive Aspects of Prejudice ." Journal of Social Issues 25 : 79-98 . Tafjel, H . 1970 . "Experiments in Intergroup Discrimination." Scientific American 223 : 96-102 . Tafjel, H . 1974 . "Social Identity and Intergroup Behaviour ." Social Science Information 13 : 65-93 . Tafjel, H ., ed. 1978 . Differentiation Between Social Groups . London : Academic Press . Tafjel, H ., ed . 1982 . Social Identity and Intergroup Relations . Cambridge, UK : Cambridge University Press .
76
NEIL J . MacKINNON and JEFFREY W . BOWLBY
Tafjel, H ., and J. C . Turner. 1979 . "An Integrative Theory of Intergroup Conflict ." Pp . 33-47 in The Social Psychology of Intergroup Relations, edited by W . G . Austin and S . Worchel . Monterey, CA : Brooks-Cole . Thurstone, L .L . 1928 . "Attitudes Can Be Measured ." American Journal of Sociology 33 : 529-554 . Thurstone, L .L . 1967 . "The Measurement of Social Attitudes ." Pp . 14-25 in Readings in Attitude Theory and Measurement, edited by M . Fishbein . New York: Wiley . Turner, J . C . 1982 . "Towards a Cognitive Redefinition of the Social Group ." Pp . 15-40 in Social Identity and Intergroup Relations, edited by H. Tafjel . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Turner, J. C . 1985. "Social Categorization and the Self Concept : A Social Cognitive Theory of Group Behavior." Pp. 77-122 in Advances in Group Processes : Theory and Research, Vol 2, edited by E . J. Lawler. Greenwich, CT : JAI . Turner, J . C., M. A . Hogg, P . J . Oakes, S . D . Reicher, and M . S . Wetherell . 1987. Rediscovering the Social Group: A Self-Categorization Theory . Oxford : Blackwell . Wallace, W. 1983. Principles of Scientific Sociology . New York: Aldine . Wiggins, B ., and D . R . Heise. 1988 . "Expectations, Intentions, and Behavior: Some Tests of Affect Control Theory." Pp . 153-169 in Analyzing Social Interaction: Advances in Affect Control Theory, edited by L . Smith-Lovin and D . R . Heise . New York : Gordon and Breach (reprint of a special issue of the Journal of Mathematical Sociology 13) . Zanna, M . P., and J . K. Rempel. 1988 . "Attitudes : A New Look at an Old Concept ." Pp . 315-334 in The Social Psychology of Knowledge, edited by D . Bar-Tal and A. W. Kruglanski . Cambridge : Cambridge University Press .
THE FORMATION OF STATUS BELIEFS IMPROVING STATUS CONSTRUCTION THEORY
Cecilia L. Ridgeway
ABSTRACT Widely shared status beliefs that characterize people in one social category as more esteemed and competent than people in another category play an important role in the organization of inequality . Status construction theory argues that the terms on which people interact across a social difference boundary can cause shared status beliefs to form and spread widely throughout a population . This chapter reviews the evidence for status construction theory and develops it further by offering an explicit theoretical account of the mechanism by which interactional contexts induce participants to form status beliefs even when those beliefs disadvantage the participant. I derive testable hypotheses from this account . I show as well how this account can be represented in the graph-theoretic terms of expectation states theory, allowing further testable predictions to be derived.
Social status is a fundamental dimension of social inequality in human societies along with social power and material wealth (Weber 1968) . Status involves relations based on social evaluations of prestige, honor, or esteem . Given its recog-
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 77-102 . Copyright © 2000 by JAI Press Inc . All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 77
78
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
nized importance in the organization of inequality, it is odd that contemporary sociologists approach social status in a disjointed manner . Macro sociologists conceptualize status as a relationship between social groups and often study it in terms of the relative prestige of occupational groups . Micro sociologists, on the other hand, approach status as a social hierarchy of influence and esteem within a group, often called a power and prestige order . These disparate approaches to status can be brought into dialogue with one another by a focus on the linking concept of status beliefs. Status beliefs are widely shared cultural beliefs that people in one social category are more esteemed and competent than people in another social category . Status beliefs can be perceptions of what "most others" believe or what actors themselves believe . As their definition suggests, status beliefs are beliefs about the evaluative relationship between social categories or groups . Yet, as decades of research with expectations states theory has shown, they are also the primary determinant of the social influence hierarchies actors form when they interact in regard to a shared goal (Berger et al . 1977 ; Webster and Foschi 1988 ; Berger and Zelditch 1998) . A broader investigation of status beliefs-how they form and change as well as what their effects are-is the key to integrating sociological approaches to status and developing a deeper understanding of the role of status dynamics in systems of social stratification and inequality . Status construction theory is a recent approach that describes one set of processes by which status beliefs about social differences might develop and become widely shared among a population (Ridgeway 1991, 1997 ; Ridgeway and Balkwell 1997 ; Ridgeway, Boyle, Kuipers, and Robinson 1998 ; Webster and Hysom 1998) . The theory claims that interactional contexts are not only an arena in which status beliefs are at play ; they are also important contexts for the development and spread of status beliefs . This chapter attempts to increase our understanding of the nature and development of status beliefs in society by elaborating and improving status construction theory's account of the formation of status beliefs in interaction .
FRAMING THE PROBLEM Status construction theory argues that when people on opposite sides of a recognized social difference boundary regularly interact in regard to shared goals, the terms on which they interact and the influence hierarchies that emerge can induce the participants to form shared status beliefs about their difference . People carry these beliefs to other encounters with different others and, by acting on them there, induce some of these others to take on the beliefs as well . This creates a diffusion process that, under some circumstances, will create roughly consensual (i .e ., widely shared) beliefs that people from one of the difference categories are more esteemed and competent than are those from the other difference category .
The Formation of Status Beliefs
79
When a status belief is roughly consensual in a society, it has become part of the society's shared culture and is part of the taken-for-granted social framework of beliefs that actors bring to interaction and use to organize their behavior together . Investigations of status construction theory suggest that interactional contexts where people from different social categories come together may indeed be a potent source of status beliefs . Experiments confirm that when influence hierarchies repeatedly develop between actors with a salient social difference, the actors form corresponding status beliefs about their difference, as status construction theory predicts (Ridgeway et al . 1998 ; Ridgeway and Glasgow 1996) . Other experiments show that actors can indeed spread status beliefs to others by treating those others according to the belief (Ridgeway and Glasgow 1996 ; Ridgeway and Erickson 1998) . Finally, computer simulations support the logical sturdiness of theory's argument that, if interactional processes create and spread status beliefs, the diffusion process will cause these beliefs to become roughly consensual in society under many circumstances (Ridgeway and Balkwell 1997 ; Mark, Smith-Lovin, and Ridgeway 1999) . How can we explain the power of interaction to create status beliefs? It is well known that the creation of any salient difference between people is enough to cause people to favor their own group over the other (Brewer and Kramer 1985 ; Dovidio and Gaertner 1993 ; Messick and Mackie 1989) . With status beliefs, however, all groups agree, or at least concede, that one group is socially recognized as better and more competent than the others are . Thus it is the beliefs of those who are disadvantaged by status beliefs that distinguish status beliefs from the in-group bias created by difference alone . What is it about an interactional context that could induce an actor to form a status belief that disadvantages that actor? Status construction theory offers an account of belief formation in interaction that can be summarized as follows (Ridgeway 1991) . When people who differ in standing in the power and prestige order of an encounter also differ in an easily recognized, distinguishing attribute, there is a likelihood that they will associate their perceived differences in competence and status in the setting with the distinguishing attribute and form a status belief about that attribute . This assumes that the actors do not already have shared status beliefs about the attribute . Note that this account of belief formation is essentially descriptive . It does not explain the processes through which an association between a nominal difference and standing in a power and prestige order induces people to generalize to status beliefs about whole categories of actors, even when these beliefs are against their personal interests . As an initial account of belief formation through interaction, this descriptive formulation has worked well . It has stimulated empirical investigations of the formation of status beliefs in interaction and led to the further development of status construction theory . Given what has been learned, however, it is now clear that this initial descriptive account of belief formation has limitations that need to be addressed . First, it does not explain exactly how an association between standing
80
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
in a power and prestige order and a distinguishing attribute leads to status beliefs among participants . The informal, general terms in which the process is described in the theory are open to diverse interpretations . Second, the formulation fails particularly to make clear why the associational process it describes would be sufficient to induce actors to take on status beliefs that disadvantage them . Finally, status construction theory uses expectation states theory to formulate key parts of its argument about the development of power and prestige orders in interactional contexts . Yet the core of status construction theory, its description of the formation of status beliefs, is not expressed in terms that are easily related to expectation states theory . Expectation states theory is the best-developed and empirically documented theory of status dynamics at the interactional level . The ability of status construction theory to improve our understanding of status beliefs and their role in linking micro and macro status processes will be greater if the theory is formulated in terms that can be articulated with the dominant micro-level account. The overall goal of this chapter is to improve our understanding of the emergence of status beliefs in society by developing status construction theory's account of belief formation . I will examine in detail the relationship between the local realities created by power and prestige orders in interactional contexts and the nature of status beliefs . Based on this examination, I will suggest a formal belief formation assumption for status construction theory that offers an explicit theoretical account of the mechanism by which interaction induces actors to form status beliefs. The goal is to theorize this mechanism in a manner that accounts for the acceptance of status beliefs by those they disadvantage as well as advantage . A specification of the mechanism by which interaction creates status belief must also take into account recent theoretical and empirical developments in status construction theory . I will then show how the belief formation assumption can be explicitly articulated with expectation states theory . I begin by reviewing recent developments in status construction theory and the issues they raise for understanding how interaction creates status beliefs . Then I turn to the task of formulating an improved and formally explicit theoretical account for this process .
DEVELOPMENTS IN STATUS CONSTRUCTION THEORY Creating Status Beliefs From Resource Differences In its initial formulation, status construction theory focused on the way a correlation between the distribution in exchangeable resources and a nominal (i .e ., unordered) distinction (say, As and Bs) among people in a society could be transformed by interactional processes into widely held beliefs that members of the resource-advantaged category are more esteemed and competent than members of the resource-disadvantaged category (Ridgeway 1991) . Given this focus, the the-
The Formation of Status Beliefs
81
ory highlighted encounters between people who differed in both resources and the AB distinction (called "doubly dissimilar" encounters) as the central contexts that drive the formation of status beliefs about the distinction . Resource advantages tend to create expectations for competence in the situation, as expectation states research has shown (Cook 1975 ; Harrod 1980 : Stewart and Moore 1992) . These expectations shape behavior in ways that result in a power and prestige order favoring the better paid . In doubly dissimilar encounters, actors may associate their standing in the power and prestige order, created by their resource differences, with their corresponding AB differences and form status beliefs about that distinction . Due to the correlation in society between resources and the A/B distinction, more doubly dissimilar encounters will foster status beliefs favoring the resource-advantaged category (say, As) than the resource-disadvantaged category (Bs) . As actors spread their beliefs formed in doubly dissimilar encounters to other encounters with people who differ on the AB distinction, the numerical predominance of status beliefs favoring As should gradually overwhelm those favoring Bs, resulting in widely held status beliefs favoring As . An experimental test of this formulation has shown that doubly dissimilar encounters do indeed induce their participants to form status beliefs favoring the resource-advantaged nominal category . After two encounters with partners who differed from them in a nominal distinction, were paid differently, and attained influence in the encounters corresponding to their pay level, subjects developed beliefs that "most people" consider the typical person in the resource-advantaged category to be more respected, competent, and leaderlike, but not as cooperative and considerate as the typical member of the disadvantaged category (Ridgeway et al . 1998) . ! Significantly, even subjects in the disadvantaged category formed beliefs that those in the other group are considered higher status and more competent than people in their own group . Two subsequent experiments, which I will describe shortly, further demonstrated that actors could transmit status beliefs to others by acting on those beliefs in interaction (Ridgeway and Glasgow 1996 ; Ridgeway and Erickson 1998) . Thus, status beliefs created in doubly dissimilar encounters can be spread more broadly through interaction . In addition to this experimental evidence, simulations of the proposed diffusion process provide logical support for the theory's prediction that status beliefs favoring the resource-advantaged category will become roughly consensual among the population (Ridgeway and Balkwell 1997) . Therefore, the evidence thus far supports (although does not fully prove) the initial predictions derived from status construction theory's assumptions about status belief formation and transmission in interaction . These predictions can be summarized as follows . Given a correlation between the distribution of resources and a nominal distinction in a society, interactional processes will be sufficient to create widely shared status beliefs about that distinction . Those beliefs will favor the resource-advantaged nominal category .
82
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
A More General Condition for the Development of Status Beliefs
Despite status construction theory's initial focus on resource differences, however, its model of belief formation actually implies a more general set of circumstances by which status beliefs could develop . If status beliefs are fostered by a systematic association between standing in power and prestige orders and a nominal distinction, then any factor that systematically biases the development of influence hierarchies in encounters between nominally different actors will create status beliefs favoring the nominal category advantaged by that factor . This second derivation is status construction theory's most general implication (Ridgeway and Glasgow 1996 ; Webster and Hysom 1998) . Webster and Hysom employ this derivation to expand status construction theory to show how distinguishing characteristics, like sexual orientation, that are not immediately visible but that carry a moral evaluation in society can become status-valued characteristics . Webster and Hysom (1998) propose as well that not only resources with exchange value, but also those with status value (e.g ., a larger office) could act as the biasing factors that create status beliefs . Differential access to valued information between As and Bs, or control over technology are other examples of biasing factors that could potentially create status beliefs about an A/B distinction . For this second, more general derivation to hold, people must form status beliefs from the simple association in encounters of standing in the power and prestige order and a nominal distinction without obvious accompanying differences in resources or other factors . In other words, the experience of interactional hierarchy itself associated with a nominal distinction must be sufficient to create status beliefs if interactional processes are to act as a general translator of biasing factors into status beliefs . In an experiment that tests this hypothesis, Ridgeway and Glasgow (1996) had confederates treat a nominally distinct subject in a deferential or assertive, nondeferential manner during a cooperative decision-making task . As expectations states theory predicts, this created patterns of behavioral exchange between the subject and confederate that resulted in the deferential confederate becoming less influential than the subject and the assertive confederate becoming more influential than the subject . After two experiences with an influence hierarchy associated with a nominal distinction, subjects formed beliefs that "most people" consider the typical member of the influence-advantaged nominal category to be higher status and more competent, but less cooperative and considerate, than the average person in the influence-disadvantaged nominal category . Again, subjects who were influence disadvantaged themselves formed status beliefs that disadvantaged their own nominal category . Thus interactional hierarchies alone, without supporting resource differences, were sufficient to create status beliefs . This suggests that status construction theory's second and most general derivation is plausible .
The Formation of Status Beliefs
83
Implications for the Spread of Status Beliefs
Ridgeway and Glasgow's (1996) experiment also indicates that if actors who have formed a status belief in one encounter then treat others according to it in subsequent encounters, those others are likely to acquire the belief themselves as status construction theory assumes . The confederates in that experiment acted as though they thought the nominal distinction between them and the subjects carried status value . By so acting, they created a power and prestige order between them and the subjects in self-fulfilling manner and from that, the subjects inferred the status beliefs themselves . Thus this experiment shows that status beliefs can be spread through behavior in interaction, as status construction theory argues . A subsequent experiment suggests that interaction may spread status beliefs quite broadly . Ridgeway and Erickson (1998) had a third member of a group observe the status valued (i .e ., deferential or nondeferential) treatment of someone who was nominally the same as they were by someone else who was nominally different. These bystander participants also formed status-corresponding status beliefs about the nominal distinction . Thus, status beliefs can be spread through observation in interaction as well as personal treatment. As a result, interaction may be a powerful teacher of status beliefs, greatly speeding the diffusion process, as simulations suggest (Ridgeway and Balkwell 1997) . Creating Status Beliefs Through Chance Processes
If any factor that systematically biases the development of influence hierarchies between nominally distinct actors can foster status beliefs, could chance processes alone result in the development of status beliefs about the nominal distinction? In the initial statement of the theory, Ridgeway (1991) reasoned that, in encounters between nominally different actors where no biasing factor was present, the association between nominal category and power and prestige would be governed by chance . As a result, these encounters would produce equal numbers of status beliefs favoring one nominal category as favoring the other category . In the diffusion process, these contradicting beliefs would eventually wash each other out . This analysis, however, neglects the way chance processes can produce path dependent effects that act as biasing factors in favor of a given status belief. By chance alone, a series of coin flips can occasionally produce a string of "heads" or "tails ." Similarly, a series of initial encounters between As and Bs could by chance produce a substantial preponderance of status beliefs favoring one category (e .g ., As) rather than another . As actors spread these beliefs through future encounters, there is a chance that this initial preponderance will be magnified and gradually result in consensual status beliefs favoring the initially preponderant category . In effect, the chance string of early encounters creating beliefs favoring one category, not the other, acts as a type of biasing factor that leads to widely held status beliefs . In a formal analysis with supporting simulations, Mark
84
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
and colleagues show that an initial predominance of status beliefs favoring a particular nominal category, created by chance, would logically result in consensual status beliefs favoring that category under many circumstances (Mark 1999 ; Mark, Smith-Lovin, and Ridgeway 1999) . Mark and colleagues' analyses suggest that the belief formation processes described by status construction theory have an additional set of implications not initially anticipated by the theory . When actors regularly interact across a nominal difference boundary, there is a likelihood that they will form shared status beliefs about the nominal distinction through chance processes alone . When status beliefs are created by chance factors, however, the group that will be favored by the beliefs cannot be predicted in advance . This is in contrast to the situation where beliefs are created by a nonrandom biasing factor such as resources or technology. Thus, when status beliefs are created by chance processes, all categories of the nominal distinction are equally likely to become high status . Conclusions and Implications
For the purposes of this paper, what conclusions can we draw from these theoretical and empirical developments in status construction theory? First, the theory's initial focus on doubly dissimilar encounters as the crucial sites for the creation of status beliefs is too limited . All encounters between people who differ on a given nominal distinction are potentially sites for the creation of status beliefs . In cases where a systematic biasing factor is present, a subset of nominally different encounters will also be doubly dissimilar encounters and the latter will be important for determining the evaluative direction (i .e ., favoring As or Bs) of the status beliefs that develop. Second, a wide variety of factors other than resources can function as the biasing factor that creates status beliefs favoring a given category of a nominal distinction . These two points suggest that any specification of the mechanism by which interactional associations induce status beliefs must accommodate encounters where no biasing factors are salient in the situation as well as encounters where such factors are present . The specification must also allow the incorporation of a variety of biasing factors .
THE NATURE OF STATUS BELIEFS
To specify a mechanism by which interaction creates status beliefs we must first keep in mind the nature of status beliefs . In the terms of expectations states theory, status beliefs are the widely shared beliefs that render a recognized social distinction into a status characteristic . Status beliefs associate higher social evaluation and expectations for greater general and/or specific competence with one state of a characteristic (men, the better educated) than another (women, the lesser educated) (Berger et al . 1977) . At a minimum, then, interaction must associate both
The Formation of Status Beliefs
85
evaluative and competence differences with actor's nominal categories in order for actors to impute status beliefs about the nominal distinction . In this section I consider the means by which interactional contexts create an apparent correspondence between a nominal distinction and differences in both social evaluation and competence . In the next section I take up the further question of how a mere situational correspondence between competence and evaluation differences and a nominal distinction could induce people to form status beliefs that disadvantage them. It is clear how goal-oriented interaction juxtaposes presumed competence differences with the actors' nominal distinction . As expectations states research shows, actors in goal-oriented interaction form differentiated expectations for the usefulness or competence of the contributions from each actor compared to the others (Berger, Conner, and Fisek 1974 ; Fisek, Berger, and Norman 1991) . These differentiated performance expectations are the foundation of the power and prestige order (i .e ., influence hierarchy) that organizes interaction in the setting . In goal-oriented settings, then, interactional hierarchies embody presumptions about differences in competence in that setting . This expectation states theory argument is the basis for status construction theory's assumption that interaction can induce status beliefs (Ridgeway 1991) . In addition to embodying presumptions of competence, the behaviors by which actors actually enact relations of influence and esteem also act as signs or markers of each actor's evaluative standing, or status, in the setting . These observable power and prestige behaviors, as expectation states theory calls them, include opportunities to participate, participation rate, positive evaluations received, influence, and choice for leadership positions (see Webster and Hysom 1998, p . 354) . These behaviors cast the influential actor in the position of the primary performer, the center of evaluative attention in the setting, while less influential actors are cast in the position of reactors to the primary performer (Wagner and Berger 1997) . It is apparent, then, that the observable power and prestige behaviors by which interactional hierarchies are enacted have a dual aspect . They are driven by and represent actors' presumptions about their differences in competence in the situation . By the same token, they are also status markers that signify differences in the social evaluation of actors in the situation (Ridgeway and Berger 1986) . Not surprising, research indicates a reciprocal relationship between the display of observable power and prestige behaviors and presumptions of competence (Berger et al . 1974 ; Ridgeway, Berger, and Smith 1985 ; Fisek, Berger, and Norman 1991) . Because these interactional power and prestige behaviors are culturally associated with the enactment of competence differences, actors can display them to create the appearance of competence and gain influence in the first place (especially among social peers) . On the other hand, any other factors that affect the actors' appearance of competence, such as external status characteristics (e .g ., occupation, education, race, or gender), resource differences, or actual performance in
86
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
the setting will also determine the power and prestige behaviors that the actor can effectively display in the situation . The enactment of an interactional influence hierarchy, then, provides a display of both apparent competent differences and status markers indicating evaluative differences . Thus the association of position in an interaction hierarchy with a nominal distinction creates a juxtaposition between that distinction and competence and evaluative differences that could encourage the formation status beliefs . Observable power and prestige behaviors, however, are not the only means by which evaluative differences among actors might be displayed in an interactional (or other) setting . The social evaluation of actors can be indicated through a variety of other social signs and attributes as well . As Webster and Hysom (1998) note, evaluative standing can be indicated by the possession of valued goal objects (a nice house) or by differences in exchangeable resources such as pay differences in addition to behavioral gestures of deference and esteem . The diverse indicators of evaluative differences between actors, however, can all be understood as status markers (Ridgeway and Berger 1986) . A status marker is any possession, attribute, or behavior that is culturally associated with a position of high rather than low status in power and prestige orders . While there are a wide variety of status markers in any culture, the observable power and prestige behaviors by which actors actually enact relations of influence and esteem may function as core status markers . I base this suggestion on evidence that the enactment of a behavioral power and prestige order creates impressions of the actors that correspond closely to what research indicates is the core content of all status beliefs . Geis and colleagues (1984) and Gerber (1996) report that actors in the high status position of an observable power and prestige order are perceived as more instrumental and directive while those in the low status position are seen as more expressive and emotional . In strikingly parallel findings, Conway and colleagues (1996) show that the status distinctions associated with gender, occupation, and general evaluative standing in a society all involve similar impressions of those in high rather than low status groups . In each case, people in higher status groups are seen as more agentic and instrumentally competent while those in the lower status groups are perceived as more interpersonally responsive and communal . Recall that experiments testing status construction theory's arguments about belief formation in interaction also found that subjects developed beliefs that one nominal group was more leaderlike and competent but not as cooperative and considerate as the other nominal group (Ridgeway et al . 1998 ; Ridgeway and Glasgow 1996 ; Ridgeway and Erickson 1998) . Perhaps it is not surprising that the content of status beliefs so closely reflects the impressions actors create when they enact an interactional status order . Status beliefs are widely shared cultural schemas for organizing cooperative interaction across a social difference boundary, but on unequal terms (Ridgeway et al . 1998) . As shared schemas for organizing interaction, status beliefs typify interactional structures . The correspondence between status beliefs and the impression actors
The Formation of Status Beliefs
87
give in observable power and prestige structures underlines the importance of interactional processes for status beliefs . It adds credence to status construction theory's claim that interaction is not only an arena that is shaped by status beliefs, but one in which such beliefs can be created and changed . The above considerations suggest a more detailed and useful conceptualization of the process by which status beliefs are created in status construction theory . To begin with, it is useful to conceptualize the process as the establishment of a link between a nominal distinction and both differences in status markers and expected competence . The concept of status markers is broad enough to encompass the diverse interactional contexts that status construction theory argues can lead to status beliefs, including those involving resource differences and those with behavioral influence hierarchies alone . This conceptualization is also phrased in the terms of expectation states theory, facilitating its integration with that approach . This is the first step in specifying the mechanism by which interaction induces status beliefs . It is still not clear, however, why a correspondence between a nominal distinction and differential status markers and competence expectations should induce people to infer status beliefs that disadvantage them . Addressing this important problem is the crucial next step in the argument .
CONSENSUS, VALIDITY, AND THE ACCEPTANCE OF STATUS BELIEFS Ridgeway and colleagues (1998) argue that interactional power and prestige orders can create local realities where a nominal difference appears to the participants to be consensually evaluated before it actually is so on a broader scale . The local appearance of an evaluative consensus about a nominal distinction, I suggest, is the key to inducing those who would be disadvantaged by a status belief to take it on . The appearance of consensus also spurs actors to generalize beyond the current situation to a belief, like a status belief, that they expect to use to make sense of future interactions . When actors with one state of a nominal distinction have consistently higher status markers and expected competence in the situation than those with another state of the distinction, then there is a correspondence in the situation among states of the nominal distinction, status markers, and expected competence . When a power and prestige order enacts such a correspondence and this correspondence is not explicitly commented upon or resisted, the enacted correspondence appears to be socially accepted and consensual . The appearance of consensus makes the correspondence seem like an objective social reality in the situation that is accepted by others as a social fact. In effect, the appearance of consensus gives the correspondence among the nominal distinction, status markers, and competence expectations social validity in the eyes of participants (Ridgeway and Berger 1986 ; Weber 1968 ; Zelditch and
88
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
Floyd 1998 ; Zelditch and Walker 1984) . 2 Following Weber (1968, pp . 31-33), Zelditch and Floyd argue that something is valid in a situation if actors expect other actors to accept that thing in the situation. Thus the correspondence is socially valid in the situation when an actor, P, expects others to accept the correspondence in the situation . In a situation where such a correspondence is enacted without contest, then, participants enter into a local reality where it seems accepted as objectively valid that people in one nominal category are more competent and leaderlike than are people in another category . Given the apparently valid social truth that the situation presents to its participants, is it surprising that they take the next step and form a more general belief that As are typically more competent and status worthy than Bs? The social validity that the situation lends to the correspondence among the nominal distinction, status markers, and competence has two important effects that facilitate this belief formation process . First, since the correspondence appears to be a valid social fact, actors presume it would be accepted as a social fact by others beyond the situation as well . The sense that it would be accepted by others is an inducement to the actors to generalize the local correspondence into a belief about As and Bs that could be transferred to other actors and situations . In effect, the social validity of the correspondence in the local situation suggests that a status belief about As and Bs is an effective social schema for making sense of and acting toward others in future encounters because those others will also accept its social truth . Second, the sense that the correspondence would be accepted as a social fact by others as well confronts the actors who are disadvantaged by the correspondence with a hard reality . Whether the disadvantaged actors like it or not, others are likely to treat them as though the correspondence indicates a valid social truth about the actors' status worthiness and competence compared to those of the other nominal category . Confronted with this prospect, the disadvantaged actors have little choice but to accept the status belief themselves as an aspect of social reality with which they must contend . They may accept the disadvantaging status belief simply as an estimate of what "most others" believe . Or they may feel the pressure of social validity more deeply and accept the status belief as a matter of personal belief as well . Either way, however, the status belief will affect how they react to others in subsequent encounters . The creation of a sense of social validity about a link between a nominal distinction and status markers and competence, by this account, is the central mechanism by which interaction induces its participants to form status beliefs . The following belief formation assumption summarizes this argument . It provides a formal belief formation assumption for status construction theory that achieves two goals . It can account for the development of beliefs in situations where resource or other differences are present and where they are not . Furthermore, it specifies a mechanism by which interaction induces belief formation even among those the
The Formation of Status
Beliefs
89
beliefs disadvantage . This formal assumption replaces the informal principle of association between standing in a power and prestige order and belief formation stated earlier . Belief Formation Assumption :
Given a situation in which there is a socially valid correspondence between individuals' differing states of a nominal distinction and their differentiated status markers and expected competence, then there is a likelihood that actors in the situation will form corresponding status beliefs about the nominal distinction. Status beliefs are corresponding when the nominal state that is associated with more valued status markers and greater expected competence in the situation is also associated in the status belief with more positive social evaluation and greater competence compared to the other nominal state . To this formal assumption about belief formation, status construction theory adds an assumption from expectation states theory that actors transfer expectations about categories of actors formed in one setting to future encounters with actors that also differ in those categories (Markovsky, Smith, and Berger 1984 ; Pugh and Wahrman 1983) . Finally, status construction theory also assumes that subsequent encounters with others who differ on the attribute that confirm an actor's newly formed status belief strengthen that belief while inconsistent, disconfirming experiences undermine it . Together, these three assumptions constitute status construction theory's account of the formation and spread of status beliefs through interaction .
CHALLENGES TO CONSENSUS AND THE FORMATION OF STATUS BELIEFS In the above analysis the appearance of consensus creates social validity and social validity fosters the formation of status beliefs . Naturally, then, a question arises about the effect that a challenge to consensus in the situation would have on the likelihood that participants would form status beliefs . An examination of this question will clarify some implications of the belief formation assumption for status construction theory and suggest a means for testing hypotheses derived from the assumption . The reasoning below draws heavily on Zelditch and Floyd's (1998) insightful analysis of the relationships among consensus, dissensus, and the construction of social validity in a situation . If a participant speaks up to challenge an apparent correspondence in the situation between actors' nominal categories and their status markers and expected competence, what is the effect? The challenge might question the validity of the competence differences enacted between nominally different actors . Or the challenge might accept the competence and status marker differences but question
90
CECILIA L. RIDGEWAY
their link to the actors' nominal categories . Such a challenge might explicitly attribute the status and competence differences to some other difference between the actors or might suggest that the actors are exceptions to their nominal categories . However phrased, the challenge suggests that a link between the nominal distinction and evaluation and competence would not necessarily be accepted by everyone, creating uncertainty about its validity as a social schema. Zelditch and Floyd (1998) argue that the validity of something that has been challenged can be reaffirmed in the situation if the majority of the actors present appear to reject the challenge and support the thing that was challenged . An explicit action on the part of some participant to reject a challenge to the correspondence among actors' nominal categories and their status markers and expected competence would be necessary to reassert its validity . Most others present must appear to support this rejection by standing by the validity of the correspondence. If, on the other hand, no one speaks up to actively resist a challenge or if the majority in the situation do not support that resistance, then the social validity of the correspondence between the nominal distinction, status markers, and competence will crumble . Furthermore, even when the validity of the correspondence is reasserted in the situation, the fact that it was challenged places some limits on the range of actors that can be presumed to accept the correspondence, narrowing and weakening its social validity . Classic research on conformity suggests that a break from the appearance of unanimity in a group greatly reduces the pressure on those who privately disagree with the majority to go along with them (Asch 1955 ; Shaw, Rothschild, and Strickland 1957) . Thus any challenge to consensus about the correspondence between actors' nominal categories and their status markers and competence undermines the validity of that correspondence to some degree, especially in the eyes of actors who are not personally persuaded by the correspondence . Actors disadvantaged by the correspondence may be more likely to fall in the latter category . These considerations suggest hypotheses that may be derived from the formal belief formation assumption in order to test its assertion that social validity is a powerful ingredient in the formation of status beliefs . The assumption implies that actors will be less likely to form status beliefs about a nominal distinction in a situation where a correspondence among actors' nominal categories and their status markers and expected competence is challenged than in a situation where the correspondence appears consensual . In addition, in a situation in which a challenge to such a correspondence occurs, the greater the proportion of participants who act to support the challenge rather than the correspondence, the less the likelihood that the participants will form status beliefs about the nominal distinction . 3 Empirical verification of these hypotheses would support the assumption that the ability of interactional contexts to lend social validity to an association between nominal differences and status and competence is central to the process by which interaction creates status beliefs .
The Formation of Status
91
Beliefs
A GRAPH-THEORETIC REPRESENTATION OF BELIEF FORMATION With a formal specification of the mechanism by which interaction induces status beliefs in hand, the next step is to represent this mechanism in the terms of expectation states theory . Expectation states theory represents its formal arguments about the development of power and prestige orders in terms of theoretical graphs (Berger et al . 1977 ; see Webster and Whitmeyer 1999 for a recent explication) . My goal here is to adapt these theoretical graphs to represent status construction theory's assumptions about the formation of status beliefs in interaction .
Graphing Belief Formation Expectation states theory's graphs represent the way established status characteristics, reward levels, and behavioral patterns that are salient in a situation shape the expectations for task performance that a focal actor, P, holds for self compared to each other actor (0 1 . .0,) in the situation . When P and 0 differ on an existing status characteristic, such as educational attainment, that carries broad, diffuse status value in society and P has a more valued state of that characteristic (is better educated) than 0, expectation states theory graphs the situation as shown in the
P
D+
0
D
P
Na(+) (I'+/Y+) C*+
0
Nb(-) (F /Y) C*
C *+
T+
C*
T
a)
I'
T
Actors who differ on an existing diffuse status characteristic b). The formation of a status belief about a nominal distinction, N
Figure 1 . a) .
92
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
top of Figure 1 . This graph for an existing diffuse status characteristic provides a template for graphing the formation of a new status belief that creates a status characteristic . For clarity, let me explain Figure la. In it "possession" lines link P to a more valued state of the diffuse status characteristic (D+) and link 0 to a less valued state of that characteristic (D-) . Negative signed "dimensionality" lines link the two states of D indicating that they are contrasting states of the same characteristic . Widely shared status beliefs about D (say, education) link it to general expectations for competence (F), indicated by "relevance" lines connecting states of D to states of F . General expectations for greater competence from the better educated (F+) than the less educated (I'-) lead through relevance lines to expectations that P has more ability at the task at hand in this situation (C*+) while 0 has less of that ability (C*-) . Expectations about task ability lead to corresponding expectations for better task outcomes (T+) from P than from 0 (T-) . When actors form status beliefs in interaction, they impute differences between nominally distinct actors in some degree of general competence beyond that necessary for the specific situational task. In addition, these imputed general competence differences between actors are linked to the state of the nominal distinction that the actor possesses . As a first step in graphing this situation, the nominal distinction can be represented as "N" which divides actors into Nas and Nbs . When, in the formation of a status belief about N, actors link general competence to the nominal distinction, it transforms N into an evaluated distinction with a more and less valued state (i .e ., N+ and N- instead of just Na and Nb) . Therefore, the formation of a status belief about a nominal distinction, N, can be represented as an imputed line of relevance that links P and O's states of N and their presumed competence in the situation (C*-T) by means of an intervening assumption about their differences in some type of valued general competence . 4 In Figure lb this logic is used to graph the formation of a status belief about N . In this graph P is an Na and 0 is an Nb . P's presumed competence in the situation is higher (C*,-T,) than O's is (C*A-TA) . From their apparent differences in competence in the situation and their differences in N, P imputes (dashed relevance lines) corresponding differences in some valued general competence (I'/y) that P infers is linked to their states of N . When actors link general competence differences with a nominal distinction, they may assume, unless they encounter evidence to the contrary, that these competence differences apply broadly across most situational tasks and goals . In this case, expectation states theory would represent the imputed competence differences as a gamma (T'), for general competence . On the other hand, actors may impute competence differences that they assume apply to a specific range of tasks, represented as an upsilon (y) . The circumstances in which actors infer one type a competence difference rather than another is a question that is beyond the scope of the present chapter .
The Formation of Status Beliefs
93 GO
/T t + C*+ T2+
TZ
C*Ti -
0Z Figure 2 .
Formation of Status Beliefs After Two "Doubly Dissimilar" Encounters
From this foundation, we can develop graphs that represent the formation of status beliefs in two situations that have been investigated in research on status construction theory . In the first "doubly dissimilar" situation, actors differ in resources as well as the nominal distinction . After two encounters like this in which power and prestige orders developed that corresponded to resource (pay) differences, Ridgeway and colleagues (1998) found that actors formed status beliefs favoring the pay advantaged nominal category . Figure 2 represents an actor, P's, formation of a status belief about a nominal distinction, N, after two doubly dissimilar encounters . P is an Nb . 0 1 , who is an Na, is the actor P dealt with in the first encounter . All P's assumptions about 0 1 from the first encounter remain as a referent for P in the second encounter where P interacts with 02 who is also an Na . Thus lines representing P's and 0 1 's links to differential task success in the first encounter (i .e ., links to T 1 ) are present in the graph as well as lines linking P and 02 to expected task success in the second encounter (links to T2) . Since, in the situation studied by Ridgeway and colleagues (1998), the task was the same for both encounters, T 1 and T2 are linked to the same ability characteristic (C*) . Both 0 1 and 02 possessed higher levels of a valued goal object (GO+), pay, than did P (GO-) . Differences in pay imply different levels of social rewards (R+ and R-) between P and each 0 which turn imply differences in expected competence in each encounter (C*-T 1 and C*-T 2 ) . After two encounters where those who are better rewarded and appear more competent are Nas rather than Nbs, P infers a link (dashed lines) between states of N and general competence (17y), forming a status belief .5 In the second situation investigated by status construction theory, nominally different actors develop a power and prestige order on the basis of the behavioral inter-
94
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
/0 1
Na(+) --
Figure 3.
The Formation of Status Beliefs After Two Behaviorally Differentiated Encounters Between Nominally Different Actors
change patterns that emerge between them without supporting differences in resources . After two such encounters, Ridgeway and Glasgow (1996) found that subjects formed status beliefs favoring the nominal category that consistently had higher standing in the power and prestige orders of the encounters . A graph of belief formation in this situation is shown in Figure 3 . P, an Nb, has had two partners, 01 and 02, both of whom were Nas . Both partners acted confidently and assertively (b 1 + and b2+) in task discussions with P, casting P into reactive, less assertive behavior patterns (b l - and b2-) . As these assertive-reactive behavioral interchange patterns came to characterize the interaction between P and each 0, they evoked cultural images of status typified, leader-follower behavior (B+ and B-) . Status typified behaviors are culturally associated with differences in general problem solving ability (Y+ and Y-) which in turn suggests differences between the actors in competence at the task at hand . After two nominally different partners who seem more competent and act more leaderlike than P, P infers an evaluative link between the nominal characteristic and general competence, forming a status belief . Graphing Social Validity and Challenges
The belief formation assumption that I have proposed for status construction theory asserts that the social validity that an interaction lends to an association between actors' nominal differences and their status markers and expected competence is an important determinant of the likelihood that actors will form status beliefs from the experience . How can social validity and challenges to social validity be represented in graph theoretic terms?
The Formation of Status Beliefs
95
Graphs represent an interactional situation from the perspective of a given actor, P . In that sense, they do not directly represent collective attributes of the actors' situation, such as consensus or social validity . On the other hand, validity develops from the appearance of consensus that the situation presents to each of the actors . In the face of a challenge, it develops from the appearance of explicit majority support for something . Graphs can represent the appearance of consensus that a situation presents to an actor . They can do so through the relationship the graph portrays between an actor, P's, own first-order expectations for each person's relative performance in the situation and the second-order expectations communicated by another actor for those people's relative performances (Moore 1985 ; Troyer and Younts 1997 ; Webster and Whitmeyer 1999) . P's own expectation that "0 knows more about this task than I do" is a first-order expectation . Second order expectations are someone else's expectations about P and 0 that are communicated to P . Thus, P's assumption that "someone else thinks 0 knows more about this task than I do" is a second-order expectation . There is substantial evidence that actors presume consensus in an interactional situation unless they receive explicit information to the contrary (see Zelditch and Floyd 1998) . When actors form expectations for self and others based on events in interaction and people's salient attributes, they presume that these expectations are shared . Consequently, a graph of the situation from P's perspective that contains no explicit second order expectations from another represents a definition of the situation that is socially valid for P because P takes it to be consensusal . A similar graph that contains another's second order expectations that support P's own expectations for people in the situation actively confirms P's sense that this definition of the situation is consensual, strongly validating it for P (Berger et al . 1998) . Therefore, a graph that contains no second-order expectations that are inconsistent with P's first-order expectation represents a definition of the situation that P presumes to be consensual and socially valid . If the graph also represents a situation where nominally different actors are consistently linked to differentiated performance expectations and valued goal objects, there is a likelihood that P will form status beliefs in the situation . An actor who speaks up to challenge an apparent correspondence between actors' nominal categories and their status markers and expected competence can be represented as communicating second-order expectations about the nominally different actors that conflict with P's first order expectations . Figure 4 graphs one such situation . In it P, an Nb, observes 0 1 , an Na, and 0 2 , an Nb, establish a pattern of behavior between them in which 0 1 is influential and leaderlike while 02 defers and accepts 0 1 's influence. P forms differentiated competence expectations for 0 1 and 0 2 , creating a correspondence between actors' states of N and performance expectations that P presumes to be consensual and, therefore, socially valid . Another actor in the situation, 0 3 , speaks up to challenge the presumed consensus, questioning 0 1 's reasoning and asking to hear more from 0 203'S second order expectations for 0 1 and 0 2 are represented by wavy lines con-
96
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
Figure 4 . Second-Order Expectations Challenge The Validity of an Association Between a Nominal Distinction, N, and Expected Competence
fleeting 02 to task success and 01 to task failure . 6 Since the second-order expectations are inconsistent with the P's first-order expectations for nominally different actors, this graph represents a situation in which the likelihood that P will form status beliefs is reduced . Graph Theoretic Implications
As these analyses suggest, the degree of consensus or dissensus in a group can be portrayed by the degree of inconsistency between P's first-order expectations for actors in the situation and second-order expectations for those same actors that others make explicit in the situation . Given the belief formation assumption, a straightforward implication of the graph theoretic representations is the following. The greater the number and strength of second-order expectations for nominally different actors in a situation that conflict with P's first-order expectations for those actors, the less the likelihood that P will form status beliefs about the nominal distinction . It is also apparent that the overall consistency of a graph structure linking nominally different actors to differentiated task outcomes also has implications for the formation of status beliefs in that situation . By overall consistency, I mean the extent to which all lines linking nominally different actors to task outcomes link those actors to similarly evaluated outcomes . Lines representing first-order as well as second-order expectations are both included . Holding constant the strength of these lines (generally inversely proportional to their length), the greater the degree of consistency in a graph structure linking nominally different actors to evaluated outcomes, the greater the likelihood that P will form status beliefs about the nominal distinction . This more general implication of the graph theoretic representation of belief formation covers situations in which a consistent correspondence between actors' nominal differences and their status marker and expected competence differences never clearly develops as well as situations where such a correspondence is explicitly challenged .
The Formation of Status Beliefs
97
There is a third prediction about belief formation that can be derived from graph theoretic representations as well . Consider a graph that represents a completely consistent correspondence between actors' nominal differences and their links to evaluated task outcomes . The more elements linking nominally different actors to differentially evaluated task outcomes in such a graph, the more comprehensive it is (Berger et al . 1998) . These elements can be attributes of the actors, such as supporting resources or status characteristics, they can be referent others from previous encounters, or they can be additional others in the present situation . The point is that each of these elements provides another consistent link between actors' nominal differences and their expected competence . Therefore, the more comprehensive a graph structure is that links nominally different actors to evaluated outcomes in a consistent manner, the greater the likelihood that P will form status beliefs about the nominal distinction . Comprehensiveness affects belief formation partly by strengthening the expected competence differences between nominally different actors . However, since the impact on competence expectations of each new consistent element is progressively less, this strengthening effect attenuates as comprehensiveness increases . Comprehensiveness also affects belief formation by broadening the appearance of consensus about an evaluative difference between nominally distinct actors by portraying a wide array of social evidence that supports it. The reinforcement of validity through wider evidence may be comprehensiveness' most powerful effect on belief formation . These predictions derived from graph theoretical representations of the belief formation process suggest the value of transcribing status construction theory into terms that are compatible with expectation states theory .
BECOMING PART OF THE SOCIAL FRAMEWORK When status beliefs are widely held in a society, they become part of its taken-for-granted, roughly consensual culture . Expectation states theory argues that status beliefs which are established in the culture form part of the social framework of beliefs that actors bring to a situation of action and use to frame their behavior there (Berger, Wagner, and Zelditch 1982 ; Zelditch and Floyd 1998) . The social framework of beliefs is a cultural tool kit of taken-for-granted beliefs that actors use to make sense of interactional situations and the actors within them in order to orient their own behavior in the situation . Among other things, the social framework includes beliefs defining the socially significant categories of actors in the culture and their social meaning and status value in society (e .g ., beliefs about men and women, people of different ethnic groups, or different occupations) . Actors presume that beliefs in their social framework are consensual and act on them accordingly .
98
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
If certain interactional experiences are sufficient to induce status beliefs in their participants, how and when do these beliefs become stable elements in those actors' taken-for-granted social framework of beliefs? Due to their specific interactional experiences, individuals who acquire a status belief about a nominal distinction may come to presume that the belief is widely consensual before it actually is in the society . These individuals learn to take the belief for granted as part of their social framework of beliefs . In this way, individuals, due to the sequences of interactional experiences they have had, may "bootstrap" the process which the status beliefs become broadly consensual in society by presuming that it already is so . Status construction theory deals with this process by arguing that beliefs that actors form in one encounter are strengthened by future encounters that enact power and prestige orders between nominally different others that confirm the status beliefs (Ridgeway 1991 ; Ridgeway and Balkwell 1997) . Of course, by acting on the newly acquired status belief in future encounters with nominally different others, the individual substantially increases the likelihood that the status belief will, in fact, be supported in those encounters . Encounters with nominally different others that disconfirm the status belief undermine it, according to status construction theory, and reduce the likelihood that the individual will act on the belief in the next encounter . The extent to which the belief is undermined by a disconfirming encounter, however, depends on strength with which the belief is held . A belief which has been strongly established in prior experience will only be slightly weakened by a single disconfirming event . The belief formation assumption offered here suggests that the "strength" of status beliefs might better be conceived as the extent to which an actor presumes that belief to be consensually valid in a society . The broader the presumed consensuality of a status belief, the more the actor can rely on the belief to effectively frame any given interaction where it is relevant and salient (i .e ., encounters with those who differ on the status valued distinction) . Subsequent encounters with different tasks and actors that support a person's newly formed status belief confirm that the belief is not merely a locally valid construction of reality, but rather, a broadly valid interpretation of the nominal distinction that, it appears, would be accepted by almost anyone . It is an empirical question how many confirming experiences are necessary before a status belief appears sufficiently consensual and valid to an actor that it becomes a stable element in the actor's taken-for-granted social framework . I suspect, however, that the number is small, say three or four . The local reality of encounters and the social validity they convey are powerfully persuasive agents for individuals . I suspect that people generalize quickly from a few such persuasive experiences of local consensus to the presumption of a more general consensus . Indeed, without such a tendency to generalize quickly from local consensus, the presumption of general consensus about a status belief would be difficult to for actors to achieve . The presumption of general consensus about a social frame-
The Formation of Status Beliefs
99
work of beliefs, in turn, is fundamental to the emergence of social structure from routine interaction . It seems that people take on status beliefs from interaction because of the appearance of consensus in a local situation that makes an enacted correspondence between people's nominal differences and their status markers and competence appear to be a valid social fact. Subsequent encounters that confirm this status belief, even if they do so because of the self-fulfilling effects of an actor's own behavior, broaden the appearance of consensus about the status belief . As the appearance of consensus is validated across contexts and actors, the belief becomes part of the actor's accepted social framework . As more actors in the society take on the belief and make it part of their social framework, the chance of disconfirming experiences drops . At some point the status belief really does become roughly consensual in society in that almost everybody assumes that "most people" hold the belief and act on it. Thus, the persuasive power of the appearance of consensus in some local situations eventually creates a genuinely broad consensus in a society.
CONCLUSIONS Given the importance of status relations in society and the central role that widely held status beliefs play in organizing status relations, it is remarkable that sociologists have so little systematic evidence about the formation and change of status beliefs . Status construction theory posits a set of processes that are sufficient (although not necessary) to create status beliefs that become part of the taken-for-granted social framework of most actors in a population . As initially formulated, status construction theory offers some deceptively simple ideas about the formation, transfer, and strengthening and weakening of status beliefs in interaction and seeks to specify the social conditions under which they would lead to widely shared status beliefs about a nominal distinction . Empirical and theoretical developments now suggest that widely held status belief are indeed likely to develop when a nominal distinction becomes correlated in a population with an inequality in resources, as status construction theory originally posited . More generally, however, current research suggests that status beliefs are likely to develop when one nominal group is relatively advantaged compared to another in any factor, not just resources, that systematically biases the development of power and prestige when members from the two groups interact . Furthermore, chance processes alone may sometimes create status beliefs about a nominal distinction through path dependent processes . Such conclusions about the development and spread of status beliefs under different social conditions depend, however, on the nature of the processes by which interaction induces actors to form status beliefs in the first place and "teach" them to others through interaction . Thus, status construction theory turns on its assump-
1 00
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
tions about the processes by which interaction causes people to form status beliefs about nominal differences . To develop status construction theory into a useful account of the development and change of status beliefs, it is important to provide a clear theoretical specification of the process by which interaction creates status beliefs and suggest means for testing this specification . This has been my goal here . Analyzing the mechanism by which an interactional context induces status beliefs in its participants even when the belief disadvantages them highlights the importance of the appearance of consensus and social validity that the context provides for those who participate in it . I argue that it is the apparent social validity of a correspondence between participants' states of a nominal distinction and their differentiated status markers and expected competence that persuades them to infer a status belief about the distinction . On the basis of this argument I have proposed a formal belief formation assumption for status construction theory and derive testable hypotheses from it . I have shown as well how this assumption can be represented in the graph theoretic terms of expectation states theory, allowing further predictions to be derived . The next step is to conduct empirical tests of these hypotheses . To understand the role of status relations in social stratification and inequality, we must understand how structural conditions, social distinctions, and status beliefs co-evolve in society . Gaining a fuller theoretical and empirical understanding of the power of interaction to create status beliefs under different structural conditions is a first step in this project . From it, we may begin to assemble the tools as well to understand the conditions under which status beliefs change in a society .
NOTES 1 . In this experiment as well as those reported in Ridgeway and Glasgow (1996) and Ridgeway and Erickson (1998), a nominal distinction was created by giving subjects a test purportedly measuring "personal response style." Subjects were told that personal response style is a stable characteristic of individuals that divides the population into two roughly equal sized categories . "Results" of the test showed that subjects and partners differed in their personal response style category . 2. Zelditch and Walker (1984) refer to this form of validity as endorsement because it is based on apparent support by an actor's peers in the situation . 3 . As a simplification, this assumption holds constant any status differences among the participants. It is likely that the support of high status participants will have a greater impact than the support of lower status participants . Incorporating the impact of status differences among the participants is a project for another paper . 4. Expectation states graphs represent actors' competence expectations for one another rather than their power and prestige behaviors because power and prestige behaviors reflect competence expectations. As a consequence, an expectations states graph of the formation of status beliefs represents more explicitly the development of a link to competence expectations than to status markers and evaluation (although the latter is implied) . However, the graph does explicitly represent the formation of an evaluative dimension to the (formally) nominal distinction by indicating that Na and Nb become N+ and N- .
101
The Formation of Status Beliefs
5 . Webster and Hysom (1998) suggest that people in doubly dissimilar situations may also form status beliefs by forming referential beliefs about N . That is, they may form beliefs that Nas generally possess more valued social rewards than do Nbs in society . In a graph this would be represented by the imputation of a link between states of the nominal distinction and levels of goal objects (GO+ and GO-). This is a plausible suggestion that awaits empirical investigation . 6 . The lines are wavy because the strength of the impact of second-order expectations on P's own expectations varies with strength of P's expectations for the person who communicates the secondorder expectations (Fisek, Berger, and Norman 1995 ; Webster and Whitmeyer 1999). I will not deal with this aspect of second-order expectations here, however . 7 . Expectation states theory refers to this as the size of the performance expectation advantage in the situation that actors of one nominal category have over those of another category .
REFERENCES Asch, S . 1955 . "Opinions and Social Pressure ." Scientific American 193 : 31-35 . Berger, J ., T . L . Conner and M . H. Fisek. 1974 . Expectation States Theory: A Theoretical Research Program. Cambridge, MA : Winthrop. Berger, J ., M. H . Fisek, R. Z . Norman, and M . Zelditch, Jr . 1977 . Status Characteristics and Social Interaction. New York: Elsevier . Berger, J ., C . L. Ridgeway, M . H. Fisek, and R. Z . Norman . 1998 . "The Legitimation and Delegitimation of Power and Prestige Orders ." American Sociological Review 63 : 379-405 . Berger, J ., D . Wagner, and M . Zeldtich, Jr. 1982 . "A Working Strategy for Constructing Theories : State Organizing Processes ." Pp . 107-123 in Metatheorizing, edited by G. Ritzer . Newbury, CA : Sage . Berger, J ., and M . Zelditch, Jr . 1998 . Status, Power, and Legitimacy: Strategies and Theories. New Brunswick, NJ : Transaction Press . Brewer, M ., and R . Kramer. 1985 . "The Psychology of Intergroup Attitudes ." Annual Review of Psychology 36 : 219-243 . Conway, M . M ., T. Pizzamiglio, and L . Mount. 1996 . "Status, Communality, and Agency : Implications for Stereotypes of Gender and Other Groups ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71 : 25-38 . Cook, K . S . 1975 . "Expectations, Evaluations, and Equity ." American Sociological Review 40 : 372-88 . Dovidio, J . F., and S . L . Gaertner. 1993 . "Stereotypes and Evaluative Intergroup Bias ." Pp . 167-194 in Affect, Cognition, and Stereotyping, edited by D. M . Mackie and D . L . Hamilton . New York : Academic Press . Harrod, W . J . 1980. "Expectations from Unequal Rewards ." Social Psychology Quarterly 43 : 126-30. Fisek, M . H ., J . Berger, and R . Norman . 1991 . "Participation in Heterogeneous and Homogeneous Groups : A Theoretical Integration ." American Journal of Sociology 97 : 114-42. Fisek, M . H ., J . Berger, and R . Norman . 1995 . "Evaluation and Formation of Expectations ." American Journal of Sociology 101 : 721-746. Gerber, G . 1996 . "Status in Same-gender and Mixed-Gender Police Dyads : Effects on Personality Attributions ." Social Psychology Quarterly 59 : 350-63 . Geis, F . L ., J. Jennings, and D . Corrado-Taylor . 1984 . "Sex vs . Status in Sex-Associated Stereotypes ." Sex Roles 11 : 771-85 . Mark, N. 1999 . "The Emergence of Status Inequality ." Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Sociological Association, Chicago, August . Mark, N., L. Smith-Lovin, and C . L . Ridgeway. 1999. "The Emergence of Status Inequality ." Unpublished paper. Stanford University .
102
CECILIA L . RIDGEWAY
Markovsky, B., L . F. Smith, and J . Berger. 1984 . "Do Status Interventions Persist?" American Sociological Review 49: 373-82. Messick, D . M ., and D . M . Mackie . 1989 . "Intergroup Relations." Pp . 45-81 in Annual Review of Psychology, Vol. 40, edited by M. R . Rosenzweig and L . W. Porter. Palo Alto, CA : Annual Reviews Press. Moore, J . C . 1985 . "Role Enactment and Self Identity : An Expectations States Approach ." Pp . 262-316 in Status, Rewards, and Influence : How Expectations Organize Behavior, edited by J . Berger and M. Zelditch . San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Pugh, M . D ., and R. Wahrman. 1983 . "Neutralizing Sexism in Mixed-Sex Groups : Do Women Have to Be Better than Men?" American Journal of Sociology 88 : 746-62. Ridgeway, C . L. 1991 . "The Social Construction of Status Value : Gender and other Nominal Characteristics ." Social Forces 70 : 367-86. Ridgeway, C . L . 1997 . "Where Do Status Value Beliefs Come From? New Developments ." Pp. 137-158 in Status, Network, and Structure, edited by J . Szmatka, J . Skvoretz, and J . Berger . Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press . Ridgeway, C . L., and J. W . Balkwell . 1997. "Group Processes and the Diffusion of Status-Value Beliefs ." Social Psychology Quarterly 60 : 14-31 . Ridgeway, C . L ., and J . Berger . 1986 . "Expectations, Legitimation, and Dominance Behavior in Task Groups ." American Sociological Review 51 : 603-17 . Ridgeway, C. L ., J . Berger, and L. Smith . 1985 . "Nonverbal Cues and Status : An Expectation States Approach ." American Journal of Sociology 90 : 955-78 . Ridgeway, C . L ., E. H . Boyle, K. Kuipers, and D . T . Robinson . 1998. "How Do Status Beliefs Develop? The Role of Resources and Interactional Experience ." American Sociological Review 63 : 331-50 . Ridgeway, C . L ., and K . Glasgow . 1996 . "Acquiring Status Beliefs from Behavior in Interaction ." Paper presented at the meeting of the American Sociological Association, New York, August . Ridgeway, C. L ., and K. G. Erickson . 1998. "Third Party Observers and the Spread of Status Beliefs in Interaction ." Paper presented at the International Sociological Association 14 World Congress of Sociology, Montreal, July . Shaw, M . E ., G . H . Rothschild, and J . F. Strickland . 1957 . "Decision Processes in Communication Nets ." Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 54: 323-330. Stewart, P . A ., and J . C . Moore, Jr . 1992. "Wage Disparities and performance Expectations ." Social Psychology Quarterly 55 : 70-85 . Troyer, L ., and C . W . Younts. 1997 . "Whose Expectations Matter? The Relative Power of First-Order and Second-Order Expectations in Determining Social Influence ." American Journal of Sociology 103 : 692-732 . Wagner, D ., and J. Berger . 1997. "Gender and Interpersonal task behaviors : Status Expectation Accounts ." Sociological Perspectives 40 : 1-32 . Weber, M . 1968. Economy and Society, edited by G. Roth and C . Wittich and translated by E . Fischoff et al . New York : Bedminster Press . Webster, M., and M . Foschi. 1988. Status Generalization : New Theory and Research . Stanford, CA : Stanford University . Webster, M ., and S . J. Hysom . 1998 . "Creating Status Characteristics." American Sociological Review 63 : 351-79. Webster, M ., and J. M . Whitmeyer. 1999 . "A Theory of Second-Order Expectations and Behavior." Social Psychology Quarterly 62 : 17-31 . Zelditch, M., Jr. and A . S . Floyd . 1998 . "Consensus, Dissensus, and Justification ." Pp. 339-68 in Status, Power, and Legitimacy : Strategies and Theories, edited by J . Berger and M. Zelditch . New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Press. Zelditch, M ., Jr. and H. A . Walker. 1984 . "Legitimacy and the Stability of Authority ." Pp . 1-25 in Advances in Group Processes, vol . 1, edited by E . J . Lawler . Greenwich, CT: JAI Press .
THE IMPACT OF TASK AND CATEGORICAL CUES ON SOCIAL INFLUENCE FLUENCY AND ETHNIC ACCENT AS CUES TO COMPETENCE IN TASK GROUPS
Margaret Foddy and Phoebe Riches
ABSTRACT A theoretical extension of Berger, Webster, Ridgeway, and Rosenholtz's (1986) theory of status cues is proposed, which argues that task cues which contradict expectations based on categorical cues may reduce or overcome the effects of the latter on status processes . Possible mechanisms for these differential effects were suggested . Two studies examined the relative impact of verbal fluency and ethnic accent on perceptions of competence, and on acceptance of influence in a group task . In Study 1 tape-recorded passages read by Greek- and Anglo-Australian speakers were judged by independent groups on rating scales which tapped three dimensions : intelligence, competence/education, (referred to as status dimensions), and solidarity . Fluency of speaker affected raters' judgments of confidence and intelligence, but
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 103-130 . Copyright © 2000 by JAI Press Inc. All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 103
104
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
not solidarity ; ethnic identity of speaker affected only ratings of intelligence . Tape recordings of fluent and stilted versions of a conversation were used in Study 2, which employed a computer controlled joint decision task . Subjects were required to resolve prearranged disagreements with a partner whose ethnicity (Anglo-Australian or Greek-Australian) and fluency (fluent or stilted) were cued by means of an overheard conversation . It was predicted and found that fluency would have a stronger impact on deference toward the partner than ethnic accent, and fluency affected post-task ratings of confidence . Partner's ethnicity did not affect rates of deference, but did affect post-task ratings of the partner : Anglo-Australians were rated as significantly more educated, quick, intelligent, and confident by both Anglo- and Greek-Australians .
INTRODUCTION When we first encounter people in a work setting or at a more informal occasion, we quickly process a great deal of information from their speech and appearance . Even before they speak, we will have noted such things as gender, race, age, and attractiveness from their physical characteristics, and perhaps socioeconomic status and sexual orientation from their dress . While the content of their initial conversation is very important, so too are the paralinguistic and nonverbal cues which accompany the words. Ethnic and class accent will add important information to our emerging impression of the person . Posture, gaze, and general demeanour will tell us whether the person is comfortable and at ease, or nervous and unconfident . Speech characteristics, such as fluency, loudness, and pitch will either confirm or contradict these initial impressions . As the televised debates of various U .S . presidential candidates showed, these latter cues can be decisive in the judgments made about the abilities and trustworthiness of well-known figures ; they are likely to be even more important in first impressions of strangers . People are also able to form strong and reasonably accurate impressions of others from hearing them speak. In an early analysis, Allport and Cantrill (1934) cited a report in the New York Times Magazine of June 18, 1933 : "The human voice, when the man [sic] is not making conscious use of it by way of impersonation, does in spite of himself, reflect his mood, temper and personality ." Although the study referred to radio speakers, another early study by Allport and Cantrill showed that listeners were quite prepared to judge both physical traits and personality of ordinary speakers from tape recordings . Further, they were more accurate than chance in judging personality dimensions such as extraversion/introversion and ascendance/submission . These authors noted the importance of stereotypes in the judgment process, with listeners including several related features once they had placed a person into a particular category ; this often reduced accuracy, but increased consensus among listeners as to the meaning of different vocal characteristics (see also Pear 1931) .
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
1 05
Subsequent studies of paralinguistic and nonverbal cues have demonstrated clearly that nonverbal cues, including paralanguage, ) have a strong influence on the perception and evaluation of others (Ball, Byrne, Giles, Berechree, Griffiths, Macdonald, and McKendrick 1982 ; Callan, Gallois, and Forbes 1983 ; Giles and Sassoon 1983 ; Ridgeway, Berger, and Smith 1985 ; Sebastian and Ryan 1985 ; Driskell, Olmstead, and Salas 1993 ; Rashotte and Smith-Lovin 1997) . Researchers studying the social impact of speech characteristics have focused on how cues such as fluency, loudness, ethnic accent, and "correctness" of speech affect different dimensions of person perception . For example, Lambert (1967 ; Lambert, Hodgson, Gardner, and Fillenbaum 1960), in his studies of ethnic accent, argued that perceptions of ethnic speech reflect two dimensions : status (competence, dominance, power, status, and achievement) and solidarity or affiliation (friendliness, solidarity, affiliation, and helpfulness) . 2 The accents of higher status groups evoke more favorable reactions from both low and high status raters on the status dimension . Other studies have shown that unfavorable evaluations are given to the speech patterns of regional speakers, ethnic group members, and lower-class populations in terms of status and prestige, from judges who may or may not be standard speakers themselves (Callan et al . 1983 ; Sebastian and Ryan 1985 ; Giles and Coupland 1991 ; Cargile, Giles, Ryan, and Bradac 1994) . Ratings on the solidarity dimension reflect a tendency for people to favor members of one's own group, although evidence for this latter relationship is mixed (Ryan and Carranza 1975 ; Callan et al . 1983 ; Nesdale and Rooney 1996) . The two dimensions, status and solidarity, also appear in ratings of speech qualities such as fluency, speed, and loudness, with higher status and competence being assigned to speakers who are fluent, loud, and fast . Several studies (Sereno and Hawkins 1967 ; Smith, Brown, Strong, and Rencher 1975 ; Brown, Giles, and Thakerer 1985) have shown that rate of speech influences listeners' perceptions, with judgments of competence a linear function of increasing rate . Similarly, fluency has been shown to affect perceptions of competence . For example, Pryor and Buchanan (1984) assessed the impact of nonverbal behavior on jurors' evaluations of the defendant's credibility and guilt and found the defendant received the highest competency ratings in the setting where he was highly fluent, maintained good eye contact, and did not fidget. Norton-Ford and Hogan (1980) demonstrated that fluent speech produced significantly higher ratings than nonfluent speech on adjectives such as assertiveness, competence, and aggressiveness (see also Rashotte and Smith-Lovin 1997) . Solidarity (or affiliation) ratings seem to be a more complex function of speech qualities . Existing evidence suggests that the relationship between rate of speech and solidarity ratings, for example, is sensitive to contextual variables such as the type of audience the speaker is addressing (Brown et al . 1985) . These effects may be best explained in terms of speech accommodation theory (Giles, Mulac, Bradac, and Johnson 1986), which predicts a positive evaluation of people who adjust their speech to suit the needs of the listener . For purposes of this paper, the effects
106
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
of nonverbal cues on the perception of solidarity are of less interest than their impact on perceived status, because it is argued that, in task groups, competence at the group task is more important to status and status-linked behavior than liking derived from shared group membership .
NONVERBAL CUES AS STATUS CUES More recent research has indicated that perceptions of competence and status reflecting the "status dimension" in nonverbal and paralinguistic cues also affect subsequent behavior in task settings (Tuzlak and Moore 1984 ; Ridgeway 1987 ; Riches and Foddy 1989 ; Sev'er 1989, 1991) . Cues which evoke impressions of greater intelligence, competence, and prestige (Tuzlak 1989 ; Riches and Foddy 1989) evoke greater deference or compliance from listeners . This research arose in part from an interpretation of nonverbal and paralinguistic cues in terms of status characteristics theory (Ridgeway et al . 1985 ; Berger et al . 1986 ; Ridgeway 1987 ; Rashotte and Smith-Lovin 1997) . Status characteristics are attributes that vary among the actors in a group, and are "differentially valued in terms of honour, esteem or desirability" (Berger, Rosenholtz, and Zelditch 1980) . They can be specific to a task (e .g ., high compared with low skill at a statistical task), or diffuse, such that people possessing the positive state of the characteristic are not only believed to have some specific abilities, but are also assumed to be generally better and more competent than those possessing the negative state (e.g ., adults are assumed to be more competent than children) . Gender, race, SES, and physical attractiveness have been identified as diffuse status characteristics, as has ethnicity (Foschi and Takagi 1991 ; Riches and Foddy 1989) . Status characteristics theory claims that members of a task group3 take all the status information about each performer, which has become salient in the situation, and combine it to form an aggregated expectation for performance at a group task.4 According to status characteristics theory, diffuse status characteristics continue to exert an influence even when more specific information about task-relevant ability is available . As noted below, one process by which this occurs is through the impact of diffuse status on nonverbal behaviors . In task groups relative expectations for task performance determine the emergence of a power and prestige order : those for whom higher expectations are held are given more opportunities to contribute, their performances are evaluated more positively, and they exert more influence over group decisions (Berger et al . 1980 ; Berger and Zelditch 1985) . Berger and colleagues (1986) argued convincingly that the theory of status characteristics and expectation states could be used to integrate the seemingly disparate set of findings about nonverbal and paralinguistic cues, by seeing them as part of the process by which relative status is expressed or enacted .
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
1 07
Berger and colleagues (1986) outlined a typology of verbal, nonverbal, and paralinguistic cues, providing a link between this typology and the general theory of status characteristics and expectation states . They distinguished task and categorical cues . 5 According to Berger and colleagues (1986), task cues are nonverbal and paralinguistic behaviors "that give information about performances taking place in the immediate interaction situation" (p. 5) . Task cues include such things as verbal fluency, loudness, eye gaze, and various gestures which give an indication of how well the actor is doing, or will do, on the group task . In studies of nonverbal cues people giving off high task cues tend to be those who come to the interaction with high external status, or who come to hold higher status within the group . Higher status people speak more quickly, interrupt more, have fewer speech dysfluencies, and so on, and people exhibiting this profile are seen to have higher status and associated task competence (Dovidio, Brown, Heltman, Ellyson, and Keating 1988) . Greater fluency has been associated with higher ratings of competence and dynamism (Sereno and Hawkins 1967) . Regardless of whether a confident speaker is in fact more competent, actors and perceivers act as if such a correlation exists . In terms of status characteristics theory, task cues are read as evidence for the level of more general problem-solving ability which becomes relevant to the immediate task situation . In other words, task cues affect expectations for good or poor performance on the task at hand . There is little research concerning the relative importance of various task cues for impressions of competence, although fluency and rate of speech are clearly important cues (Sereno and Hawkins 1967 ; Cargile et al . 1994) . Berger and colleagues (1986) distinguish between "speech task cues" and "behavioral task cues," but their central point is that while these are superficially very different, they may have very similar effects . While task cues seem to signal possession of competencies relevant to the task at hand, Berger and colleagues (1986) claim that they are "governed" by relative position on external status characteristics brought to the group . These may be signaled by categorical cues, which are signs that a person is a member of a particular social group, or "category," and include things such as skin color, visible indicators of sex or age (Ridgeway et al . 1985), as well as class and ethnic accent, modes of dress, and other status indicators . In the framework of status characteristics theory, categorical cues such as class and ethnic accent have their effect by establishing the relative external status of speakers and listeners, so that an upperclass accent, for example, cues the listener that the speaker possesses the positive state of a diffuse status characteristic, with the attendant positive expectations for performance on a group task . Riches and Foddy (1989) showed that listeners perceived an ethnic Greek-Australian accent as signaling lower education, intelligence, and competence than an Anglo-Australian accent . According to the account offered by Berger and colleagues (1986), cues will come to coincide with any differentiation established by categorical cues to diffuse and specific status characteristics . This is an important theoretical proposition, which suggests that many of the diverse findings about the nonverbal
108
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
behavior of men and women, people of different military rank, people of different age, and so on can be explained by a more general proposition about how relative societal statuses external to the group become salient in the group setting, and form the basis for performance expectations . Thus, it is predicted that cues such as confident speech patterns are not stable individual propensities, but rather, expressions of the actors' beliefs about who is likely to know more about the task at hand in any given situation . In turn, these beliefs reflect aggregated status characteristics incorporating both specific and diffuse status characteristics of speaker and listener . For example, a tutor who speaks fluently and with confidence to a group of freshmen students, may make only tentative and stumbling contributions in a staff meeting with senior colleagues . Women may display authoritative task cues on a female task, but be deferential when dealing with tasks more associated with men .
INCONSISTENCY BETWEEN TASK CUES AND CATEGORICAL CUES Less studied, but equally important theoretically, is the possibility that relative expectations for competence based on categorical cues may be altered or reversed if task cues are inconsistent with them . What will happen if a person with the lower state of a diffuse characteristic, for example, race, exhibits a high level of task cues, while the person possessing the higher state of the diffuse characteristic (white) does the reverse? The status dominance principle implies that such a combination is unlikely, but status characteristics theory provides mechanisms for aggregation of both consistent and inconsistent status information . Because of their greater "immediacy," task cues may contribute more to the formation of relative expectations than categorical cues . When status information is being combined, some information is given greater weight : characteristics which are more directly relevant to the task at hand have greater impact on expectations (see Humphreys and Berger 1981 ; Berger et al . 1986) . Connections between characteristics and expectations for task performance are represented as "paths of relevance" of differing length ; characteristics with lengthy paths are weighed less in the aggregation of status information than are those with shorter paths . Berger and colleagues (1986) suggest that task cues should have a greater effect than categorical cues on expectations for task performance, other things being equal, although there is no evidence available about this "strength of relevance" prediction for cues (p . 14) . Aside from intuitions that task cues are more "immediate," the relatively greater impact of task cues may rest on a belief that such cues are determined by one's diffuse and specific status characteristics . Such a belief implies that incompetent people cannot act confidently, and that because people with low diffuse status (women, blacks in mixed-sex or mixed-race groups) will feel relatively incompetent, they will be unable to control
Fluency and
Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
109
the expression of these self-evaluations . Unfortunately, the research literature provides only a small number of studies of the effect of task cues on perceptions of status and competence (e .g ., Ridgeway 1987 ; Tuzlak and Moore 1984 ; Sev'er 1989) . Sev'er's work compared the relative impact of a large number of task cues (demeanor, gaze, verbal fluency) and a diffuse status characterisic, race . She found that while demeanor could overcome the negative effect of race on rates of influence in a mock jury setting, both demonstrated confidence and race affected ratings on a range of attributes, such as confidence and task capacity (but not intelligence) . What are the possible mechanisms for such differential impact? First, task cues may have a shorter path of relevance to task outcomes than do categorical cues . Expressed nonverbal confidence may lead an observer/listener to infer higher levels of intelligence and general ability in the actor . The numerous studies of speech characteristics and speaker evaluations (e .g., Cargile et al . 1994) provide evidence for a direct link between paralinguistic cues such as rate of speech, loudness, hesitations (confidence), and perceived competence/intelligence . Many of these studies were designed to assess the correlation between speech characteristics and "personality," and so the measured variables may skew the results in favor of inferences to internal traits . Nevertheless, it is plausible that an observer/listener may make a link between task cues and generalized competence . Berger and colleagues (1986) make the explicit claim that "the path of relevance linking task cues to abstract task ability to task outcomes is shorter than that linking status characteristics to task outcomes" (p . 14) . They argue that task cues such as fluency, speech rate, tone of voice, and so on activate states of more general problem-solving ability, and that these states are applicable to the immediate situation . Confidence displayed in a task situation through expressive task cues, for example, may be seen to be "possessed" by an individual, and to induce a link directly through abstract task ability, to the specific task characteristic C*, or instrumental ability to produce a positive task outcome, T(+) . As noted above, such confidence is normally encountered in those with an expectation advantage, that is, those who also possess more positive states of diffuse and specific status characteristics . However, task cues indicating confidence may come to signal task competence in their own right . In this interpretation, when task cues are the only information that a person has about another actor, higher levels of expressed confidence will create relatively high expectations for a positive outcome on the task . This process of inference is very general : nonverbal confidence (paralinguistic, demeanor, gaze, etc .) in any task setting would generate inferences of higher task ability than unconfident cues . The key point is that confident task cues produce a strong inference to a positive task outcome, in contrast to hesitant cues . This is the first interpretation of the term "immediate ." Because there is no existing convention for the representation of task and categorical cues, we use the graph representations of paths of relevance from Fisek, Berger, and Norman (1991) . These authors introduced the concept of "behavior
110
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
patterns" which may signal higher or lower status . One person may make a suggestion, which the other accepts ; this differentiates the actors and may become salient, especially if no other status characteristics do . 6 Fisek and colleagues argue that behavior patterns are linked to generalized task ability, and that behavior patterns may therefore link actors to task outcome through a burden of proof process (see Skvoretz and Fararo 1996) . We make a parallel argument that task cues may also enter as behavioral elements in the task situation . A person who makes firm, confident statements is making a claim that she has the ability to make a positive contribution ; a hesitant style cues a willingness to let others take the lead . We may represent this as follows : p b (+) Y (+) C*(+) T(+) o b (-) Y (+) C*(-) T (-) p = focal actor; o = other; b = task cue (behavior pattern) ; Y = abstract task ability ; C* = task characteristic ; T = task outcome . A second interpretation is that task cues directly signal the person's state of the instrumental task characteristic in the immediate situation . In this case, a person who knows that he or she can do the task would be expected to sound confident ; if the person sounds confident, it indicates competence to do the task . On this interpretation, the path of relevance would be even shorter-there would be a direct link from the person to the instrumental task ability, to the task outcome : p b (+) C* (+) T (+) o b (+) C* (-) T (-) p = focal actor ; o = other ; b = task cue (behavior pattern) ; C* = task characteristic ; T = task outcome. Here the impact of task cues would be very strong indeed . However, our interpretation of the literature on the effects of task cues such as fluency and rate of speech, for example, suggest that they are mediated through their effect on evaluations of actors as possessing generalized competence . In addition to the information they provide about confidence in the immediate situation, some task cues may also have links to diffuse and specific status char-
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
111
acteristics . For example, fluent speech may also signal high levels of education and dominant social class ; particular intonations may be associated with high status backgrounds as well as immediate confidence . As a result there may be multiple paths of relevance to the task outcome, and these may contribute to the strong impact that task cues have on expectations for ability . Because most of the literature on nonverbal cues is not organized in terms of their effect on status organizing processes, it is not possible to make a strong case that task cues have more paths of relevance than do categorical cues ; this is an empirical question which should be investigated . In contrast to task cues, categorical cues may have a relatively long path of relevance to task outcome (unless they signal a very specific relevant status characteristic (e .g ., a physician's diploma on the wall in a medical setting) . Status characteristics theory predicts that they will be given less weight in the formation of expectations than will task cues . Skin color and ethnic accent provide information about which states of a diffuse status characteristic a person possesses . These are argued by Berger and colleagues to be less immediate and to have lower impact on expectations for competence than cues such as demeanor, gaze, speech fluency, loudness, and so on. A graphical representation might be : p categorical cue (+) D (+) I' (+) o categorical cue (-) D (-) F (-)
C* (+) C* (-)
T (+) T (-)
p = focal actor ; o = other ; D = diffuse status characteristic ; F = generalized expectation state ; C* = task characteristic ; T = task outcome . Even if length of paths of relevance are the same for task and categorical cues, the former may be in some sense "stronger," reflecting Berger and colleague's (1986) notion of greater "immediacy ." Foddy and Smithson (1996) outlined three different ways in which paths of equivalent length might produce differing strength of paths of relevance ; one of these was that different indicators of abilities might vary in their "diagnosticity" for task performance, producing more certain inferences about competence . An analogous idea may be applied to cues : some cues, such as task cues, may be regarded as more diagnostic or predictive of performance in the immediate situation, and be treated as "strong cues," while category memberships may be "weaker ." Thus, whether task cues and categorical cues have close or distant relationships to task performance, task cues may have a greater impact on aggregated expectation states . There is currently no way to represent the idea of "stronger paths" in the graph theoretical framework for status
112
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
characteristics theory (Foddy and Smithson 1996) ; this possibility is not pursued in the current study, but left to future research . The relative impact of task and categorical cues is difficult to detect when they are consistent, but a clearer picture may be gained when they lead to inconsistent expectations . Thus, while we have noted that task cues may usually be governed by categorical cues, there are situations in which they may provide contradictory and inconsistent information . This is the subject of the research reported below . We now state these ideas in the form of general hypotheses, and then outline a more specific test situation . There we examined the relative influence of ethnic accent, a categorical cue, and fluency, a task cue, on evaluations of speakers and on acceptance of influence in a dyadic decision-making task . We take as background the propositions of Berger and colleagues (1986), which claim that : (1) in groups which are initially equal in external status, task cues will determine the power and prestige order which emerges ; and (2) in groups where external status is not equal, aggregated external status will govern task cues in interaction, and that these will contribute to the emergence of the power and prestige order . Differences in the resulting power and prestige order will reflect status differences ; people with higher aggregated status will receive and accept more action opportunities, receive higher evaluations, and exert more influence because they will have a higher net expectation advantage compared to those with lower status . Because our research also investigated perceivers' evaluations of speech, our hypotheses contain reference to evaluations .
HYPOTHESES Hypothesis 1 . When actors are differentiated on categorical cues to status characteristics, their relative expectations for task competence will be consistent with relative evaluations of these status characteristics . Hypothesis 2 . Relative expectations for task competence will be consistent with task cues exhibited by group members . Hypothesis 3 . Combination of task and categorical cues : Task cues will have a greater impact on relative evaluations and expectations for competence than will categorical cues . When a task cue is inconsistent with a categorical cue, net evaluations and expectations of actors will be consistent with the task cue . When multiple task and categorical cues are present, expectations will be formed according to the aggregation principles of status characteristics theory (Humphreys and Berger 1981) . To provide an initial test of these hypotheses we apply them to the case of ethnic accent and speech fluency . We argue that these paralinguistic cues are systematically interpreted as cues to diffuse status characteristics and general task
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
113
ability, respectively . Ethnic accent is a categorical cue that a person is a member of a particular ethnic group ; ethnicity is in turn a diffuse status characteristic, when it has associated with it differential evaluations and performance expectations . When people have to make decisions about who is likely to be competent in a novel task setting, they will generalize from their evaluations and expectations about ethnic groups, to consistent beliefs about relative competence of members of the ethnic groups on various group tasks . Ethnic accent has its effects on status/ competence beliefs, by acting as a cue that a given speaker is a member of a particular category (see Riches and Foddy 1989 for a fuller discussion) . As outlined above, fluency of speech is a task cue-people who speak without hesitation and relatively quickly are considered to be more confident and competent than those who do not . While higher status people may normally speak more fluently, we examine the case in which these two cues are deliberately made independent, in order to assess whether expectations evoked by external category membership may be changed or canceled by a more immediate task cue . In the research reported below, we tested the prediction that a task cue (fluency) would have greater impact on evaluations of speakers than would a status cue (ethnic accent) . We also predicted that expectations for performance, and thus rates of rejection/acceptance of influence would also show these effects . An equally important result will be if we find that the two sorts of cues have equal impact. This will suggest that they should be represented as having paths of relevance of equal length and strength . Aside from their importance to the theoretical framework outlined above, studies of the relative impact of different sorts of nonverbal and paralinguistic cues are needed . Most research to date has focused on single cues, or has sought simply to establish that a number of cues has an effect . There is no systematic evidence, for example, concerning which of several fluency cues (pauses, disfluencies, speed, etc .) has the greatest impact on ratings of fluency, or on impressions of competence . Nor is it known how fluency cues interact systematically with other speech characteristics to create overall impressions . The status characteristics framework provides a basis from which investigations of the combinations of cues and their relative impact can proceed . We report the results of two experiments . The first assessed the relative impact of fluency and ethnic accent on perceptions of competence/status and solidarity on ratings made of Anglo-Australian and Greek-Australian speakers . In an earlier study, Riches and Foddy (1989) showed that a Greek-accented speaker received lower ratings on competence-related dimensions (industrious, powerful, educated, intelligent, and competent) than did an Australian-accented speaker .' The first study extends this work to examine how fluency of speech combines with ethnic accent . The second study makes use of the now familiar "dyadic decisionmaking task" developed for tests of status characteristics theory (Berger, Fisek, Norman, and Zelditch 1977, chap . 5), to investigate how fluency and ethnicity jointly affect the acceptance of influence in a group task .
114
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
An important feature of our research strategy was the measurement of perceivers' impressions of a speaker based on paralinguistic cues . We wanted to discover whether these impressions would differentially reflect task and categorical cues . More specifically, we tested whether these two different cues would have effects of different magnitude, and whether each would have an impact on different dimensions (perceived confidence versus diffuse status) . If this turns out to be the case, it provides a tool for testing the processes by which expectation for competence arise .
STUDY 1 : RATER EVALUATIONS OF RECORDED SPEECH Method In the first study four female speakers were presented to the subjects, three Greek-accented and one Anglo-Australian . The age range of the speakers was 21 to 28 years . A total of 89 first-year female psychology students (Anglo-Australians) listened to one of eight audio-tapes, and made ratings of the speaker (described below) . Subjects were tested in small laboratory classroom groups . Two of the Greek-accented speakers were actors and one was a native Greek speaker ; the Australian speaker was not an actor, and English was her native language. Each confederate read the same passage twice, once fluently and once in a stilted manner. The fluent passage was recorded with no pauses, pacing was maintained at a constant level, and no "ums" and "uhs" were present . The same passage was used for the stilted reading with pauses, and "ums" and "uhs" included at predetermined positions . 9 The experimenter introduced the study by explaining to the subjects that people often form impressions of others by listening to voices on the telephone or radio . Subjects were instructed to form an impression of the speaker by listening to a recording of her reading a passage out of a novel . They were then given a questionnaire which contained : (1) 14 six-point semantic differential adjective scales for rating impressions of the speaker (e .g ., intelligent, helpful ) ; (2) five six-point adjective scales for rating speech quality (loud, fast, natural, high-pitched, and fluent) ; (3) questions about the speaker's demographic background ; and (4) questions about the demographic background of the subject judging the tape . Most of the subjects were Anglo-Australian, and the ratings of those from Greek and Italian students were not included in the analysis . In terms of relative diffuse status characteristics, the listener-judges were equated with the Anglo-Australian speaker (same gender, same ethnicity), and higher status than the Greek-Australian speaker. No measures were made of the subjects' fluency . A further object of the first study was to identify one Anglo- and one Greek-accented speaker whose taped voices would be clearly identifiable as having one of these ethnic accents (the diffuse status characteristic), and whose stilted
Fluency and
Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
115
Table 1 . Means and (Standard Deviations) for Subjects' Ratings of Fluency for the Anglo - and Greek-Accented Speakers : Study 1 Versions of Speech Ethnic Accent of Speaker Anglo-Australian Greek-Australian Total
Fluent
Stilted
Total
4 .67 (0 .97) 3 .10(l .07) 3 .86(l .23)
2 .76(l .2) 2 .00 (0 .67) 2 .48(l .08)
3 .740-44) 2 .67(l .10)
and fluent readings of the passage would be perceived as discriminably different on this speech characteristic . Surprisingly, the native Greek speaker was judged least reliably as having a Greek accent . The Greek-accented actor whose tape produced most reliable identification of ethnicity was chosen for use in Study 2 . 10 It was hypothesized that there would be main effects for fluency and ethnic accent on ratings of competence and intelligence (hypotheses 1 and 2), and that the effect size for fluency would be greater than that for ethnicity (hypothesis 3) . Support for hypothesis 3 would also be gained if fluency influenced judgments of the speakers, but ethnic accent did not . 11 Results : Study 1 Manipulation Check : Ratings of Fluency
The fluency ratings for the Greek-accented speaker and the Anglo-Australian speaker are presented in Table 1 . A 2 x 2 ANOVA (ethnicity by fluency) produced a significant main effect for fluency of speaker (F=28 .23, d .f. 1, 62, p < .001), and a main effect for ethnicity (F = 21 .70, d.f. 1, 62, p < .001) ; there was no interaction . The effect size for fluency (d = 1 .5) was greater than for ethnicity (d = 1 .2), but both are reasonably large (Cohen 1977) . Although care was taken to ensure that the fluency of the Greek and Australian speakers was equal in the fluent conditions, and equally stilted in the stilted conditions (same number of pauses, same number of disfluencies, similar length, similar loudness, etc .) rated fluency reflected both speech qualities and ethnicity of the speakers . As we discuss below, expectations based on categorical cues may lead listeners to "hear" the speaker's fluency as consistent with these expectations . Ratings of Speaker Attributes
A factor analysis of the ratings of the two speakers in both the stilted and fluent versions was conducted in order to collapse the 19 variables (14 traits and five speech qualities) on the personality questionnaire . The aim was to examine
116
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
'table 2. Variables Good Dependable Helpful Pleasant Natural Industrious Competent Active Powerful Confident Loud Fast
Factor Loadings of the Rating Scales onto Three Factors : Study 1 a Factor I
Factor 2
.792 .648 .494 .526 .433 .580 .712 .567 .365 - .383
- .385
.650
Fluent Big Educated Intelligent Note:
Factor
.410 .639
- .667 .308 -.750 - .749
a . Variables with loadings less than .3 are not presented .
whether factors would emerge which coincided with those found in investigations using the matched guise technique, namely, status and solidarity/affiliation dimensions, and whether the ethnic accent and fluency would affect these differently. Principal components analysis and varimax rotation revealed three factors with eigenvalues over two which accounted for 45 percent of the variance . As presented in Table 2, the first factor represents a cluster similar to that described previously as a solidarity/affiliation factor (good, dependable, helpful, pleasant, natural). The second factor may be argued to represent a confidence/ competence dimension (fast, industrious, powerful, confident, active, competent) ; and the third factor an intelligence/education factor . The term "competent" also loaded on the third factor, but to a lesser degree than intelligence and education . One may argue that "competent" is not all that different from "intelligent" in relation to "general task ability" . We comment on this in the general discussion . Of the speech dimensions, "fast" and "loud" loaded on the second factor, and fluency loaded on factor 3 . Factors 2 and 3 are both similar in many ways to the "status" factor of language attitude studies . A two-way MANOVA (ethnicity by fluency) on the three factors as dependent variables produced a significant effect for ethnicity of speaker on the intelligence dimension (F = 29 .806, d .f. 1, 62, p < 0 .001) . The Anglo-Australian speaker was rated significantly higher on the intelligence dimension (factor 3) than the Greek-Australian. The effect of fluency was found to be significant for both dimensions two and three (F= 8 .11, d .f., 1,62, p < 0.01) and (F = 39 .79, d .f. 1,62, p < 0.001) ; the fluent speaker was rated more positively than the stilted speaker on
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups Table 3 .
117
Mean Ratingsa of Speakers' Attributes by Fluency and
Ethnicity of Speaker (standard . deviations in parentheses) : Study 1 Speaker Attribute Confident Competent Intelligent Educated Note:
a
Anglo-Fluent 3 .38(l .24) 4 .22 (1 .17) 4 .89 ( .583) 5 .38 ( .608)
Greek-Fluent 4 .4 4 .4 4 .0 4 .2
( .681) ( .821) ( .973) ( .894)
Anglo-Stilted 3 .00 3 .41 4 .12 4 .24
( .935) ( .795) ( .60) ( .903)
Greek-Stilted 2 .7 ( .949) 3 .2 ( .919) 4 .0043) 3 .2 (1 .033)
Rating scales were from 1-6, with higher ratings indicating higher levels of the attribute .
both . There were no significant interaction effects for any dimension . The subjects rated the Anglo-Australian speaker as intelligent 35 .5 percent more often than they rated the Greek-Australian speaker as intelligent . They rated the fluent versions of the speakers as intelligent 73 percent more often than the subjects rated the stilted versions as intelligent, the lower overlap indicating a stronger effect for fluency (the task cue) . The responses to the solidarity dimension were not influenced by either of the independent variables . Looking at the effect sizes for the separate attributes of confidence and competence, only fluency had a sizeable effect size (ds 1 .07 and 1 .08, respectively [Cohen 1977]) ; for ethnicity the effect sizes were close to zero (see Table 3 for means and standard deviations) . However, on the attributes intelligent and educated, both fluency and ethnicity had moderate to large effects (for intelligence, .49 for fluency, .65 for ethnicity; for education, 1 .24 for fluency, 1 .28 for ethnicity) . The estimates of the speakers' age and education level showed some indication that accent and fluency act as status cues . Both the Australian and Greek speaker were judged to be in the same age range as the subjects, although the Anglo-Australian was judged somewhat older than the Greek-Australian (26 and 21 years, respectively) . The speakers were in fact 25 and 26 years . A large number of the subjects estimated the Anglo-Australian speaker to have a university degree-17 for the fluent version and 13 for the stilted reading . The fluent Greek speaker was estimated to be a university student by only five of the subjects and a high school graduate by the majority (15) subjects . No subjects estimated the stilted Greek-Australian speaker to be a university student, she was believed to be a high school graduate by seven of subjects and primary level by three . These judgments are consistent with the loadings of education and intelligence on the third factor (educated/intelligent) . While we were not surprised to find that stilted reading produced judgments of lower education levels, it was surprising that this effect was larger for the Greek-Australian speaker . The results of the first study support the argument that a task cue, fluency, has a significant impact on perceptions of generalized task competence and confidence, and on perceptions of the more diffuse characteristic, education/intelli-
118
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
gence ; the latter presumably also has a path of relevance to expectations for task performance . Ethnicity, a categorical status cue, influenced judgments of the more diffuse status characteristic (education) and a general judgment of ability (intelligence), but did not appear to influence directly judgments of competence and confidence in the situation . These results are interesting in their own right, for they show that paralinguistic task cues make salient status characteristics that attract differential evaluations . While we do not wish to make too much of the different patterns of effect for fluency and ethnicity, they do suggest that future research should include measures of impressions made by different status cues . This would allow an assessment of whether behavioral cues produce qualitatively and quantitatively different effects than do categorical cues (i .e., through different sorts of paths of relevance) . The findings from the first experiment also provided the materials needed to construct an experimental situation in which fluency and ethnicity could be varied independently, so that their relative effects on expectations and influence could be examined . We needed to identify paralinguistic cues which signaled category membership (ethnicity), and levels of task cues (fluency) ; the first experiment established that Greek-Australian accented speakers and Anglo-Australian speakers would be reliably identified as such, and that listeners could also distinguish between fluent and non-fluent speech cues . While the first experiment's results also provide evidence of differential evaluation of the speakers' status characteristics, it remains to be demonstrated that these evaluations translate into differences in influence in a task group .
STUDY 2 : RELATIVE IMPACT OF STATUS CUES ON INFLUENCE IN TASK GROUPS Overview In the second study naive Anglo-Australian and Greek-Australian female subjects participated in the standard expectation states influence task, in which they were led to believe they would be making decisions in a two-person group . In the course of performing the task, the subject found herself in disagreement with her (simulated) partner, and had to resolve the disagreements by staying with her own choice (rejecting influence), or changing to the partner's choice (accepting influence) . The design makes it possible to test the impact of ethnicity and fluency of partner's speech as cues to competence, by assessing their impact on acceptance of influence . Levels of ethnic accent (Anglo or Greek) and fluency (fluent, or disfluent) were introduced via overheard conversations between the experimenter and the bogus partner . Post-experimental impressions of the partner's attributes were obtained in the form of rated "personality impressions ." The experimental paradigm emphasizes the importance of the task, and encourages a collective ori-
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
119
entation ; both of these are important scope conditions of status characteristics theory (Berger et al . 1977) . Subjects Female university students who volunteered to participate in the experiment completed an information sheet . Included on the sheet were questions about the ethnic background of the subjects and languages spoken at home . Second generation Anglo- and Greek-Australians (n = 95) were initially selected to participate in the study . Subjects were categorized as second-generation Greek-Australian if at least one of their parents were born in Greece and Greek was spoken at home, and as Anglo-Australian if both their parents were born in Australia . Subjects were fluent speakers of English . The average age of the subjects was 21 .79 years. Of the initial pool of 95 subjects, 80 were retained for analysis, (40 Anglo-Australians and 40 Greek-Australians) . Of the 15 excluded, five expressed clear suspicion of the study, two failed to meet scope conditions, and eight failed to detect the accent of the speaker . Procedure Female participants worked on the task in same-sex dyads and were randomly assigned to one of eight conditions in a 2x2x2 factorial design (fluency of confederate, ethnicity of confederate and ethnicity of subject) . Subjects were told they would be working with a partner on a task that required them to judge complex patterns presented to them on a computer screen . They were told that the task involved working with a "partner" positioned in an adjacent room . Subjects were told that the "partner" was simultaneously completing the first stage of the study . The computer-controlled task 12 presented pairs of stimuli composed of black and green rectangles ; the subject's job was to decide which of the pair had more black in it, and to type their response ("left" or "right") . Subjects were told that successful performance of the task required "contrast sensitivity," an important and well-researched ability . In fact, the patterns were generated by a program to ensure that there were equal amounts of black and green displayed on the screen, in scattered blocks . Proportions of choices of "left" or "right" were virtually equal on practice trials, supporting the conclusion that the task was ambiguous . The study was presented to subjects as an investigation of workplace settingsone in which they worked alone and one in which they worked with a partner . The rationale given to subjects for including a "partner" was that people's ability to make the correct decision might be improved with the additional information provided by the "partner's" response . It was explained that responses would be scored on the basis of the number of correct choices made by the dyad, and so it was legitimate to seek and give advice during the second phase of the experiment . The notion was that subjects would change their answer to agree with the "part-
120
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
ner's" response if they believed that the "partner" was more competent than themselves and more likely to give a correct response (see Berger et al . 1977 for details) . The subjects' willingness to defer to the partner thus reflects their expectations about their partners' ability ; the central dependent variable in the experiment is the proportion of times a subject rejects influence, that is, refuses to defer to the partner .
First Phase: (no partner) Subjects were given five practice trials, then completed 10 trials, without feedback about their performance . This was done to familiarize them with the task . Once the response was recorded the next set of patterns were presented . At the completion of the first phase the experimenter asked if there were any questions, then went to see if the "partner" was ready .
Second Phase: (partner) Manipulation of accent and fluency of partner . In the adjacent room the experimenter controlled an intercom and tape recorder so that subjects heard a prerecorded conversation between one of the confederates and the experimenter . The conversation involved a discussion on the malfunction of the computer and the "partner's" readiness to complete the second phase of the procedure . Efforts were made to avoid reference to status cues other than fluency and accent. Subjects were led to believe that they were eavesdropping on the conversation, as no mention was made by the experimenter of the conversation on her return to the testing room . The second phase task consisted of 20 patterns . After making each choice in phase two, the subject was told she would receive "feedback" from the "partner ." Once the subject received the "partner's" choice the computer asked for a second choice from the subject, after which the next set of patterns were presented. The subjects were not given information about the partner's second choice, and had to decide whether the partner was more or less likely to be correct when their answers disagreed . The crucial dependent variable is the P(s) or the proportion of critical trials on which the subjects resolved disagreement by staying with their own choices . On the assumption that higher rates of rejection of influence would reflect higher levels of perceived ability relative to the partner, it was hypothesized that subjects with fluent partners would reject influence less than subjects with less fluent partners ; that Anglo and Greek subjects would reject influence more from Greek than from Anglo partners, and that the effect of fluency would be stronger than the effect of ethnic accent . More specifically, we predicted the following patterns of means for P(s) :
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
121
Empirical Predictions
For Anglo-Australian and Greek-Australian subjects (focal persons), the order of P(s) from highest to lowest for the four types of partner is predicted to be : Greek-stilted > Anglo-stilted > Greek-fluent > Anglo-fluent If fluency completely overcomes the effect of ethnicity, the first and the last two means should be equal . A comment is needed on our reasons for predicting that Greek-Australian subjects would reject influence more from Greek than Anglo partners . The theory of status characteristics suggests that beliefs related to social categories, stereotypes, will be shared among members of the society, but it is not obvious that the Greek-Australian subjects would necessarily share beliefs about the competence of other Greeks relative to self (but see Ellemers and van Knippenberg 1997) . Further, these subjects were equated on ethnicity with the Greek-Australian subjects (so that only fluency should affect their expectations, just as with Anglo-Anglo pairs) . But, relative to Anglo-Australians, they possess the lower state of the characteristic, ethnicity . Thus, while it is possible that their rates of rejection of influence will be affected only by fluency and not accent for partners of the same ethnic group, ethnicity should be activated with the Anglo partner, and be reflected in lower P(s) values . Thus, the same ordering of means for P(s) are predicted for Anglo and Greek subjects . We did not measure the fluency of the naive subjects ; it was assumed that they were more fluent than the stilted "partner," and equally or less fluent than the "fluent" partner . At the conclusion of the task, the experimenter interviewed each subject, following a protocol of questions concerning task and collective orientation, credibility of procedures, and level of interest . A post-task questionnaire was also completed to check whether subjects met the scope conditions and whether the accent and fluency variables had been activated . Subjects completed a semantic differential type adjective scale of 11 pairs to check their impressions of the "partner" ; these included all but the speech and physical characteristics ratings used in the pre-test . 13 Results : Study 2 Manipulation Checks
Manipulation checks were conducted prior to the analysis of the dependent variables to ensure that the scope conditions of the theory had been established for an adequate test of the hypothesis . Detection of accent . All subjects paired with the Anglo-Australian confederate correctly recognized her as Anglo-Australian . Nine of the 20 Anglo-Austra-
122
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
lian subjects paired with the Greek-Australian confederate classified the speaker as Greek, while seven recognized her as Southern European and four believed her to be Italian . The Greek-Australian subjects classified the Greek-Australian "partner" as either being Greek (14 out of 20), or Southern European (six) . Because the evaluation of Southern Europeans tends to be similar (McAllister and Moore 1991), all of these subjects were retained for analysis . Detection of fluency . Subjects were asked for a free description of the "partner's" speech on the post-task questionnaire . It was expected that subjects would recognize the paralinguistic cue and classify it with adjectives commonly used to describe fluent and stilted speech . Eight of the 40 subjects classified the fluent speaker as confident, 15 classified her as fluent, 10 regarded her as speaking normally, and seven classified her speech as "proper ." Of the 40 subjects whose partner was stilted, 15 classified the speakers as hesitant, 16 as slow, and nine as timid . Rejection of influence (P(s)) A three-way ANOVA was conducted to investigate the differences among the means . The only significant difference was found for the comparison of the fluent and hesitant versions of the speech (F = 7 .45, p < 0 .01, d .f. 2, 72) . As indicated by the means, the level of rejection of influence was greater for the stilted versions than for the fluent versions . The effect of ethnicity of partner's accent was not significant (F = 2.12, p = 0 .15, in the direction of greater rejection of influence from Greek partners) . There was no interaction effect for subject's ethnicity and partner's ethnicity . While the interaction between fluency and ethnicity of subject was not significant (p = 0 .10), a trend was apparent : Greek-Australian subjects were more influenced by the "partner's" fluency than were Anglo-Australian subjects . The highest rate of rejection of influence was found in the condition where the Anglo subject's "partner" was a Greek-accented stilted speaker (see Table 3) ; the lowest P(s) occurred in the condition where the Greek-Australian subject had a fluent Anglo-Australian partner . These means are consistent with predictions, but otherwise the predicted order of means was not found for the Anglo subjects : levels of P(s) were similar for all cells except when the partner had a stilted Greek-Australian accent . In the other conditions, the levels of P(s) were consistent with the subject having formed equal, or slightly more positive expectations for self than for other . While fluency might "save" the Greek-fluent partner from the effects of ethnicity, the similar level of P(s) for the stilted Anglo partner does not support the claim that fluency will have a greater impact on expectations than ethnicity . For Greek-Australian subjects, the pattern of results was somewhat different, although not sufficiently different to have produced any significant interaction
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
1 23
Table 4 . Mean P(s), Means and Standard Deviations of Stay Responses, by Ethnicity of Subjects, and Ethnicity and Fluency of Partners : Study 2 Partner's Ethnic Background Anglo
Anglo subjects Fluent partner Stilted partner Greek subjects Fluent partner Stilted partner
Greek
P(s)a
M
s.d.
.68 .69
10 .3 10 .4
2 .06 2 .12
.55 .77
8 .3 11 .5
3 .71 2 .12
P(s)
M
s .d .
.71 .78
10 .6 11 .7
2 .59 2 .41
.66 .77
9 .9 11 .5
2 .56 1 .51
Note : P(s) is the proportion of stay responses over 15 critical (disagreement) trials .
effects with ethnicity of subject . The order of means of the subject's P(s) with the four partners was : Greek-stilted = Anglo-stilted > Greek-fluent > Anglo-fluent . Here, fluency of partner seems to have been a more important factor ; the Greek subjects rejected influence from both Anglo and Greek partners when they were hesitant ; the levels of P(s) were close to those of the Anglo subjects paired with a stilted Greek partner. The lowest rates of rejection of influence were, as predicted, when the partner was both Anglo and fluent (P(s) = .55) . Since we did not measure the fluency of the subjects' speech, we are not able to establish the extent to which our results depended on relative expectations formed on the basis of this cue . Personality impressions . Analysis of the series of personality impressions of the "partner" by the subjects in experiment 2 was conducted to investigate the consistency between performance outputs and perceptions . A MANOVA (ethnicity of partner, ethnicity of subject, and fluency) was conducted on the 11 variables, and the multivariate effect was significant for fluency (F = 2 .03, d .f. 11, 62, p < .05) and ethnicity (F = 2 .80, d .f. 11, 62, p < .01) . There were no significant interaction effects . Examining the univariate effects, a main effect for fluency was found only on the confidence variable (F = 6 .61, d .f. 1,72, p < 0.05) . The fluent speaker was rated as being more confident than the stilted speaker (fluent : M = 4 .2, stilted : M = 3 .5) . The univariate effect for partner's ethnicity was significant on the following ratings (in all cases, d .f . = 1, 72) : educated (F = 17 .8, p < .0001), quick (F = 9 .2, p < .01), intelligent (F = 5 .6, p < .02) and confident (F = 8 .6, p < .01) . The Anglo-Australian partner was rated significantly higher than the Greek-Australian partner . (The ratings were generally less variable than in Study 1, and sub-
124
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
jects tended to check between three and four on the six-point scales) . Effect sizes (ds) ranged from .64 for "confident," to .91 for "educated." Given the very minimal exposure that subjects had to their partners' voice over the intercom, the effects are surprisingly large . The post-experimental rating results, on which ethnicity had a more pervasive influence than fluency, seem at first to be inconsistent with the other results which suggest that fluency is a much stronger cue to competence (but see Tuzlak 1988 ; Sev'er 1989) . However, if task cues such as fluency have their effect through their immediacy, that is, by cueing competence in the immediate task setting, then there is no reason to expect this effect to last or to generalize . The naive subject heard only two short verbal interchanges in which the ethnicity and fluency of the confederate were conveyed, and it is possible that the impression of fluency would dissipate more quickly than would the ethnic identification of the partner . Tuzlak (1988) has provided a similar explanation for the relative decay of demeanor effects over time, while the effects of a diffuse status characteristic (race, in her study), increased . Such an interpretation would suggest that while high task cues will be more salient determinants of influence in task-oriented interaction, the experience of having one's category-based stereotypes contradicted will not necessarily produce a lasting effect on those stereotypes . Nevertheless, one should not lose sight of the result, that despite the greater number of effects of ethnicity on post-task ratings relative to fluency, it was still the case that fluency alone had a significant effect on rates of influence . General Discussion
We set out to provide an assessment of the claim that task cues would have a larger impact on evaluations, expectations, and influence than categorical cues to status, and more generally, to investigate the status characteristics theory interpretation of status cues . We offered possible interpretations of the claim that task cues are more "immediate" than categorical cues, and provided suggestions for graph representations of these interpretations . These graphs reflect the argument that the path of relevance from task cues to task outcomes may not only be shorter than that for categorical cues, but there may also be more paths . We adopted an empirical strategy to directly measure whether the two cues appear to "activate" different impressions of the speaker, as would be expected by the definitions of task and categorical cues (or elements, in the graph) . Having obtained some supportive evidence for this latter claim from listeners who judged the impressions of speakers who differed in ethnicity and fluency, we used an experimental design to assess whether the two types of cue could predict levels of influence accepted (a behavioral outcome) . Here we found that only fluency of speaker had a systematic effect, and ratings of the partners after the task showed that fluency affected perceived confidence of the partner . While ethnicity appeared to influence post-ses-
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
1 25
sion ratings on several attributes, these had not translated into sufficiently differential expectations to have a systematic effect on P(s) . While we are not the first to use rated impressions of the partner in empirical tests of status characteristics theory (Tuzlak 1989 ; Rashotte and Smith-Lovin 1997), these have not been used in previous work to investigate the process of inference from status cues to the emergence of status hierarchies in groups . One empirical study is not enough to establish that these direct measures will bear a stable and consistent relationship to status characteristics, but the method is promising and can be employed in the study of a range of behaviors thought to constitute behavior elements (Fisek et al . 1991), or behavioral enactments (Rashotte and Smith-Lovin 1997) . It is important to note that we are not claiming that people can report directly on the process of generalization from status characteristics to beliefs about task ability and task outcome, but rather, that we can measure their impressions of others' characteristics which the theorist may then employ in explanations of status emergence . This raises a further theoretical question concerning status cues themselves . Status cues are not status characteristics-they are visible and audible indicators of status, which operate by activating relationships of possession and relevance . While the status characteristics theoretical formulation of the operation of nonverbal cues provides a useful framework for understanding their effect on impression formation and interaction, there is much to be learned about how they exert this effect . Fisek, Berger, and Norman (1991), and Skvoretz and Fararo (1996) provide possible representations of how behavior patterns may induce differential expectation states, through links to abstract ability . Our research suggests that these links may be more complex-task cues such as fluency may trigger beliefs associated with diffuse and specific status characteristics, as well as abstract task ability . Categorical cues may activate expectations for competence, and thus biased perceptions of performance and evaluations of task cues . To date, status cues themselves are not represented in the graph representations of the theory ; in this paper we have shown them as "behavioral cues," but much work needs to be done to establish just how cues activate status characteristics . In the second study fluency had a greater impact on acceptance of influence (P(s)) than did ethnic accent, but the ratings of the partner after the experimental session suggest that the effect of ethnicity will not invariably be weaker. According to the status characteristics theory interpretation of nonverbal and paralinguistic cues, diffuse status characteristics "govern" task cues, making it difficult if not impossible for lower status participants to display confident cues . It might thus be argued that the combinations of fluency and ethnic status in this experiment are unnatural, since it is unlikely that a person with Greek-accented English would speak more fluently than would an Anglo-Australian . However, such "unnatural" combinations do occur, and the reactions of subjects to them shed light on the relative importance given to, task (fluency) and categorical (ethnic accent) cues . It may well be that a perceiver assumes consistency between specific (fluency-cued)
126
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
and diffuse (ethnicity) status characteristics, but inconsistency is also interpretable . In the case studied in this experiment, task cues inconsistent with ethnicity seemed to be interpreted as evidence that the speaker was competent . It is important to note that there was, however, no evidence for an "augmentation" effect, as proposed by attribution theorists (Jones and Davis 1965 ; Hansen and O'Leary 1985) for cases in which enhanced ability is attributed to the member of a category who is expected to do poorly, but in fact performs well (see also Biernat and Kobrynowicz 1997) . If anything, the Greek-Australians were judged by a stricter standard for ability (Foschi and Foddy 1988 ; Foddy and Smithson 1989) when they spoke fluently (high performance), and a more lenient standard for lack of ability when they spoke in a stilted fashion (low performance) . This interpretation is consistent with the ratings given in the first study ; although the tapes of the fluent Greek-Australian were equivalent to those of the Anglo-Australian on length, number of pauses, number of disfluencies (that is, fluency), the Greek-Australian was judged to be less fluent . This only makes sense if the Greek-Australian was being judged by a stricter standard for fluency . It would seem necessary to make the Greek-accented speaker much more fluent on objective measures, before she was judged to be equally fluent, in comparison to the Anglo-Australian . This points to the need for further definition of the concept of fluency ; ethnic accent may be part of perceivers' understanding of what it is to be fluent . While a central aim of the current study was to assess the relative impact of a task and categorical status cues on expectations for task competence and related influence processes, the generality of the finding of greater impact for the task cue can only be established by empirical research using a variety of task and status cues . As Nemeth (1983) has noted, decisive tests will be difficult to construct, because of the difficulty of equating strength of the task and categorical cue stimuli . More important, it may not always be the case that perceivers attend more to "immediate" cues ; in some circumstances, categorical cues may provide better prediction of task competence, or may be believed to provide better prediction . For example, negative stereotypes about Aboriginal Australians are often so pronounced that a high level of task cues might well have minimal impact on beliefs about the actor's task competence . When a diffuse status characteristic has multiple short paths of relevance to task competence, it may well be a more important determinant of expectations . The theory of status characteristics makes explicit provision for the variability in beliefs about and evaluation of the characteristics of the members of different social categories but does not at present incorporate the concept of magnitude of different status characteristics which may operate in a continuous rather than a discrete manner (Foddy and Smithson 1996, 1999) . There is evidence from language attitudes research which is also relevant . Brennan and Brennan (1981) showed that the degree of accentedness of the speech of Mexican Americans predicted the extremity of status ratings . Ryan, Carranza, and Moffie (1977) found that Spanish-American accents were rated negatively, and the more extreme the accent, the more negative the stereotype . These findings
Fluency and Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
127
suggest that the magnitude of status differences suggested by different status cues needs to be taken into account in predicting their net impact . Elaboration of the theory to allow for "degree of difference" on status characteristic may provide an explanation of those cases in which categorical cues outweigh more immediate task cues . In addition to such an elaboration, recent developments in status characteristics theory provide potential accounts of the conditions under which task cues might not be as strong as expected . Ridgeway and Berger (1988) have suggested that the interpretation of task cues may be qualitatively different for high and low status actors, especially in legitimated status orders (i .e., the same task cue may indicate that an actor is competent or "uppity") . Similarly, Foddy and Smithson (1989) argued that the same nonverbal behaviors may be evaluated against different standards, depending on the status of the actor (p . 85 .) These possibilities merit exploration . As this study, and a previous one (Riches and Foddy 1989) have shown, our understanding of nonverbal behavior will be enhanced by exploiting a systematic theoretical framework that provides a link between the perception of these cues, and subsequent behavior .
ACKNOLWEDGMENTS We thank Ben Ong for programming the task and for statistical advice, and Joseph Berger for comments on an earlier version of the manuscript . The comments of two anonymous reviewers were also valuable .
NOTES 1 . Following De Paulo and Friedman (1998, p. 3), we define "nonverbal" as "not words ." They note that vocal cues such as voice tones and inflections are nonverbal in that they are not words, and include them with facial expression, touch, gaze, and gestures as "nonverbal communication ." 2. The term "affiliation" will be used here to refer to this dimension, although it is more frequently labeled "solidarity" in studies of speech perception. 3 . The scope of the theory is explicitly limited to groups in which members want to solve or perform well on a task requiring an important ability, but for which there is no objectively correct answer . While this limits the range of the theory, there are many settings in which the scope conditions are met, particularly those where attributions of competence must be made. 4 . Expectations are always held relative to others in the group . 5 . They also distinguished expressive and indicative cues ; this distinction will not be discussed in this paper. We deal only with two sorts of expressive cues . 6 . Fisek and colleagues (1991) argue that behavior patterns activate "status typification states," or "abstract conceptions of typical high-status and low-status behaviors" (p . 1373) ; these then become relevant to like-signed abstract task ability . For our purposes, we do not need to include the additional step of status typification states . 7 . Several studies have shown that unfavorable evaluations are given to the speech patterns of regional speakers, ethnic group members, and lower-class populations in terms of status and prestige, from judges who may or may not be standard speakers themselves (Ryan and Sebastian 1985 ; Callan, Gallois, and Forbes 1983) .
128
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
8 . In Melbourne, as in other parts of Australia, Greeks form a sizeable minority group, many of them first-generation migrants to the country. Studies of social distance indicate that Anglo-Australians evaluate Greeks below people from Northern Europe and North America, but higher than a number of other groups from Southeast Asia and the Pacific . 9 . The duration of the fluent tape was two minutes 20 seconds, and the stilted tape was slightly longer, due to the insertion of pauses and "umm's" and "uh's" (two minutes 45 seconds (Australian accent), and three minutes 10 seconds (for the longest Greek-accented passage) . Subjects responded to only one version of the passage. 10. For the fluent version of the Greek accented speaker, there were 24 raters ; 13 judged her to be Greek, three Italian, four Mediterranean, and four Yugoslavian . For the stilted version there were 12 raters ; five judged her to be Greek, two Italian, three Mediterranean, and two Indian . The degree of inaccuracy was not of concern since previous research had shown that perceptions of Greeks, Italians, and Southern Europeans were similar with respect to competence. All raters judged the Anglo-Australian speaker's ethnicity accurately in both the stilted and fluent versions . 11 . It is always possible that the particular operationalizations of task and categorical cues maybe relatively more or less successful, and that any differences in impact may reflect such differences . While we endeavored to make both cues equally salient, we recognize that this calibration problem is a persistent one. 12. Barry Markovsky provided the first version of the task which was then modified by Ben Ong to suit the experiment. A copy of the modified program is available from the first author . 13 . The rating dimensions were: industrious, educated, powerful, pleasant, competent, interested, quick, considerate, intelligent, helpful, and confident .
REFERENCES Allport, G . W., and H . Cantrill . 1934 . "Judging Personality from Voice ." Journal of Social Psychology 5 : 37-55 . Ball, P., J. Byrne, H . Giles, P . Berechree, J. Griffiths, H . Macdonald, and I . McKendrick. 1982 . "The Retrospective Speech Halo Effect : Some Australian Data." Language and Communication 2 : 277-284. Berger, J ., M . H . Fisek, R . Z. Norman, and M . Zelditch. 1977 . Status Characteristics and Social Interaction. An Expectation States Approach . New York: Elsevier . Berger, J., S . J . Rosenholtz, and M . Zelditch . 1980 . "Status Organising Processes." Annual Review of Sociology 6 : 479-508 . Berger, J., M . Webster, C . Ridgeway, S . J. Rosenholtz. 1986 . "Status Cues, Expectations and Behaviors." Pp. 1-22 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol . 3, edited by E . Lawler . Greenwich, CT : JAI Press . Brennan, E. M ., and J . S . Brennan . 1981 . "Accent Scaling and Language Attitudes : Reactions to Mexican American English Speech." Language and Speech 24 : 207-221 . Brown, B . L., H. Giles, and J. N . Thakerar . 1985 . "Speaker Evaluations as a Function of Speech Rate, Accent and Context." Language and Communication 5 : 207-220. Callan, V., C . Gallois, and P. A . Forbes . 1983 . "Evaluative Reactions to Accented Speech : Ethnicity, Sex Role and Context ." Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 14 : 407-426 . Cargile, A . C ., H . Giles, E . B . Ryan, and J . J . Bradac . 1994 . "Language Attitudes as a Social Process : a Conceptual Model and New Directions ." Language and Communication 14 : 211-236 . Cohen, J . 1977 . Statistical Power Analysis for the Behavioral Sciences . New York : Academic Press. Depaulo, B . M ., and H. S . Friedman . 1998 . "Nonverbal communication ." Pp . 3-41 in The Handbook of Social Psychology (4th ed .), edited by D. T . Gilbert, S . T. Fiske, and G. Lindzey . Boston : McGraw-Hill .
Fluency and
Ethnic Accent as Cues to Competence in Task Groups
129
Dovidio, J. F ., C . E . Brown, K. Heltman, S . L . Ellyson, and C . F . Keating . 1988 . "Power Displays Between Women and Men in Discussions of Gender-linked Tasks : a Multichannel Study ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 55 : 580-587 . Driskell, J. E., B . Olmstead, and E. Salas . 1993 . "Task Cues, Dominance Cues, and Influence in Task Groups ." Journal of Applied Psychology 78 : 51-60. Ellemers, N., and A . van Knippenberg . 1997 . "Stereotyping in Social Context ." Pp. 208-235 in The Social Psychology of Stereotyping and Group Life, edited by R . Spears, P . J . Oakes, N . Ellemers, and S . A . Haslam. Oxford : Blackwell . Fisek, H., J. Berger, and R. Norman. 1991 . "Participation in Heterogeneous and Homogeneous Groups : a Theoretical Integration ." American Journal of Sociology 97 : 114-142. Foddy, M ., and M . Smithson . 1989 . "Fuzzy Sets and Double Standards : Modelling the Process of Ability Inference ." In Sociological Theories in Progress : New Formulations, edited by J . Berger, M . Zelditch, and B . Anderson . Newbury Park, CA : Sage. Foddy, M ., and M. Smithson . 1996 . "Relative Ability, Paths of Relevance and Influence in Task-oriented Groups ." Social Psychology Quarterly 59: 140-153 . Foddy, M ., and M . Smithson . 1999 . "Can Gender Inequalities Be Eliminated?" Social Psychology Quarterly 62 : 302-324 . Foschi, M ., and M . Foddy. 1988 . "Standards, Performances and the Formation of Self-other Expectations." Pp . 248-260 in Status Generalization : New Theory and Research, edited by M . Webster and M . Foschi . Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Foschi, M ., and J. Tagaki . 1991 . "Ethnicity, Task Outcome and Attributeions : A Theoretical Review and Assessment ." Pp. 177-203 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol . 8, edited by B . Markovsky and E. Lawler. Greenwich, CT : JAI Press. Giles, H., and N . Coupland. 1991 . Language : Contexts and Consequences . Milton Keynes : Open University Press . Giles, H ., A. Mulac, J . J . Bradac, and P . Johnson. 1986 . Communication Yearbook 10 : 13-48 . Giles, H ., and R . N . St . Clair . 1985 . Recent Advances in Language, Communication, and Social Psychology . London : Lawrence Erlbaum . Giles, H., and C . Sassoon. 1983 . "The Effect of Speakers Accent, Social Class Background, and Message Style on British Listeners' Social Judgments ." Language and Communication 3 : 305-313 . Hansen, R . D ., and V . E . O'Leary . 1985 . "Sex-determined Attributions ." In Women, Gender and Social Psychology, edited by V . E . O'Leary, R . K . Unger, and B . S . Wallston . Hillsdale, NJ : Lawrence Erlbaum . Humphreys, P., and J . Berger. 1981 . "Theoretical Consequences of the Status Characteristics Formulation ." American Journal of Sociology 86 : 953-983 . Jones, E . E ., and K . E . Davis . 1965 . "From Acts to Dispositions : The Attribution Process in Person Perception ." In Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol . 2, edited by L . Berkowitz. New York: Academic Press . Lambert, W . E. 1967 . "The Social Psychology of Bilingualism ." Journal of Social Issues 23 : 91-109 . Lambert, W . E ., R . C . Hodgson, R. C . Gardner, and S . Fillenbaum . 1960. "Evaluational Reactions to Spoken Languages ." Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 60 : 44-51 . McAllister, I., and R. Moore . 1991 . "Social Distance among Australian Ethnic Groups ." Social Science Research 75 : 95-100. Nemeth, C . J . 1983 . "Reflections on the Dialogue Between Status and Style : Influence Processes of Social Control and Social Change." Social Psychology Quarterly 46 : 70-74 . Nesdale, D ., and R . Rooney . 1996 . "Evaluations and Stereotyping of Accented Speakers by Pre-adolescent Children ." Journal of Language and Social Psychology 15 : 133-154 . Norton-Ford, J . L., and D. R. Hogan . 1980. "Role of Nonverbal Behaviors in Social Judgments of Peers' Assertiveness ." Psychological Reports 46 : 1085-1086 . Pear, T . H . 1931 . Voice and Personality . London : Wiley .
130
MARGARET FODDY and PHOEBE RICHES
Pryor, B ., and R. W . Buchanan. 1984 . "The Effects of a Defendant's Demeanor on Juror Perceptions of Credibility and Guilt." Journal of Communication 34 : 92-99 . Rashotte, L . S ., and L. Smith-Lovin . 1997 . "Who Benefits from Being Bold? The Interactive Effects of Task Cues and Status Characteristics on Influence in Mock Jury Groups." Pp . 235-255 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol . 14, edited by E . Lawler. Greenwich, CT : JAI Press. Riches, P., and M . Foddy . 1989 . "Ethnic Accent as a Status Cue." Social Psychology Quarterly 52: 197-206. Ridgeway, C . L. 1987 . "Nonverbal Behavior, Dominance, and the Basis of Status in Task Groups ." American Sociological Review 52: 683-694. Ridgeway, C . L ., and J. Berger. 1988 . "The Legitimation of Power and Prestige Orders in Task Groups ." Pp . 207-231 in Status Generalization : New Theory and Research, edited by M. Webster and M . Foschi . Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Ridgeway, C . L ., J . Berger, and L. Smith . 1985 . "Nonverbal Cues and Status : An Expectation States Approach ." American Journal of Sociology 90 : 955-978 . Ryan, E . B ., and M . A. Carranza . 1975 . "Evaluative Reactions of Adolescents Toward Speakers of Standard English and Mexican American Accented English ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 31 : 855-863 . Ryan, E . B ., M. A . Carranza, and R. W. Moffie . 1977 . "Reactions Towards Varying Degrees of Accentedness in the Speech of Spanish-English Bilinguals ." Language and Speech 20 : 267-273 . Sebastian, R . J ., and E. B . Ryan . 1985 . "Speech Cues and Social Evaluation : Markers of Ethnicity, Social Class, and Age ." Pp . 112-143 in Recent Advances in Language, Communication, and Social Psychology, edited by H . Giles and R . N . St. Clair. London : Lawrence Erlbaum . Sereno, K. K., and G . J . Hawkins . 1967. "The Effects of Variations in Speakers' Nonfluency upon Audience Ratings of Attitude Toward the Speech Topic and Speakers' Credibility ." Speech Monographs. 34 : 58-64. Sev'er, A . 1989 . "Simultaneous Effects of Status and and Task Cues : Combining, Eliminating, or Buffering?" Social Psychology Quarterly 52: 327-335 . Sev'er, A . 1991 . "Women, Men, and Dominance in Small Groups : A Social Roles Assessment ." Canadian Journal of Sociology 16 : 265-280 . Skvoretz, J ., and T . J. Fararo. 1996 . "Status and Participation in Task Groups : A Dynamic Network Model." American Journal of Sociology 101 : 1366-1414 . Smith, B. L., B . L. Brown, W. J . Strong, and A. C . Rencher. 1975 . "Effects of Speech Rate on Personality Perception ." Language and Speech 18 : 145-152. Tuzlak, A . 1988. "Boomerang Effects : Status and Demeanor over Time ." Pp. 261-274 in Status Generalization : New Theory and Research, edited by M . Webster and M . Foschi . Stanford : Stanford University Press. Tuzlak, A . S. 1989 . "Joint Effects of Race and Confidence on Perceptions and Influence : Implications for Blacks in Decision-making Positions ." Canadian Ethnic Studies 21 : 120-126 . Tuzlak, A ., and J . C . Moore . 1984. "Status, Demeanor and Influence : an Empirical Reassessment ." Social Psychology Quarterly 47 :178-183 .
STRATEGIC DECISION MAKING
Frans N . Stokman, Marcel A .L.M . van Assen, Jelle van der Knoop, and Reinier C .H . van Oosten
ABSTRACT This paper introduces a methodology for strategic intervention in collective decision making . The methodology is based on (1) a decomposition of the problem into a few main controversial issues, (2) systematic interviews of subject area specialists to obtain a specification of the decision setting, consisting of a list of stakeholders with their capabilities, positions, and salience on each of the issues ; (3) computer simulation . The computer simulation models incorporate only the main processes through which differences in positions and salience are accommodated in binding decisions : management of meaning through the provision of convincing information, challenges, and exchanges . The methodology generates insights into the likely outcomes of the process, the amount of conflict involved, and the stability of the outcomes . These insights and the investigation of the effects of strategic moves provide major strategic advantages to the user . This is likely to lead to a better representation of the user's own position in the decision outcome and the creation of a broader political and social support behind the decision outcome .
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 131-153 . Copyright m 2000 by JAI Press Inc . All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 131
132
FRANS N. STOKMAN ET AL . INTRODUCTION'
Collective decision making is one of the most fundamental processes in society . People's long-term common interests often require binding decisions for their successful accomplishment . Whenever all people strive toward the same outcome there is no problem . They can simply turn the preferred outcome into a decision and act accordingly . Collective decision making becomes difficult when stakeholders take different positions and express different preferences with respect to the outcome . Then, the different positions have to be accommodated in one way or the other . The dynamics in the decision-making process result from the fact that each stakeholder, with different intensity and potential, attempts to realize his 2 position whereas only one outcome can be chosen . Small informal groups can often make decisions on the basis of informal rules and agreements . As soon as common interests become more complex and groups larger, collective decision making has to be institutionalized through the elaboration of generally accepted decision-making procedures . Such formal procedures can be found at all levels of society . They specify, among other things, which bodies have the authority to make the final decisions, how these bodies are composed and their members selected, and which stakeholders at what moment have to be heard or are otherwise involved in the decision making . In addition, rules specify procedures for appeal against decisions that are harmful or not made according the required procedures . In the social sciences, models for collective decision making have been developed since the early eighties that provide far-reaching insights into collective decision-making situations (among others, Bueno de Mesquita et al . 1985 ; Coleman 1990 ; Laumann et al . 1987 ; Stokman and Van den Bos 1992 ; Stokman and Van Oosten 1994 ; Torenvlied 1996 ; Konig 1997 ; Pappi and Henning 1998) . Game theoretical insights are combined with mathematical models and computer simulation to model essential collective decision-making processes . The models represent three processes that precede formal decision making and that affect the final positions of the stakeholders involved . First, position changes are sometimes . induced because stakeholders receive or provide new convincing information rather to take other positions (management of meaning) . Second, in other situations stakeholders feel challenged by others to change their positions because the losses incurred by losing such a challenge are larger than the losses incurred by defending their position . Finally, stakeholders may change their positions when they see possibilities to create win-win situations through exchanging (logrolling) . All models require a limited set of data obtained through interviews with subject area specialists . The models generate information on the outcome, the type of process, and the amount of conflict to be expected . The aim of the models is twofold . First, the models are used for the analysis of decision-making processes and for the prediction of decision outcomes without intervention . On the basis of a
Strategic Decision Making
133
large number of evaluation studies of mostly political decisions at the international, national, and local level (Bueno de Mesquita and Stokman 1994 ; Ray and Russett 1996 ; Stokman and Berveling 1998 ; Rojer 1999 ; Payne 1999), it can be concluded that the models are quite accurate . 3 Second, the models are particularly useful for intervention in decision making in order to optimize the utility of one stakeholder, to create sufficient support for a decision, or to arrive at a fair decision on the basis of mediation . These strategically oriented applications are mainly applications for large organizations and governmental agencies . They prove the usefulness of the models for obtaining direct strategic insights and for intervention in ongoing decision-making processes . The models depart from a systematic analysis of the decision-making situation which is useful in itself. Such a systematic approach involves at first a decomposition of the problem resulting in the specification of a limited number of main controversial issues to be solved . Subsequently, an analysis of all stakeholders is required, including an overview of their positions, capabilities, and salience on each of the issues . Next, different strategies have to be considered. Computer simulation models are particularly useful for evaluating these strategies . We will elaborate each of these elements .
THE DECOMPOSITION OF THE PROBLEM INTO CONTROVERSIAL ISSUES The first essential step in a strategic decision-making analysis is the specification of the problem at stake in terms of a limited number of issues on which decisions have to be made . Each issue can be seen as a major controversial point for decision . Decisions of the stakeholders on the specified set of issues should determine the contours of the chosen solution . Usually, one to five issues are sufficient, even in complicated situations, but incidentally up to 20 issues have been used in some applications . The requirement of the specification of a limited number of issues is in its own right a good exercise to distinguish main from subordinate points . Ill-defined specification at this stage implies a possible solution to something that has little impact on the actual problem . Misspecification of the issues is the main cause of the failures in model predictions . An important aid in the specification of issues is the requirement that at least the two extreme positions on each issue should be identified . Identification of the two extreme positions actually implies that an issue can be seen as unidimensional, a straight line on which different positions can be located . 4 Intermediate positions indicate more moderate positions, but also possible compromise outcomes . If extreme and possible intermediate positions cannot be ordered, the specification of the issues is wrong, for example, because more underlying issues are involved . In such cases it is recommended to go one step deeper and to identify the underlying dimensions .
134
FRANS N. STOKMAN ET AL .
If we, for example, aim to analyze the merger of two companies, typical issues are the premium to be paid for the other company above the market or shares value, the desired degree of integration of the two companies, the initial number of representatives of each company in the integrated board, the timing of the merger, and which of the two presidents will be nominated as the president of the merged company . The last issue is an example of a dichotomous issue without intermediate outcomes . Often, such issues are most difficult to solve, as no compromises are possible . Whenever possible, it is therefore advisable to integrate such issues with other issues, facilitating, for example, a solution through an exchange with other issues (e .g., the initial number of representatives in the board) . A decomposition of the problem also implies at least a provisional specification of the main stakeholders . Without such a specification it will be difficult to specify extreme and intermediate positions . Stakeholders can be individuals or organizations . Individuals usually represent organizations or hold important positions in organizations .
CAPABILITIES, POSITIONS, AND SALIENCE After specifying the issues, the stakeholders, and the different possible positions on the issues, the next step in a strategic decision analysis consists of the specification of three characteristics of each stakeholder in relation to each issue . These data are usually obtained in interviews with one or two experts who make estimates relating to all stakeholders . The experts should have a good overview of the whole decision-making setting . Numerical specifications are required in the models . An example of such a numerical specification is given in Table 1 . The example originates in a project carried out by a transition manager from the Dutch company W&S Transition and Interim Management . W&S was asked to reorganize a company in the Amsterdam harbor that was facing serious economic problems . The company, given the acronym ABC, had a strong ideological orientation and had to accept more projects on economic grounds in order to survive . Maintaining the present ideological orientation was highly controversial . Some stakeholders wanted it to be reduced, whereas others wanted its continuation or even strengthening . We specified the central issue of the ideological orientation as the percentage of projects that the company would be allowed to accept on ideological grounds after the reorganization . The second column of Table 1 gives the positions of the stakeholders on the issue . The range is between 0 percent for competitors to 100 percent for the trade unions . The transition manager, the chairman of the supervisory board, and the economically oriented faction in the board took the rather radical position of 10 percent . Several other intermediate positions were also taken .
Strategic Decision
Making
135
Table 1 . Example of a Specification of an Issue and the Capabilities, Positions and Saliences of the Stakeholders Issue : Ideological Orientation Capabilities
Position
Salience
0 .15 0 .15 0 .30 0 .30 0 .15 0 .15 0 .30 0 .20 0 .70 0 .40
70 10 40 80 80 90 30 70 100
0 .2 0 .3 0 .3 0 .4 0 .2 0 .3 0 .3 0 .4 0 .1 0 .1 0 .4
Ideological faction in the Supervisory Board Economically oriented faction in the Supervisory Board Managing director Deputy director Administrator Project leaders Managers of commercially oriented departments Managers of ideologically oriented departments Trade unions Municipality of Amsterdam Employee Board
0 .9 0 .2 0 .9 0 .2
Transition manager Accountant Chairman of the Supervisory Board Competitors
0 .60 0 .80 0 .10 1 .00 0 .10 Note:
80 50 10 50 10 0
Position : Percentage of projects with an ideological orientation .
The interests of the stakeholders are not only represented in the positions they take, but also in the degree to which they are interested in the issue . We denote this as the salience of the issue for the stakeholder . The salience indicates the willingness of the stakeholder to push his position in the decision making . If the issue is hardly related to essential interests of a stakeholder, he will hardly fight for an outcome close to his position and he is to be expected to compromise quickly . If the issues are related closely to his main interests, a stakeholder will put all available clout behind his position and he is unlikely to compromise quickly . In the table, salience is scored on a scale from 0 (not related to own interests) to 1 (the stakeholder is willing to go to the limit) . The transition manager was hired to transform the company into an economically viable one . As the success of his task depended strongly on his success on this issue, the issue was very salient to him . In other words, he had a strong interest in the outcome . The chairman of the supervisory board hired the transition manager and had committed himself to make the company economically viable . For him too, success on this issue was highly important . Failing would probably have cost him his chairmanship . The other stakeholders took other positions but were also less committed to them . In the literature and in practice it is often forgotten that the combination of position and salience determines the behavior of stakeholders . These combinations are generated by the incentive structures of stakeholders . If one of the two is overlooked (in practice often salience), serious miscalculations are inevitable . The third element is the capabilities of the stakeholders to co-determine the outcome. This refers to a potential, not the actual mobilization of the capabilities .
1 36
FRANS N . STOKMAN ET AL .
Formal discretional or voting power is an important capability to co-determine the outcome of decisions . Nevertheless, people with the authority to make the final decision do not do so in isolation without taking into consideration the interests of the other stakeholders . If they were to neglect the interests of others, their decisions would quickly provoke societal and political opposition, resulting in the undermining of their own authority and legitimacy . Apart from that, most decision makers lack the required expertise to decide themselves and have to rely heavily on experts and advisors who are often strongly committed themselves . In addition, decision makers often need the cooperation of others for the implementation of their decisions, for example for the required financial resources or for loyal implementation . Other capabilities, therefore, result from exclusive expertise ahd information, financial resources or the capability to mobilize a large number of people. Scaling capabilities therefore requires the addition of things that are difficult to compare . Nevertheless, experts are often able to provide such a scale . During the extraction procedure, a "1" is often assigned to the stakeholder with the largest capabilities . Subsequently, the capabilities of the others are related to the one with the highest capabilities and to the capabilities of each other . Additivity is assumed here . If, for example, two stakeholders form a coalition against a third, their joint capabilities are compared with those of the third to determine which of them is stronger . When a subject area specialist tries to construct such a scale, it is important to make many such comparisons, that is, to compare many opposing coalitions of different compositions and sizes . Capabilities and salience together determine the effective power of stakeholders . Salience can be interpreted as the fraction of capabilities that a stakeholder is
2.5 a
2 m
•
1
5
• capabilities effective power
1
05 a • u
0 O Position Figure 1 .
Capabilities and Effective Power on the Position Scale
Strategic Decision
Making
137
willing to mobilize to effectuate his position in the outcome of the decision . A graphic showing the distribution of capabilities and effective power over the positions often generates much insight in the decision-making setting . Figure 1 contains an example of such a graphic for the data in Table 1 . Two aspects become clear immediately : a large amount of capabilities was concentrated behind the 10 percent position and almost all of that potential was mobilized . The latter was not true on the other side of the continuum . There, only a small fraction of the capabilities was mobilized . This immediately leads to the conclusion that the transition manager (who had the position of 10 percent) had to avoid a strongly confrontational strategy because this would have had the danger of mobilizing a countervailing power . If that had happened in this example, it would also have resulted in a bipolar distribution of effective power over the continuum . Such issues are often difficult to resolve in contrast to issues where the power distribution is unimodal .
PROCESSES AND STRATEGIES The dynamics of decision making result mainly from the efforts of stakeholders to realize an outcome of the decision that is as close as possible to their own position . The first and most obvious target for these efforts are the positions of the other stakeholders : is it possible to move their positions toward one's own, thus building an effective coalition behind one's own position? Building such a coalition makes it more likely that final decision makers will shift their positions, resulting in a decision closer to one's own position . A characteristic of collective decision-making processes is that not only one stakeholder attempts to build support for his own position, but that they all do, thus provoking countervailing forces with the possibility that the coalition behind one's own position is not strengthened but weakened . An analysis of a particular strategy might even result in the insight that one's own position cannot be maintained whereas the aim was to build a strong coalition behind it . There are three main processes through which a stakeholder changes his position : he receives convincing information implying that another position reflects his incentive structure better (management of meaning) ; he feels more or less forced to change his position because others challenge his position ; or he is prepared to take another position in exchange for a favorable (for him) move by another stakeholder on another issue . In management of meaning and challenge processes, in principle at least, only one issue is involved, whereas in exchange more issues are always involved . We therefore consider management of meaning and challenge processes first . The three processes are also points of departure for individual strategies and we will therefore also consider them from this perspective in the next sections .
1 38
FRANS N . STOKMAN ET AL . Management of Meaning Processes and Strategies
In management of meaning processes convincing information plays a dominant role (Weick 1979 ; O'Reilly 1983 ; Bouwen 1993) . As stated above, the position and salience of a stakeholder are connected to his incentive structure . The more directly an issue is connected to the central higher ordered objectives of a stakeholder and the more an issue is seen as an important condition for their realization, the more salient the issue is to him . His position on the issue corresponds to the outcome of the decision that he sees as optimal for the realization of his objectives . It does not matter what his higher ordered objectives are or where they come from . They may be related to the goals of the organization he represents or they may be related to his personal goals, such as status and behavioral confirmation, or to a combination of these . His own perception of the salience of the issue and the best outcome (position) in terms of these higher ordered objectives is essential . New information can drastically change this perception of salience and best position only if the new information is seen as reliable and is accepted as relevant . Two conditions substantially increase the likelihood that this will happen and, consequently, determine the success of convincing information strategies . First, convincing new information is generally more easily accepted in earlier stages of the decision making than in the later ones . During the decision-making process, positions taken by the stakeholders tend to freeze . In the beginning, stakeholders often do not have very crystallized ideas about the connection between the issue and their objectives . They are relatively open to information that clarifies that connection . Second, a substantial amount of trust in the provider of the information increases the likelihood that information is accepted as relevant and reliable . Trust will be greater if the provider has proven to be reliable in the past and if the provider can be expected to experience future negative consequences of providing distorted or incomplete information . This "shadow of the future" (Axelrod 1984) is more effective if the provider of distorted information loses his reputation not only with respect to the recipient stakeholder but also with respect to others (Raub and Weesie 1990; Buskens 1999) . Trust will also be greater if the information is less related to central interests of the provider . These conditions for trust emerge more readily among like-minded stakeholders and among stakeholders who also meet each other in other contexts, than among stakeholders with conflicting interests . Stakeholders also tend to assign more weight to the opinion of powerful stakeholders, whereas powerful stakeholders tend to listen more to one another than to less powerful ones (Molm 1997 ; Stokman and Zeggelink 1996) . 5 In general, convincing information strategies do not work well or sufficiently in relation to strongly polarized issues (see Figure 1) and in situations with huge power differences . Misuse of trust strongly reduces the effectiveness of convincing information strategies in the future . In decision-making processes this should not only be a guideline for one's own behavior, but can be made unequivocally clear to
Strategic Decision Making
139
others, thus reducing their inclination to provide distorted or incomplete information . In the context of convincing information strategies it is important to take account of the fact that people tend to be myopic in two respects . First, short-term benefits and costs weigh stronger than long-term ones, otherwise nobody would smoke, nor would obligatory retirement arrangements be necessary (Lindenberg 1998) . Second, stakeholders tend to see small differences around their own position much sharper than differences among remote positions (Bauer at al . 1963) . This may result in strong trust crises in one's own coalition about differences of opinion that outsiders would classify as being of minor importance. Challenge Processes and Strategies
In challenge processes differences in power and salience play an important role . To the degree that the salience of the issue to oneself is lower and the power dominance of stakeholders who support other position is larger, one will be inclined to give up his own position . Unnecessary costs are saved by conceding a position on an issue that is only marginally related to one's own interests . In challenge processes power dominance relations are more important than arguments . The process is therefore represented in the form of a noncooperative game (Bueno de Mesquita et al . 1985 ; Bueno de Mesquita 1994) . A challenge is more likely to be successful to the degree that the salience of the other stakeholder is lower and the support for the other's position is lower relative to the support for one's own position. In the computer simulation these two aspects dominate the determination of which stakeholder will challenge which other stakeholder (see Figure 2) . Each stakeholder makes this choice in relation to each of the other stakeholders . Based on the challenges made, each stakeholder has a set of cards in his hands that represent the challenges made and received . If he received challenges, he has to draw the one that is best for him . The result is either conflict (if he made a challenge to the other as well) or a forced position change . These position changes create a new decision-making setting (iteration in the computer simulation model) . In that new setting the stakeholders repeat the choice process . This continues until none of the stakeholders move anymore (substantially) or until all stakeholders take the same position . The latter does not occur often but it does in the example of Table 1 . Table 2 shows how the decision making evolves on the issue of the ideological orientation of the company . The first column gives the original positions of the stakeholders as the subject area specialist provided them (see Table 1) . The second column shows that (in the computer simulation) some stakeholders had to adapt their position because of the challenges obtained . Almost all movements are in the direction of the 10 percent position . After the first round or iteration the support for that position increases substantially, resulting in a still stronger movement in that direction . In iteration four all stakeholders take that position . In reality,
1 40
FRANS N . STOKMAN ET AL .
consensus emerged around that position, notwithstanding the very controversial nature of the issue at the beginning . For challenge strategies to be successful at least three elements have to be considered explicitly . The first involves the choice of one's own position at the beginning of the decision-making process . Will a more extreme position result in a better outcome (closer to one's own position or an outcome with a larger amount of political and social support) or is it better to choose for a more moderate position? The same holds for the leverage a stakeholder shows to others . 6 Is it better to push with all available clout or will a less involved stance to better results? If decision-making processes were to evolve monotonically, a more extreme position and a higher leverage would always lead to a better result, but this is not the case . The main reason is that individuals behave differently in loss situations than in gain situations, both in individual decision making (e .g ., Kahneman and Tversky 1979) and in collective action in social dilemma situations (Raub and Snijders 1997 ; Van Assen 1998) . In loss situations individuals are more willing to accept risks, whereas they tend to be more risk averse in gain situations . If a stakeholder confronts his adversaries with a strong loss situation by taking an extreme position and showing a high leverage, his adversaries tend to become more risk seeking and resisting . The consequence may well be that he loses support for his position and that he has to accept a worse outcome . These effects are also incorporated in the simulation model and can be evaluated systematically . If, for example, the transition manager in the example of Table I had chosen for the position
Challenge Existing Policy
Do Not Challenge Existing Polic
No Change Policy
Source :
Policy Changes
Opponent Gives in
Bueno de Mesquita et al . 1985
Figure 2 .
The Challenge Process
Opponent Does Not Give in
141
Strategic Decision Making Table 2.
Example of Evolution of Challenge Process (Computer Simulation) Positions in iterations Iteration Iteration Iteration Iteration
Initial
1
2
3
4
70 10
10 16
40 80 80 90 30 70 100
10 80 35 90 10 70 100
10 10 10
10 10 10
10 10 10
80 50 10 50 10 0
35 10 10
10 10 77 10 10 100 10 10 10
10 10 10 10 10 40 10 10 10
10 10 10 10 10 12 10 10 10
10 10 2
10 10 10
10 10 10
10 10 10
Ideological faction in the Supervisory Board Economically oriented faction Supervisory Board Managing director Deputy director Administrator Project leaders Managers of commercially oriented depts . Managers of ideologically oriented depts . Trade unions Municipality of Amsterdam Employee Board Transition manager Accountant Chairman of the Supervisory Board Competitors
of 0 percent, the predicted outcome would still be 10 percent . However, unanimity would then only have been reached after six iterations with a larger amount of conflict . This would have also resulted in a lower prestige for the transition manager, as the computer simulation shows he would have had to move from 0 to 10 percent in the fifth iteration . In addition to an explicit reflection on one's own position and leverage, an explicit evaluation of the likelihood of success of challenges is recommended . If a stakeholder takes an extreme minority position, his own chances of successful challenges are likely underestimated (resulting in no or less challenges) for the same reason as above : there is a tendency to overestimate the risks stakeholders close to the expected outcome are likely to take . As they are in a gain situation, stakeholders with positions close to the expected outcome are reluctant to make challenges and are an easier target than stakeholders with extreme minority positions expect . The simulation model provides insight into such likely misperceptions of stakeholders and their effect on the outcome of the decision . Repeatedly, these misperceptions have been shown to exist in reality and their analysis has increased success rates considerably (Ray and Russett 1996) . Exchange Processes and Strategies In exchange processes contrasting interests play a dominant role . Contrasting interests manifest themselves in a combination of fundamental differences in positions and salience over different issues . Whereas management of meaning
1 42
FRANS N . STOKMAN ET AL . Table 3 .
Position Exchange Possibilities Issue 2 Left
Issue 1
Right
Left
Right
strategies are effective among like-minded stakeholders, exchanges of positions are most profitable between stakeholders who have (1) opposing positions on the issues and (2) very different patterns of salience . The latter means that one stakeholder is mainly interested in one issue, whereas the other issue is strongly related to higher objectives of the other stakeholder . The result of a position exchange between two stakeholders is that they shift their voting position in the direction of the other on the issue that is relatively more salient for the other. In this way they create a win-win situation . Table 3 describes exchange possibilities in terms of positions held by the stakeholders . Exchange possibilities exist between stakeholders who hold opposing positions on both issues, that is, are located at different sides of the expected outcome on both issues. From this perspective we distinguish four groups of stakeholders . Stakeholders in group A are located on the left side of the expected outcome on both issues, stakeholders in group D on the right side . They have opposing interests on both issues and are therefore important potential exchange partners . The same holds for the groups B and C . As A and B have the same position on the first issue, they cannot exchange . A and C cannot exchange as they have the same position on the second issue . Similar arguments hold for the groups C and D, and B and D . Stakeholders from two groups with opposing positions can profit from position exchange if the relative salience of the two issues for each of them is different (Stokman and Van Oosten 1994) . A position exchange is then profitable for both, but has also important side effects for others . This can be seen clearly in Figure 3 . Assume a stakeholder from group D attaches relatively more salience to issue 1 than to issue 2 if we compare his saliences with those of a stakeholder in group A. Then issue 1 is D's demand issue and A's supply issue . Position exchange between A and D implies that A is willing to shift his position on issue 1 in the direction of D, whereas D does the same on issue 2 . If they do, they both shift away from B in the direction of C on both issues . B is thus punished doubly and C rewarded doubly, while none of the two is engaged in the exchange . If issue 1 would have been A's demand issue, C would have been punished twice and B rewarded twice .
Strategic Decision Making
143
Exchanges can also be threatening for internal group cohesion . Threats emerge when stakeholders in a group differ in their prioritization of the issues . We consider again two potential exchange groups, for example A and D . Assume that there are two stakeholders in group A, A 1 and A2 (see Figure 4) . Assume also that the salience of issue 2 for A 1 relative to issue 1 is higher than that for the stakeholders in group D, while the reverse is true for A 2 . Then D can split group A . For A 1 , issue 1 is the supply issue on which he is prepared to shift his position in the direction of D . In contrast, A 2 wants to maintain his position on issue 1 and is prepared to shift his position on issue 2 in the direction of D . If D were to exchange with both, the effect would be that D shifts on both issues in the direction of A, and that A 1 and A2 differ in their positions on both issues (see Figure 4) . It can be shown that D creates a prisoner's dilemma for A 1 and A2 where both A 1 and A2 are better off not exchanging at all (Van Assen et al . forthcoming) . The representation of exchanges used in our models is fundamentally different from the representation used in most social exchange theory literature . The representation of exchanges we use is similar to that used by Coleman (e .g ., 1972, 1990) who also represents both actors' interests in goods and the goods actors possess . In network exchange theory the division of a common resource pool (e.g ., Bienenstock and Bonacich 1992 ; Cook and Yamagishi 1992 ; Friedkin 1992 ; Markovsky, Willer, and Patton 1988 ; Skvoretz and Willer 1993) is used to represent exchanges . Van Assen (forthcoming) demonstrates that the often-used division of a common resource pool is generally not a theoretically valid representation of exchanges . All solutions proposed for the exchange rate in the literature can be applied to both our representation and the representation in terms of the division of a common resource pool . Stokman and Van Oosten (1994) use an equal utility gain for both exchange partners . This has the advantage that exchanges have the same utility for both partners and can be handled in order of attractiveness to both . The disadvantage is that it involves an intersubjective comparison of utility, which is theoretically unattractive . For our representation of exchanges two solutions of the exchange rate have been derived that are independent of the utility scale : the Nash solution (Achterkamp 1999 ; Van Assen forthcoming), and the Raiffa-Kalai-Smorodinsky (RKS) solution (Van Assen forthcoming) . There is a strong link between our work and network exchange theory because exchange-resistance solution used in network exchange theory (e .g ., Willer, Markovsky, and Patton 1988 ; Skvoretz and Willer 1993 ; Willer and Szmatka 1995) is also derived from the game theoretical RKS solution (Heckathorn 1980) . Van Oosten (forthcoming) bases the exchange rate on satisficing adaptation of random rates . A difference between our work and work in network exchange theory is that the latter until now only deals with exchanges of private goods . This is also the starting point for Coleman's models and his generalizations to public goods are not straightforward (Stokman and Van Oosten 1994) . We, however, investigate
1 44
FRANS N . STOKMAN ET AL .
exchanges of voting positions with externalities for other actors . A change in voting position affects all stakeholders in collective decision making . Interestingly, network effects on exchanges and their rates in social exchange theory are completely different from these effects in exchanges of goods with externalities to other actors (Van Assen et al . forthcoming). In exchange processes, three elements have to be considered explicitly when formulating one's own stance . The first concerns the selection of the issues one wants to include in the exchange process . Of course, one cannot always determine this alone, but there are many situations in which this is possible, for example, through the order in which different issues are negotiated . The second is the change one incorporates deliberately into one's own positions . Change will in general be incorporated in the less salient issues and is designed to facilitate concessions during an exchange . One should of course realize that extreme positions could provoke extremity on the other side, which easily nullifies the positive effect by resulting in more conflict and tension . The third element concerns one's prioritization of the issues, the distribution of the leverage over the issues that one shows . Here too a certain balance is needed . If one shows too much leverage on highly salient issues, one has to give in a lot on the other issues to obtain a position shift by the other stakeholders (it is generally known that in social relations, the person most interested in the relation tends to be exploited (Blau 1964) . If one does not show enough leverage on highly salient issues, one's own position and salience may well not be discerned by others, giving them an opportunity to move
Issue I
A}
rte
C D
B 01
Issue 2 A
D
-4
B
C 02
Figure 3 .
Effects of Exchanges for Third Stakeholders
I
145
Strategic Decision Making
Issue 1 (q1
~
01
Issue 2 A1
D
-.4
D
-0 1
1
02
After two exchanges both A t and A 2 have changed their position . Figure 4 .
Effects of Differences in Prioritization within Groups
the issue aside and to maintain the status quo . If one shows too quickly that one is not really interested in less salient issues, the proposal to shift one's own position on these issues may well not be seen as a serious concession that justifies a move on another issue by the other stakeholder . An Example of a Combined Strategy
Table 4 contains an example of how different strategies can be combined to determine which issues should be included in the exchange process in order to obtain an optimal outcome . The example is derived from an application in the context of Dutch labor negotiations . The main issue concerned a fundamental change in social benefit rights . The data were collected just before the start of the negotiations . In the row "Position" the positions of the client at the start of the negotiations are given . The client aimed at an obligatory start of the new system for all employees younger than a certain age (position 100) . The other stakeholders aimed at an obligatory start only for new employees (position 70) or no new system at all (position 0 ; status quo) . The positions 70 or 0 would imply considerable delay or no change at all . A second important issue in the new regulation concerned a certain degree of freedom for the employees to adapt the new system to their own wishes (in Table 4 denoted "Introduction of Choice Elements") . The client was for a large amount of freedom (position 100), while the other parties
146
FRANS N . STOKMAN ET AL .
Table 4.
Effects of Different Strategies in Labor Negotiations
Position Outcome before Exchange, No Optimization Challenge at Main Issue, Rest through Exchange Best Exchange on First Three Issues Exchange without Alternative Exchange Issue Exchange without Choice All Issues Included in Exchange Notes:
Alternative Introduction Exchange Of Choice Issue Elements 0 100
Main Issue 100
Guarantee 60
Exchange Issue 50
40
75
70
100
70
70
70,75
70
50
70,100
100
63,75
70
Excluded
100
100 100
68,75 70,75
70 70
Excluded 40
81,100 100
100
70,75
70
40
86
Not included in exchange solution . Italics : Acceptance by unanimity . Normal : majority, including the largest stakeholder . Double number : Majority for first, excluding the largest stakeholder . Bold :
wanted the freedom to be limited strongly (position 0) . A third important issue concerned guarantees for a minimum level of the benefits (the higher the position, the higher the guarantee) . A fourth issue concerned the level of another social benefit, in the table denoted "Exchange Issue ." The client introduced this issue explicitly as his supply issue and chose to adopt a low position initially that could be changed during the negotiations . An external advisor from an organization with a much experience in this subject area advised to include another issue in the exchange process, denoted "Alternative Exchange Issue" in Table 4 . This would have been very risky, as any concession on this issue would have been very expensive for the client . Moreover, the issue is normally dealt with in another negotiation context . The client's position was 0 (no change) against position 100 supported by all other stakeholders (resulting in extra benefits) . The client aimed at an outcome of the negotiation process that was not only close to his positions but was broadly supported as well . The row "Outcome Before Exchange, No Optimization" contains the outcomes predicted by the computer simulations when all issues are dealt with in isolation . These are the predicted outcomes on the basis of the aforementioned challenge strategy . They are obtained in different iterations without optimization aiming at outcomes closer to the positions of the client or at broader support . The predicted outcome on the main issue implies no change in the system or only in the long run . The outcomes on the other issues are also far from the preferred positions of the client. Under this scenario, the best course of action for the client would be to call a halt to the decision-making process immediately .
Strategic Decision Making
147
The row "Challenge at Main Issue, Rest through Exchange" gives the outcomes with an optimal challenge strategy on the main issue combined with an exchange process over all remaining issues . With optimization we were able to arrive at a computer prediction of 70 for the main issue, corresponding to implementation for all new employees . The optimization consisted of a carefully selected leverage the client should show in combination with certain challenges the client would likely miss (and were indeed surprising for him) . The exchange outcomes on the other four issues are not very promising . None of the predictions corresponds with his position . He has to give up a lot on the other issues in return for a better result on the Alternative Exchange Issue that has a high salience for him because of the large costs involved . Even then, he has to make a huge concession on that issue . The next row, "Best Exchange on First Three Issues," shows the results of a strategy that produces broadly supported outcomes close to the positions of the client . In this solution the Alternative Exchange Issue is entirely left out of the decision-making process . In isolation from the other issues, the issue cannot be solved . The best solution would be to exclude the issue entirely from the decision making . The main argument for its exclusion is the other negotiation platform to which it belongs . Our analysis therefore showed that the advice of the external advisor to include this issue was really very disadvantageous for the client . We advised that the decision on the issue Choice Elements should be made after negotiations on the first three issues had taken place . Choice Elements is the only nonfinancial issue . Moreover, the outcomes on the first three issues have to be known before one can make sensible decisions on this issue . Using an optimized challenge strategy the issue could be resolved according to the position of the client. By using an exchange strategy, broadly supported outcomes close to the positions of the client were obtained on the first three issues . In the last rows of the table the results are shown of alternative strategies in which more issues are included in the exchange . All these strategies produce worse results than the strategy "Best Exchange on First Three Issues ." Therefore, we recommended that strategy and the client implemented it successfully . This example demonstrates the power and fruitfulness of our approach .
CHANGING THE DECISION SETTING The management of meaning, challenge, and exchange strategies take a decision setting as given . The setting corresponds to the specification of the issue(s) and the stakeholders with their capabilities, positions, and salience . If none of the strategies is effective and the issues are essential to obtain higher ordered objectives, a stakeholder can deliberate on whether the setting itself could be changed for better goal attainment . Stakeholders are inclined to pose this question more forcefully when they, time and time again, do not succeed in obtaining their objectives or when the decision-making process is blocked repeatedly by funda-
148
FRANS N. STOKMAN ET AL .
mental controversies . The approach presented above focuses directly on how to realize such a change in the decision setting . As the stakeholders with their power, positions, and salience determine the decision-making setting, strategies to change the decision setting can best be evaluated on their likely effects on the distribution of these three variables . The combination of position and salience of the stakeholders is connected with the incentive structures of the stakeholders . Changing the incentive structures is consequently the most important point of departure to obtaining fundamental changes in position and salience of certain stakeholders . Assume, for example, that the cooperation of farmers is essential for the success of an environmental policy concerning the disposal of manure, and that they are not prepared to cooperate freely or to accept certain policy measures . Their position and salience can then be influenced by a tax system that shifts their short-term economic interests in the direction of a more environment-friendly way of farming . This will lead to another stance of the farmers on issues related to manure policy (Baarda 1999) . An important part of the power distribution between stakeholders is related to institutional arrangements . Long-lasting deprivation of certain stakeholders often results in a demand for institutional change, for example, through changes in the composition of bodies and advisory committees, changes in competencies between bodies, extension or reduction of possibilities for appeal . Changes in institutional arrangements and customs are therefore the most important ways to change the power distribution among stakeholders . In addition, other, more informal capabilities can be increased or diminished . One can think of alliances, takeovers, or even mergers that can shift the power balance considerably .
CONCLUSIONS We have demonstrated that far-reaching insights into the decision-making process can be obtained from a correct problem decomposition, a decomposition resulting in a few main controversial issues, and a proper specification of the decision setting (stakeholders with their capabilities, positions, and salience) . These insights concern the processes and the likely outcomes of the process, but also the amount of conflict involved and the stability of the outcomes . These insights are obtained by combining a systematic decomposition of the problem into main issues with systematic interviews of subject area specialists and computer simulation . In these computer simulation models not all aspects of the decision-making process are represented, but only the main processes through which differences in positions and saliences are accommodated in binding decisions . In our view, three main processes are at stake : management of meaning through the provision of convincing information, challenges, and exchanges . In the provision of convincing information, trust and credibility play a dominant role . These conditions prevail among stakeholders with rather similar positions, between stakeholders with bridgeable
Strategic Decision Making
149
power differences, and in situations where the positions are not yet fixed and still have to be formed . In contrast, in challenge strategies stakeholders purposively exploit power differences to build coalitions . In exchange processes large differences in interests prevail, not only in terms of extreme opposing positions but also in terms of the priority rankings of the issues . Important strategic advantages can be gained from the insights generated by such an analysis . They can be used to obtain a better representation of one's own position in the decision outcome, and also to broaden the political and social support behind the decision outcome . With respect to challenge strategies, the effects of increasing or reducing leverage and of taking a more extreme or moderate position can be investigated . Moreover, warnings against often occurring misperceptions are generated, misperceptions resulting from differences between stakeholders' attitudes toward risks that are often neglected . For exchange strategies, the effects of linking or excluding issues, of differences in prioritization, and of built-in change can be investigated . These are fundamental new insights in collective decision-making processes that have been generated by the social sciences since the beginning of the eighties . This has resulted in a shift of attention from questions about power differences to differences in the effects of power differences . These effects are context dependent . It is the combination of the power distribution over positions and the differences in leverage of the stakeholders that co-determines the setting . It is this combination that conditions the effects of power differences (Mokken et al . 1998) . The approach presented above has passed the experimental phase . The team of scholars around Bueno de Mesquita and the Dutch group analyzed more than 6,000 issues . In the United States the first applications were related to American foreign policy, but gradually the emphasis has switched toward business applications . In the Netherlands the method has been applied for several ministries, large municipalities, and large companies for the analysis of complicated and important issues . Time and time again the clients indicated that they obtained many new insights through the approach and that they were able to realize their objectives more than they expected to do . Many clients returned for advice on other problems . Important scientific questions remain . Within the domain of collective decision making a further analysis of the three processes continues . The conditions under which each process is dominant is one of the main questions to be answered (see also Achterkamp 1999) . This is of particular importance because some of these processes are based on cooperative strategies, whereas others are based on conflictual strategies . Under what conditions do we need to be prepared for conflict strategies and what macro effects do such conflictual strategies have? Do they result in other and worse outcomes from the perspective of social welfare? Do noncooperative strategies lead to longer and more difficult decision-making processes? Is it possible and desirable to add complexity to the models? How do these models relate to other models, such as coalition and pure game theoretic models?
150
FRANS N . STOKMAN ET AL .
From the perspective of societal relevance, the conditions for broadly supported outcomes are of central importance . The approach described above enables much more sophisticated research to be conducted on this question, thus contributing to research with a view to the enhancement of social cohesion and solidary behavior . In addition, central questions remain concerning the relation between collective decision making and other processes . The models make intensive use of insights from game theory, social psychology, and economics . Nevertheless, further investigation of the relationship between these areas in general, and individual and collective decision making in particular could well result in important new insights . Such research could help to derive positions and salience on issues from the incentive structures of stakeholders . Research on the weight of the different power components in the overall power or capability index of a stakeholder could provide fundamental insights to be used in the design of institutional arrangements in society . All these questions belong to the central questions of the social sciences and cross several disciplinary boundaries . Answers to these questions will likely have huge societal impact and utility .
NOTES 1 . This paper is based on insights gained during the long-term development of the methodology described here, and applications of collective decision-making models . The roots of this development can be found in Mokken and Stokman (1976) . Part of the methodology is based on a model developed by Bruce Bueno de Mesquita of Stanford University . The collaboration with him has been very inspiring and helped in developing our own contributions . Many insights originate from scientific applications, mainly within the context of PhD projects in the Dutch Interuniversity Research Institute and Graduate School ICS . Commercial applications of the methodology by DECIDE by helped significantly in the systematic analysis and testing of the effectiveness of strategic moves. DECIDE by is a company associated with the University of Groningen and the ICS . We thank Robert Thomson for correcting the English . 2 . Wherever we use the male form, we also imply the female one . 3 . A good illustration of the accuracy of the models was given in 1996 . At the start of the labor negotiations in the Dutch metal industry (July 1996) Maurice Rojer and the first author collected data on 16 controversial issues and publicly announced that we had given our predictions in a sealed envelope to a notary . At the end of the negotiations in September we opened the envelope at a press conference. One issue was held in study . Of the other 15 issues we predicted 13 correctly according to sharp criteria (87%) . Among these 13 were exact predictions of the salary increase and the changes in the retirement arrangements, two of the most controversial issues. 4 . All models discussed in this paper assume that the issues are unidimensional and that the stakeholders have single-peaked preference functions . 5 . In our management of meaning model, three parameters are estimated for policy networks . The first parameter is related to the overall density of influence relations, the second to the difficulty to surmount power differences in establishing influence relations, and the third to the importance of similarity of positions on issues in establishing influence relations (Van Assen and Stokman forthcoming) . If no network data are available (only the capability, position, and salience scores of the stakeholders on the issues), the model can be used to estimate the network effects and the effects on the outcomes of the issues of different values of the parameters.
151
Strategic Decision Making
6. The term leverage is used to refer to the strategically chosen salience in decision-making processes. For a model that optimizes the leverage over a set of issues, see Stokman and Stokman (1995) . 7 . The exchange process as described and modeled is an example of a cooperative game model. The analysis of win-sets is an example of a noncooperative game through which stakeholders can create win-win situations . Win-sets are solely based on an analysis of the positions of the stakeholders . They do not take salience into account .
REFERENCES Achterkamp, M. 1999 . Influence Strategies and Models in Collective decision Making . A Comparison of Two Models. Amsterdam : Thela Thesis . Axelrod, R. 1984 . The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books . Baarda, C . 1999 . Politieke Besluiten en Boerenbeslissingen . Her draagvlak van het Mestbeleid tot 2000. Amsterdam : Thela Thesis . Bauer, R . A ., I . de Sola Pool, and L. A . Dexter. 1963 . American Business & Public Policy . The Politics of Foreign Trade. Chicago : Aldine Atherton . Blau, P. M . 1964 . Exchange and Power in Social Life. New Brunswick, NJ : Transaction Publishers . Bienenstock, E . J ., and P . Bonachich. 1992 . "The Core as a Solution to Exclusionary Networks ." Social Networks 14 : 231-243. Bouwen, R . 1993 . "Organizational Innovation as a Social Construction : Managing Meaning in Multiple Realities ." Pp . 133-49 in Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Organization Studies, edited by S . Lindenberg and H . Schreuder . Oxford : Pergamon Press. Bueno de Mesquita, B . 1994 . "Political Forecasting : An Expected Utility Method ." Pp . 71-104 in European Community Decision Making . Models, Comparisons, and Applications, edited by B . Bueno de Mesquita and F .N. Stokman . New Haven, CT: Yale University Press . Bueno de Mesquita, B ., D . Newman, and A. Rabushka. 1985 . Forecasting Political Events, The Future of Hong Kong. New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Bueno de Mesquita, B ., and F . N. Stokman, eds . 1994. European Community Decision Making. Models, Comparisons, and Applications. New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Buskens, V . 1999 . Social Networks and Trust. Amsterdam : Thela Thesis . Coleman, J . S . 1972 . "Systems of Social Exchange ." Journal of Mathematical Sociology 2 : 145-163 . Coleman, J. S . 1990. Foundations of Social Theory. Cambridge, MA : The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press . Cook, K. S ., and T . Yamagishi. 1992 . "Power in Exchange Networks : A Power-dependence Formulation ." Social Networks 14 : 245-265 . Friedkin, N . E . 1992. "An Expected Value Model of Social Power : Predictions for Selected Exchange Networks." Social Networks 14 : 213-229. Heckathorn, D . D . 1980 . "A Unified Model for Bargaining and Conflict ." Behavioral Science 25 : 261-284 . Kahneman, D ., and A . Tversky. 1979 . "Prospect Theory : An Analysis of Decision Under Risk." Econometrica 47 : 263-291 . Konig, T. 1997 . Europa auf dent Weg zum Mehrheitssystem . Griinde and Konsequenzen nationaler and parlamentarischer Integration . Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag . Laumann, E . 0., D. Knoke, and Y .H. Kim . 1987 . "Event Outcomes ." Pp. 343-373 . in The Organizational State . Social Choice in National Policy Domains, edited by E. O . Laumann and D . Knoke. Madison : The university of Wisconsin Press . Lindenberg, S . 1998 . "Solidarity : Its Microfoundations and Macrodependence . A Framing Approach." Pp . 61-112 in The Problem of Solidarity. Theories and Models, edited by P. Doreian and T . Fararo . Gordon and Breach Publishers.
152
FRANS N. STOKMAN ET AL .
Markovksy, B ., D. Willer, and T . Patton 1988 . "Power Relations in Exchange Networks ." American Sociological Review 53 : 220-236. Mokken, R . J ., and F . N. Stokman . 1976 . "Power and Influence as Political Phenomena." Pp . 33-54 in Power and Political Theory, edited by B . Barry . London : John Wiley . Mokken, R . J ., D . Payne, F. N . Stokman, and F . W. Wasseur . 1998 . "Praferenzaggregation and Effektivmacht. Die Reform der EG-Strukturfonds fur Irland ." Pp . 344-362 in Europa der Burger? Voraussetzungen, Alternativen, Konsequenzen, edited by T. KSnig, E . Rieger, and H . Schmitt . Frankfurt : Campus Verlag . Molm, L . 1997 . Coercive Power in Social Exchange . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press . O'Reilly, C . A . 1983 . "The Use of Information in Organizational Decision Making : A Model and Some Propositions ." Research in Organizational Behavior 5 : 103-139 . Pappi, F . U ., and C . H. C . A . Henning . 1998 . "Policy Networks : More than a Metaphor?" Journal of Theoretical Politics 10 : 553-575 . Payne, D . 1999 . Policy Making in the European Union . An Analysis of the Impact of the Reform of the Structural Funds in Ireland . Amsterdam: Thela Thesis . Raub, W., and J. Weesie . 1990. "Reputation and Efficiency in Social Interactions : An Example of Network Effects." American Journal of Sociology 96: 626-654. Raub, W., and C . Snijders . 1997 . "Gains, Losses, and Cooperation in Social Dilemmas and Collective Action: The Effects of Risk Preferences ." Journal of Mathematical Sociology 22: 263-302. Ray, J ., and B . Russett . 1996 . "The Future as Arbiter of Theoretical Controversies : Predictions, Explanations and the End of the Cold War ." British Journal of Political Science 26 : 441-470 . Rojer, M . 1999 . "Collective Decision making Models Applied to Labour Negotiations in the Netherlands : A Comparison between an Exchange Model and a Conflict Model ." Rationality and Society 11 : 207-235 . Skvoretz, J ., and D . Willer 1993 . "Exclusion and Power : A Test of Four Theories of Power in Exchange Networks ." American Sociological Review 58: 801-818 . Stokman, F . N ., and J . M . M . Van den Bos . 1992 . "A Twostage Model of Policy Making : With an Empirical Test in the U.S . Energy Policy Domain ." Pp . 219-253 in The Political Consequences of Social Networks, Volume 4 of Research and Society, edited by G . Moore and J . A . Whitt. Greenwich, CT : JAI Press . Stokman, F . N ., and R . Van Oosten. 1994 . "The Exchange of Voting Positions : An Object-Oriented Model of Policy Networks ." Pp. 105-127 in European Community Decision Making . Models, Comparisons, and Applications, edited by B . Bueno de Mesquita and F . N. Stokman. New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Stokman, F . N., and J. V . Stokman . 1995 . "Strategic Control and Interests . Its Effects on Decision Outcomes ." Journal of Mathematical Sociology 20: 289-317 . Stokman, F . N., and E . P . H . Zeggelink. 1996. "Is Politics Power or Policy Oriented? A Comparative Analysis of Dynamic Access Models in Policy Networks ." Journal of Mathematical Sociology 21 : 77-111 . Stokman, F . N., and J . Berveling . 1998. "Dynamic Modeling of Policy Networks in Amsterdam ." Journal of Theoretical Politics 10 : 577-601 . Torenvlied, R. 1996 . "Political Control of Implementation Agencies . Effects of Political Consensus on Agency Compliance" Rationality and Society 8 : 25-56 . Van Assen, M. A. L . M . 1998 . "Effects of Individual Decision Theory Assumptions on Predictions of Cooperation in Social Dilemmas ." Journal of Mathematical Sociology 23 : 143-153 . Van Assen, M . A. L . M . Forthcoming. "Representation of Exchanges in Exchange Theory: Review and Critique ." Internal manuscript. Van Assen, M . A . L . M ., and F . N . Stokman . Forthcoming . "Assessing Power and Policy Orientation in Policy Networks ." Internal manuscript . Van Assen, M . A . L . M., F. N . Stokman, and D . Willer . Forthcoming . "Social Exchange Theory Applied to Exchanges of Goods with Externalities ." Internal manuscript.
Strategic Decision
Making
153
Weick, K. E. 1979 . The Social Psychology of Organizing . Reading, MA : Addison-Wesley . Willer, D ., and J . Szmatka 1993 . "Cross-national Experimental Investigations of Elementary Theory : Implications for the Generality of the Theory and the Autonomy of Social Structure ." Pp. 3781 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol . 10, edited by B . Markovsky and E. Lawler . Greenwich, CT : JAI Press .
THE NORMATIVE REGULATION OF POWER
Morris Zelditch and Henry A . Walker
ABSTRACT In most theories of authority, normative regulation is the price that power pays for legitimacy . But what are the mechanisms by which norms regulate power and under what conditions do they in fact constrain its use? In an experimental study of a three-level hierarchy of power and authority, we found that the internal constraint of conscience alone was not sufficient to constrain the abuse of power by authority : Where authority had something to gain, one in four Ss abused power out of selfinterest; where it had nothing to gain, one in three followed their own conscience rather than the situation's norms . But internal constraints are not the only constraints on the exercise of power by authority . The mechanisms of the normative regulation of power depend on the fact that the exercise of authority, at least in organizations, is a collective phenomenon . It is not simply a matter of a superior, A, exercising authority over a subordinate, B, but of multiple actors executing the directives of A in such a way that the behavior of B is in fact directed . The normative regulation of power depends on how norms regulate these other agents of power and how dependence on these other agents, in turn, controls the behavior of A .
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 155-178 . Copyright m 2000 by JAI Press Inc . All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 155
1 56
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
In the present paper we report the results of nine experiments, five of which investigate the use of power by A and four of which investigate conditions under which that behavior is or is not supported by superiors and peers of A and peers of B . The driving force of the normative regulation of power is the validity of the norms-where by validity we mean a collective consensus that observably governs, and is binding on, the behavior of the members of a group . In the first instance, the effect of validity is on authorization of the behavior of A, its support by superiors and peers of A, and its endorsement, its support by the peers of B . Expectations of authorization and endorsement, in turn, together with the direct effect of validity (i .e., of conformity) and validity's (social influence) effect on propriety, on A's own sense of what is right, are the mechanisms that constrain the abuse of power by A. To the extent that validity is what drives the superiors and peers of A and the peers of B, norms regulate the exercise of power . But we found that external constraints on the abuse of power by authority were themselves easily subject to abuse, especially by eccentric consciences . Under what conditions do norms actually regulate the use of power by authority? Our theory implies that (1) there must be substantial consensus with respect to the norms ; (2) A must actually be dependent on others for his or her power ; (3) the ties of these others to A must be dense ; and, especially important, (4) the ties among these others must themselves be dense. Only to the extent that agents of social control are themselves densely interconnected are the eccentricities of any one agent of control constrained and norms do in fact regulate the abuse of power by authority .
PROBLEM The Normative Regulation of Power
In Barnard (1938) and Weber ([1918] 1968), normative constraint is the price of legitimate power . In both theories, authority is a relation between A and B such that B is obligated to comply with A's directives . A's power to exact B's compliance is said to be "legitimate" if it is in accord with rule and felt to be right . In both Barnard and Weber it is legitimacy that empowers A : Without it, A is unable to mobilize the resources that provide authority with its power ; and, in any case, A has no warrant to expect B's compliance . With it, A expects B to voluntarily comply with A's directives, independent of B's preferences ; and A has the resources required to negatively sanction Bs who fail to comply . But legitimacy imposes constraints on the exercise of power : A has no right to expect B's compliance or to negatively sanction B's noncompliance with directives outside the scope of A's authority . This has always been a puzzling conception of authority because empowering A gives A control over resources that, once available, are available whether or not B's noncompliance is within the scope of A's authority . In Barnard, furthermore, A's judgment is the only judgment that really counts in deciding whether non-
The Normative Regulation of Power
1 57
compliance is or is not within the scope of A's authority . It is true that B also has some power over A : A depends on B for performance of a task valued by A . But B's power is necessarily less than A's . If the only judgment that matters is therefore A's, the only constraint on the illegitimate use of power by A is voluntary and is entirely internal to A . The Frailty of Internal Constraints on the Use of Power by Authority
But internal constraint is a frail protection against the illegitimate use of power by authority : In the first instance, self-interest may override it . In the first experiment we describe a subject (S) that controlled the agenda of a group's decision about whether or not, and how, to change the structure of a centralized network that unfairly under-rewarded everyone in the group except S . S was at the center of the network and was unfairly over-rewarded . The group had a legitimate right to change the structure of the network if a majority agreed, but almost half the Ss at the center of the network made illegitimate use of their control over the agenda to delay or prevent the majority from voting to change the structure of the network. Of this half, about half redressed inequity by other means . But half simply took the money and ran . Thus, one in four Ss allowed self-interest to simply override internal constraints on the abuse of their power . But even if self-interest does not directly override internal constraint, the individual beliefs on which internal constraint depends may be self-serving . In the experiment just described, many Ss resisted change simply because a centralized network was the most efficient way to perform a valued, collective task and its effectiveness made it legitimate (cf. Lipset 1959) . But post-session questionnaires found that belief in the legitimacy of the centralized network by Ss at its center increased as Ss' gain from it increased . Some part of the effect of the legitimacy of the wheel was therefore self-serving . Even if the beliefs on which internal constraint depends are not self-serving, they may differ from the accepted norms of the group, either because of dissensus or because norms, values, and beliefs are open to interpretation even if there is consensus . In a later experiment described below, S, assisting the experimenter (E) in E's office, was responsible for final decisions about how to divide team earnings . Where individual beliefs in equity were inconsistent with an equality norm backed by E, fully a third of the Ss followed their own conscience rather than the norms of the experiment (Walker et al . 1997) . How and Under What Conditions do Norms Regulate Power?
Thus, internal constraint is not sufficient to constrain the illegitimate exercise of power by authority . In Weber, the solution to this problem lies in the fact that legitimacy is external as well as internal to A . To the extent that a moral order is "valid" it is not only "exemplary," it is "binding" (Weber [1918]1968, p . 31) . It is
1 58
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A. WALKER
made "binding" on A by embedding it in a system of social controls which makes compliance expedient even if A does not share the system's norms . But even in Weber the mechanisms that actually constrain the use of power by authority are unclear . The present paper therefore addresses two questions : First, if there is normative regulation of power, what are its mechanisms? Second, equally important, under what conditions do they constrain the illegitimate use of power by authority?
THEORY
Scope of the Theory
With some elaboration, Dornbusch and Scott's theory of authority (1975) is sufficient to answer the first question (see also Walker and Zelditch 1993 ; Zelditch and Walker 1984) . This theory applies to multilevel groups oriented to goals that can be transformed into divided tasks . These tasks are divided among positions that can be evaluated for performance . In particular, in this theory there is a division of labor in authority : Rights to make final decisions, allocate tasks, direct performance, assess performance, allocate sanctions, and execute sanctions are divided among different positions . Hence, the exercise of authority is a collective rather than individual act . Because of the division of labor in authority, authority depends on the cooperation of others both for resources and for support . A control attempt or an attempt to positively or negatively sanction a subordinate is powerless if these other positions do not support it by carrying out their tasks at authority's command . The theory is driven by evaluation processes : In particular, because authority depends on the cooperation of others, it is accountable to others (cf. Tetlock 1992) . Accountability is effective to the extent that (1) members of the group care about its positive and negative sanctions, (2) the sanctions depend on evaluations, and (3) evaluations depend on performance . In Dornbusch and Scott, task structures are therefore also power structures . Positions are given differential access to the sanctions that control the performance of other positions . But, because of the division of labor in authority, positions of authority are as accountable as any other positions in an organization . It is fundamental to the theory's model of authority that some control others but are themselves subjected to control . Basic Concepts of the Theory
Dornbusch and Scott's theory makes three distinctions that will matter to our analysis of the normative regulation of power . The first is between individual and collective sources of legitimacy, hence between propriety, which is a matter of
The Normative Regulation of Power
1 59
individual belief, and validity, which is a matter of collective consensus . A norm, value, belief, practice, or procedure is "proper" if individual p believes it is right . It is "valid" if it observably governs the behavior of and is binding on members of a group . Thus, from the point of view of an individual actor p, validity in Dornbusch and Scott, following Weber, is an object of orientation ; it is how others will act if p does or does not violate the norms, values, beliefs, practices, or procedures of the group . Validity is difficult to operationalize except in rational legal systems with written statutes made by established procedures . Thus, equality of outcomes is made valid in one experiment described below by incorporating it into written rules to be followed by Ss, playing the role of E's assistant, who are responsible for final decisions allocating rewards . Written codes aside, validity is essentially actual, or from the perspective of any individual actor, perceived consensus . But what is important is the distinction the theory makes between individual belief and an externally given normative order, An important property of the normative order this presupposes, and hence validity, is that it is enduring : In any particular encounter it is pre-given ; between encounters it is trans-situational . A second distinction made by Dornbusch and Scott is between sources of legitimacy and sources of support for it-where "support" includes both execution of directives and positive sanctions for compliance or negative sanctions for noncompliance . Given the second distinction, the third simply stratifies sources of support : Support by the peers and/or superiors of A is authorization ; support by peers of B is endorsement. (We will indicate peers or superiors of A by A' and peers of B by B' .) For example, a superior of A, A', authorizes a directive of A if A' sanctions B for noncompliance with it ; a peer of B, B', dis-endorses it if B' allies with B in resisting it. Mechanisms Constraining the Use of Power by Authority Thus, the theory has four mechanisms that regulate the exercise of power by authority-propriety, validity, authorization, and endorsement-three of which are external to the actor . The mechanism that drives the theory is validity . The theory describes the normative regulation of power simply by assuming that, first, independent of either individual preferences or propriety, validity causes authorization by A' and endorsement by B' of acts by A that are valid, but de-authorization by A' and dis-endorsement by B' of acts by A that are outside the scope of authority's power. Second, again independent of individual preferences or propriety, it assumes that embedding validity in a system of social controls external to A causes A to exercise power when it is valid but deters A from exercising power when it is not . The effect of validity, in turn, is driven by the presupposition of consensus . Following Weber, the theory assumes that a valid social order is (or is nearly) consensual (Zelditch and Floyd 1998) . Hence, individual actors presuppose
1 60
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
consensus with respect to it in any particular situation : If an actor p (p = A, B, A', or B') accepts a norm, value, belief, practice, or procedure e l as valid in the situation, p expects any other actor in the situation to accept e as valid unless and until p learns otherwise . Given the presupposition of consensus, the validity of norms, values, beliefs, practices, and procedures has four kinds of effect on the conduct of A (and, in particular, on A's use of power) . It has a direct effect, either because custom and law are respected or because "that's the way things are ." But it also has three indirect effects . One indirect effect is through propriety . Perceived consensus has a social-influence effect on individual beliefs : If p believes others believe e, p is more likely to believe e . Individual beliefs cause compliance with the norms regulating the use of power by authority . But propriety and validity also interact in such a way that the effect of propriety on A's conduct is stronger when it is backed by validity. A is more likely to act on his or her conscience when it is backed by the norms of the group . This follows from the scope of the theory : Decisions that affect group outcomes, commit group resources, or enforce group norms have consequences for others. A can be held to account for them, hence owes others a justification for them (Tetlock 1992 ; Zelditch and Floyd 1998). Where a valid norm, value, belief, practice, or procedure exists, behavior in accord with it justifies A's actions . But the presupposition of consensus also creates expectations of authorization, which creates a second indirect effect of validity on the conduct of p . As in Weber, a valid normative order is prescriptive . 2 If an actor p presupposes consensus with respect to e, p not only expects others to accept e, p also expects them to support e . If p acts in accord with e, p expects either positive sanctions for compliance, or at least that others do nothing that contradicts e . If p does not act in accord with e, p expects negative sanctions for noncompliance . To the extent that A is accountable to others, A is therefore constrained to comply with e by expectations of support for e whether or not A personally believes in it . Hence expectations of authorization will constrain the use of power by A . The final indirect effect of validity is through expectations of endorsement . There will be some difference between the effects of the two kinds of support, because they differ both in source and object . The difference in source of support (A' vs . B') is a difference in power . The difference in object of support (A vs . B) is that peers of A directly sanction A, while peers of B support A by negatively sanctioning noncompliance by B, which from the point of view of A is a less direct effect . Together, these differences make authorization a more powerful constraint than endorsement . Nevertheless, to the extent that A depends on B for performance of a task on which A's own evaluations depend, expectations of endorsement will also constrain the use of power by A .
The Normative Regulation of Power
1 61
Normative Regulation of the Mechanisms Constraining the Use of Power by Authority
Thus, propriety is neither necessary nor sufficient for validity to constrain the behavior of A . The theory embeds norms in a system of social controls that it assumes is, in turn, driven by validity . Propriety, of course, may also affect authorization and endorsement . But the theory assumes that validity affects authorization and endorsement independent of propriety (and, of course, of preferences) . It is the fact that validity drives the system of social controls that explains the normative regulation of power . In the first instance, independent of either preferences or propriety, validity causes authorization of acts that are valid, de-authorization of acts that are not . The peers and superiors of A are more likely to support a directive by A if it is valid, less likely to support it if it is invalid . Furthermore, the theory's conception of social control implies that validity and propriety again interact in such a way that the effect of propriety on authorization is stronger when validity is present than when it is absent-that is, that A' is more likely to actually sanction A and/ or execute the directives of A if the personal beliefs of A' are backed by group consensus . Similarly, independent of either preferences or propriety, validity causes endorsement of acts that are valid, dis-endorsement of acts that are not . The peers of B are more likely to support a directive by A if it is valid ; B' either withholds support of B if B does not comply or actually sanctions B negatively for noncompliance . If the conduct of A is invalid, B' is less likely to support A and more likely to support B ; B' may positively sanction B, or even ally with B, if B does not comply. Furthermore, validity and propriety will interact such that the effect of propriety on endorsement is stronger if validity is present than if it is absentB', like A', is more likely to act on individual beliefs if they are backed by consensus .
METHOD Standardized Experimental Setting
Eight of the nine experiments described in the present paper were carried out in a standardized experimental setting. Task
Five participants solved a series of 10 problems, each of which required them to construct a five-point, multi-arc graph . Each participant had some but no-one had all of the information required to solve the problem . Each trial of the experi-
1 62
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
ment therefore required participants to coordinate information distributed to them at the beginning of each problem (from Bavelas 1950) . A trial ended when each participant submitted a solution to E . Interaction Conditions Participants worked in separate rooms, communicating by written messages only . Communication was further restricted in such a way that messages could pass from a participant only to those members of the team linked to the participant by open channels of communication and all networks were initially centralized, forming a "wheel" : A central position (C) could communicate directly with all others but the four peripheral positions (P) could communicate only with or through C (also from Bavelas 1950) . Incentives Teams earned a reward for each correct solution. Team earnings were divided equally among members . However, on each trial of the experiment there was also a bonus for the person who first submitted a correct solution . The value of the bonus on each trial was equal to the total value of a team's earnings on any given trial had each member of the team obtained the correct solution . In a centralized network, only C ever won the bonus . This was uniformly seen by all participants as unfair and the inequity was typically blamed on centralization of the network . To underline the inequity, participants were told that all of them were alike and had been allocated to positions in the network purely by chance . Dependent Variable Participants were allowed to change the structure of the network at any trial of the experiment by adding or subtracting channels of communication if a majority agreed (MacKenzie 1976) . An all-all network, for example, would equalize opportunity to win the bonus . There was a small fee for adding channels . Therefore, to alter channels of communication, a member of the group had to make a motion specifying the proposed changes and the motion had to be seconded by another member of the group . If the motion were seconded, an election would be held to determine if a majority agreed . E never actually held an election : In previously published experiments in this setting all Ss were in peripheral positions of the network and the dependent variable of the experiment was a change-response by an S in the P position, that is, a motion by P, addressed to P', to change the structure of the network . Ss were stopped, interviewed, and debriefed at any trial at which they made a change-response or, if they did not, if they completed 10 trials of the experiment (for reviews see Walker et al . 1991 ; Walker and Zelditch 1993 ; Zelditch et al .
The Normative Regulation of Power
1 63
1983 ; Zelditch and Walker 1984 ; for specific experiments, see Ford and Zelditch 1988 ; Thomas et al . 1986 ; Walker et al . 1986 ; Walker et al . 1988 ; Zelditch and Ford 1994) . But in the experiments reported in the present paper, Ss were either in a C position or in a position to support C . The dependent variable was either (1) resistance by an S at the C position to a change-response made by a confederate at a P position; or (2) support of a change-response (made by a confederate at either C or P) by an S who was a peer of C (C') ; or (3) support of a change-response (made by P) by a peer of P (P') . In all three cases, a confederate made an attempt to change the structure of the network at the end of the second or third trial of the experiment . When S is at the C position, S effectively controls the agenda of any decision by the group because all messages pass through C . A change-response by C was therefore measured by the rate at which C forwarded change-responses made by and addressed to others . (Thus, the forwarding rate, P(F) = df the probability that C forwards a change-response .) Use of the agenda power to delay or prevent change is an abuse of C's power unless authorized by E . The use of C's power to delay or prevent change was measured by the rate at which C does not forward the confederate's message to its addressee (1-P(F)) . Support was measured by (1) the execution of directives (from C or P) by C' ; (2) the endorsement of them by P' ; or (3) positive or negative sanctions by C' or P' for compliance or noncompliance with either rules or directives (from C or P) . To create a peer of C, E assigned S to a role as an assistant to E in E's office and support was measured by the rate at which S authorized change (or resistance to change) by a confederate at either C or P . (This measured the probability of authorization, P(A) .) To create peers of P, a confederate at a P position attempted change and support was measured by the rate at which Ss at other P positions endorsed it . (This measured the probability of endorsement, P(E) .) Sanctions by C' were measured by re-assignment of leaders in the two-team variant of the standardized experimental setting described below . Sanctions by P' were measured by acceptance or rejection of P as a co-worker at the end of the standard experiment .
A Variant of the Standardized Experimental Setting One of the experiments we describe in the present paper (from Walker et al . 1997) was set in a variant of the standardized experimental setting in which C' assisted E by monitoring performance (at the same task) by two teams, half of which were centralized and half decentralized . There was no bonus in this setting, no change procedure, and all Ss (at C') completed five trials of the experiment . Instead of a bonus, the procedure creating inequity was that team leaders of each team made recommendations to C' about how team earnings should be divided, half of which were equal and half unequal . Centralization made unequal divisions equitable while decentralization made them inequitable .
1 64
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A. WALKER
An important difference between the standardized and variant settings was that the variant gave C' more autonomy than the standardized setting . C was responsible not only for monitoring team performance (e .g ., calculating the number of correct solutions), calculating team earnings, and communicating results, but also for making final decisions about how to divide team earnings and reassigning team leaders at what Ss at C' thought was mid-experiment, that is, at the end of the fifth trial of the experiment . Overview
The nine experiments described in the present paper divide into five in which S is at the C position and four in which S is either C' or P' . The five in which S is at the C position test hypotheses about the effect of internal and/or external constraints on the use of the agenda power by C . The four in which S is either C' or P' test hypotheses about the effects of valid norms, values, beliefs, practices, and procedures on authorization or endorsement .
MECHANISMS A Baseline Experiment
If S is at the C position, a bonus for the first correct solution of the task has two sides to it : It is both a gain to C and an inequity for which C is responsible . A baseline experiment showed that the two effects tend to cancel each other . It also showed considerable abuse of the agenda power even when there was no bonus . The purpose of the baseline experiment was to provide a standard against which to measure all other results of experiments with S at the C position . In the control group of the baseline experiment (which was carried out in the standardized experimental setting), no bonus was awarded, the agenda power was neither authorized nor de-authorized, and the wheel was neither endorsed nor dis-endorsed . Under these conditions, 71 percent of Ss at the C position forwarded a change-response made by a confederate at a P position . But even without the incentive of a bonus, 29 percent of Ss in the C position delayed or prevented change in the wheel . A post-session measure of the efficiency and propriety of the wheel showed that, other things being equal, Cs in the control group believed the wheel was the most efficient, and therefore the "right," way to organize for performance of the task, which in turn justified attempts to delay or prevent change (cf . Lipset's "effectiveness" hypothesis [1959] ; see also Linz 1978) . 3 In two treatment conditions a bonus of either $0 .75 or $1 .50 was awarded for the first correct solution of the task . The size of the bonus did not significantly affect the forwarding rate . At $0 .75, P(F) =.52 ; at $1 .50, P(F) = .60. (The likeli-
The Normative Regulation of Power
1 65
hood ratio chi square L2 =2.10, P = n . s .) . The most likely explanation for this is that the increase in gain was offset by the increase in inequity . There was clearly a "gain effect," because 25 percent of Cs in the two bonus conditions neither forwarded P's change-proposal nor redistributed the bonus by other means . But, as gain increased so did the off-setting effect of inequity . Hence, the size of the gain did not affect the forwarding rate . However, gain had more, hence inequity arguably less, effect on post-session measures of the efficiency and propriety of the wheel . Without a bonus, Cs in this setting uniformly regarded the wheel, because it was efficient, as the proper way to organize for performance of the task (see note 3) . It was the bonus that de-legitimated the wheel : A bonus of $0 .75 significantly decreased both its efficiency and propriety . However, at a bonus of $1 .50 both the efficiency and propriety of the wheel increased again and the deviation from linearity was in both cases statistically significant . (For the post-session measure of efficiency, F for the deviation from linearity was 4 .58, P = .004 . For the measure of propriety, F = 5 .10, P = .03) . 5 Mechanisms Constraining the Use of Power by Authority Propriety
The effect of the bonus on measured propriety is an important factor to take into account in interpreting the behavior of C because propriety, in general, had a significant effect on the forwarding rate : Aggregating over five experiments with S at the C position, P(F) was inversely proportional to the propriety of the wheel (see Table 1, row 2) . If the wheel was proper, C felt empowered to delay or prevent change ; if the wheel was improper, C felt constrained to forward a change-proposal . However, although gain affected propriety, the effect of propriety on P(F) was not due simply to gain : P(F) was correlated with propriety even in those experiments in which gain was a constant (Phi= - .16, P < .001) . Thus, propriety affected P(F) even when it was not self-serving .
Table 1 .
Source of or Type of Support for Legitimacy Validity Propriety Validity x Propriety Authorization Endorsement
Odds of Not Forwarding a Change-Proposal by Source of or Type of Support for Legitimacy
N 88 307 88 40 41
Odds
Ratio
4 .50 4 .50 8 .68 4 .56 1 .08
L2 7 .50 12 .22 2 .74 8 .60 1 .50
df
P
1 1 1 1 1
< .001 < .10 < .01 n .s .
< .01
1 66
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
Validity
In the Dornbusch-Scott theory of authority, validity, independent of propriety, regulates the use of power by authority . In order to test this hypothesis, we made the bonus, and hence the wheel, proper by emphasizing the effort required by C's role ; or improper, by saying nothing to justify the bonus . We made the wheel valid by making change invalid, instructing Cs that change damaged E's objectives in this particular experiment ; or valid, by saying nothing about the validity of change-Cs were left to infer that change was valid from the existence of a change procedure in the experiment . The agenda power was neither authorized nor de-authorized, the wheel neither endorsed nor dis-endorsed . But in this particular experiment, the confederate at P sent not one but four change-proposals to S at the C position, E stopping S the first time S forwarded a change-proposal . Thus, the measure of the forwarding rate in this experiment is the probability of ever forwarding a change-proposal . We found that independent of the effect of propriety, there was a direct effect of validity on P(F) (Table 1, row 1) : If change was invalid, C felt empowered to delay or prevent change by not forwarding a change-proposal . If change was valid, C was constrained from using the agenda power to delay or prevent change . Furthermore, validity interacted with propriety (though the significance level was marginal) in such a way that Cs were more willing to follow their conscience if it was backed by validity (Table 1, row 3) . Authorization
In addition to the direct effect of validity on P(F), validity should have an indirect effect through its effect on expected authorization . We did not test the hypothesis that validity creates expectations of authorization, but we did test the effect that authorization, as a proxy for expected authorization, has on P(F) . In order to test the hypothesis, E both authorized and de-authorized use of the agenda power by C . The wheel was neither endorsed nor dis-endorsed and the bonus was $1 .50 in both conditions . Authorization of the agenda power had the largest effect found in any experiment in which S was at the center of the wheel (Table 1, row 4) . If the agenda power was authorized, C felt empowered to not forward change-proposals and only 35 percent of Cs forwarded them . If the agenda power was de-authorized, C felt constrained to forward change-proposals and 80 percent of Cs forwarded them . Endorsement
In order to test the expected endorsement hypothesis, E manipulated the outcome of an election that Ss at the C position knew would not determine the structure of the network but that did express the majority's preferences for or against
1 67
The Normative Regulation of Power
the wheel . Half the Cs were informed that a majority favored the wheel, half that it favored an all-all network . The agenda power in this experiment was neither authorized nor de-authorized and again the bonus was $1 .50 . The expected endorsement hypothesis was not confirmed by this experiment . There was in fact a direct effect of endorsement on propriety (The odds ratio=8 .18, L2 = 7 .52, P < .01) and P(F) was inversely proportional to propriety (Table 1, row 2), but there was no direct effect of endorsement on P(F) when propriety was controlled (Table 1, row 5) . 6 That endorsement had no direct effect on P(F) would be easy to explain if peripheral positions had no power, but in fact the task in this experimental setting is such that any individual in a P position has the power to prevent anyone else from ever getting the correct solution simply by withholding the information that she or he controls . But it is possible that Ss in the C position were not conscious of P's power or, even if they were, simply took it for granted that P would without question provide others with the information on which the solution of the task depended . We therefore tested the expected endorsement hypothesis again by making C more aware of the power of P and manipulating the expected probability that P would use the position's potential power . In order to magnify the effect of this manipulation we authorized the use of the agenda power by C and dis-endorsed the wheel (Zelditch 1999) . Unfortunately, we failed to anticipate the effect that the illegitimacy of the use of P's potential power would have on C : We did find that P(F) was directly proportional to the cost to C of the use of power by P (Table 2, column 2) . But the effect was curvilinear, because P(F) was also inversely proportional to the legitimacy of the use of power by P . Withholding task information violated task norms, making use of it as power by P illegitimate . At a low probability of retaliation, Cs who were made aware of P's power decreased P(F) because illegitimacy of such a use of power by P offset the costs to C of its use . At a high probability of retaliation, the use of power by P was even less legitimate, as is indicated by the significant decrease in the probability of redistribution by other means (Table 2, column 3) . But the negative effect of legitimacy was offset by the increase in expected costs to C of the use by P of P's power . (The chi square for the deviation from lin-
Table 2 .
Odds of Authorizing or Endorsing a Change-Proposal by Source of and Type of Support for Legitimacy
Source of Legitimacy
Type of Support
Validity Interest Validity Propriety Endorsement
Authorization Authorization Endorsement Endorsement Endorsement
N
Odds Ratio
L2
df
P
83 83 88 168 80
8 .90 3 .09 2 .50 5 .18 4 .00
21 .89 6 .70 4 .60 25 .70 9 .50
1 1 1 1 1
< .001 < .05 < .05 < .001 < .01
168
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
Table 3 .
Odds of Sanctioning the Source of a Change-Proposal by Source of and Type of Support for Legitimacy
Source of Legitimacy
Type of Support
N
Odds Ratio
L2
df
Validity Propriety Validity Propriety
Authorization Authorization Endorsement Endorsement
83 83 88 88
0 .28 0 .08 0.38 0 .65
9.14 24 .00 4 .42 1 .30
1 1 1 1
P < .01 < .001 < .05 n .s.
earity is significant [Table 2, rows 6 and 7 of column 2] .) Thus, given power at the periphery, the effect of expected endorsement is to empower C to delay or prevent change if the wheel is endorsed but to constrain C if the wheel is dis-endorsed (for details see Zelditch 1999) . Normative Regulation of Constraints On the Use of Power by Authority Authorization
Other things being equal, almost all Ss at C' authorized an election to change the structure of the wheel in the standardized experimental setting . In an experiment in which C' assisted E by evaluating team performance (against an answer key), calculating and allocating team earnings, and communicating results to team members, C' also had the agenda power. When the wheel was made improper by a bonus of $1 .25 and change was valid, 95 percent of Ss at C' authorized an election (proposed by a confederate at the P position) that would change the structure of the wheel (Zelditch, Gilliland, and Thomas 1984) . If change was invalid, 39 percent of Ss at C' approved an election to change the wheel-a large number, certainly, but a significant decrease due to validity (Table 3, row 1) . Furthermore, the effect of validity was independent both of preferences, also manipulated in the experiment, and of propriety . Gain was manipulated in this experiment by paying C' either a flat fee for participation or an amount equal to the highest amount paid to any member of the team C' supervised . A vested interest in the status quo had a significant independent effect on authorization (Table 3, row 2), but the effect of validity was independent of gain and the interaction of the two was not statistically significant . Propriety should have little or no effect on authorization . But propriety did not differ by condition in the experiment just described . It was equally low in all conditions. To test the propriety hypothesis, it was necessary to re-design the standardized experimental setting, which was the reason for a two-team variant of it . In a two-team setting C' again assisted E by evaluating team answers (from an answer key), calculating team earnings, and communicating results to each team, but in addition made final decisions about the distribution of team earnings rec-
1 69
The Normative Regulation of Power
ommended by C in each team . C' was also charged with responsibility for reassigning C at mid-experiment if C' believed it was required . An important feature of the experiment-one we underestimated-was the much greater structural autonomy of C' in this setting . In E's instructions, emphasis was placed on the fact that the decisions of C' were final . To create propriety we varied the structure of the teams instead of introducing a bonus . Absent a bonus, which creates a very large inequity, a centralized network does legitimate some inequality (Walker et al . 1997) . Therefore, we used a wheel to legitimate recommendations by C of a moderately unequal division of team earnings and used an all-all network to de-legitimate them . ("C" in an all-all network was arbitrarily assigned .) Half of the confederates at the C position recommended an equal division, half recommended an unequal division of team earnings . Validity was also manipulated in this experiment : To create validity, E either instructed C (overheard by S at C') that team earnings should be divided equally or made no rule about how to divide team earnings . Because both the structure of the network and the distribution rule had an effect on the post-session measure of propriety, this experiment has to be thought of in terms of three rather than two effects on authorization : An effect of network structure (manipulated propriety), validity (whether or not their is a rule), and measured propriety (a co-variate due to both structure and rule) . And in fact, contrary to hypothesis, acceptance of unequal pay recommendations by C' was directly proportional to the propriety of inequality (Table 4, row 3 of the right-hand panel of the table) . In fact, where validity and propriety were inconsistent, 33 percent of C's violated the rule in order to act on their conscience . Even worse for our hypothesis, sanctions were also directly proportional to mea-
Table 4.
Mean Earnings of C Authorized by Subjects Assisting E, by Source of Legitimacy with Selected Statistics of Repeated Measures Analysis of Variance
Source of Legitimacy: Inequality is
Repeated Measures Analysis of Variancea Mean Earnings of C
Proper and Valid
$3 .14
Proper and Invalid
$2 .94
Improper and Valid
$2 .38
Improper and Invalid
$2 .49
Note:
a. b.
Source of Variation Validity Structure Propriety b VX S V x P S X P V x S x P
Sum of Squares
df
F
P
.03 .08 7 .31 .75 .04 .24 1 .21
1 1 1 1 1 1 1
.16 .42 37 .49 3 .83 .21 1 .25 6 .21
n .s . n .s . < .001 .05 n .s . n .s . .02
Omitting constant, error, and within S's source of variation . No within-S's factor was statistically significant. Both the strcuture of the communication network and the rule affected propriety as measured in the post-session questionnaire . The means are for the types of structure that make inequality proper or improper . The RMANOVA distinguishes these structures from measured propriety .
170 Table 5.
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER Odds of Sanctioning the Source of a Change-Proposal by Source of and Type of Support for Legitimacy
Source of Legitimacy
Type of Support
Validity Propriety
Authorization Authorization
Validity Propriety
Endorsement Endorsement
Odds
L2
df
3 .62
9 .14
1
< .01
0 .08 2 .62 1 .55
24 .00 4 .42 1 .30
1 1 1
< .001 < .05
N
Ratio
83 83 88 88
P
n .s .
sured propriety, independent of the effect of either structure or validity (Table 5, row 2) . Not only did propriety have a main effect on both the division of team earnings and sanctions, but validity, though it did have a direct effect on sanctions (Table 5, row 1), had only an indirect effect, through propriety, on the division of team earnings (Table 4, row 1 of the right-hand panel) . Validity did interact with propriety to increase the effect of propriety on the division of team earnings : The effect of manipulated propriety was stronger if it was backed by validity and the effect of measured propriety was stronger if both structure and validity backed it (Table 4, rows 4 and 7 of the right-hand panel) . But in the case of sanctions, manipulated propriety (Table 5, row 2), measured propriety (not shown in table 5), and validity (Table 5, row 1) all had direct effects on sanctions and none of the interactions were statistically significant . All this, we believe, was due to the structural autonomy of C' in the two-team setting . In the standardized experimental setting, authorization was directly proportional to validity (Table 3, row 1) . There, C' was responding to a change-proposal by P, not C, which should have increased the effect of personal inclinations, but was less autonomous than C' in the two-team setting . Aside from the difference in the confederate's position, the critical difference between the two experiments is the freedom of C' from constraint in the two-team setting . Endorsement To study the effect of validity and propriety on endorsement, we varied both the validity of change and the propriety of the wheel in the standardized experimental setting with both S and the confederate in P positions . A confederate at P sent a change-proposal to S, also at P, who either did or did not second ("endorse") it . On the post-session questionnaire, sanctions were also measured . The Ss (as in most of the nine experiments) were male . Propriety was manipulated by awarding a bonus for the fastest correct solution in half the groups but no bonus in the other half. Validity was manipulated by making change invalid (because it damaged the objectives of E) in half the groups and valid in the other half .
The Normative Regulation of Power
1 71
Endorsement by P' of change proposals by P was inversely proportional to both the propriety and validity of the wheel . (See Table 3, rows 3-4 . Row 4 aggregates the results of two experiments .) Their interaction was not significant . Sanctions by P' were directly proportional to the validity of the wheel but propriety had no effect on them (Table 5, rows 3-4) . On the other hand, a separate experiment that directly manipulated endorsement of the wheel by others, though it found that-independent of proprietyendorsement of the wheel by others decreased endorsement of change by P' (Table 3, row 5), found too few sanctions to test the hypothesis that sanctions were proportional to endorsement . The difference in the probability of sanctions between the two studies of endorsement is too large to be due simply to chance (57% versus 5%) . The Ss in the second of these experiments were female and the gender of the Ss is of course a possible explanation of the differences in the rate of sanctions . But this explanation is inconsistent both with other evidence in these two experiments (see Walker et al . 1990) and evidence in other experiments in the program (see Walker and Smith-Donals 1985) . A more likely explanation is the difference in the source of legitimacy between the two experiments . Validity (the source of legitimacy in the first case) is a normative effect of consensus and is clearly enforceable . On the other hand, the effect of endorsement (the source of legitimacy in the second case) is equivocal: If one member of the group proposes change, she or he is not necessarily violating a norm because she or he is also changing the state of consensus in the group and decreasing consensus weakens backing for sanctions (Walker et al . 1990) . Frailties in the Normative Regulation of External Constraints on the Use of Power by Authority
An important finding of experiments on the normative regulation of external constraints on the use of power by authority is that the same frailties found in internal constraints on the use of power are found in its external constraints . Self-interest, self-serving propriety, and eccentric propriety are all frailties in the internal constraints on the use of power by authority . But self-interest and eccentric propriety also affected authorization (see IVC(1)) . Our interpretation of the latter finding-that it depended on structural autonomy-raises an important and more general question : Under what conditions do norms actually constrain the use of power by authority? The same question arises from other anomalies in the findings : That endorsement had no effect on an S at the center of the wheel until S was made aware of the potential power of the periphery-implying that the effect of external constraints depends on power-dependence (IVB(4)) ; that decreasing endorsement by others decreased the likelihood of sanctions by P'-implying the dependence of sanctions on consensus (IVC(2)) . These anomalies cast doubt on the initial conditions of our experiments, not the general conceptual and theoreti-
1 72
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
cal ideas of the theory . They raise questions not about the mechanisms of the process but about the conditions under which norms regulate power . Therefore, we now turn to the question of what our theory and results imply about the conditions under which norms regulate power . We do not ask the conditions under which there are frailties ; what we ask is the conditions under which, if there are frailties, norms regulate them . And what we offer are not findings, but untested hypotheses : the deductions of the conditions of the normative regulation of power from our theory of authority were not tested by the experiments we have reported in the present paper and the interpretation of anomalies in our results are ex post facto, hence also untested .
CONDITIONS The Dornbusch-Scott theory of authority implies four conditions on which normative regulation of the use of power by an authority A depends : consensus ; density of ties to A ; dependence of A on peers and superiors, A', and/ or subordinates, B and B' ; and density of ties to A' . Consensus The entire structure of the Dornbusch-Scott theory of authority depends on validity . But validity presupposes consensus (Zelditch and Floyd 1998) . Consensus is therefore an important condition under which norms regulate the abuse of power. In the first instance, actual consensus conditions the effect that validity has on authorization by A' and endorsement by 13' . In addition, the perception of consensus by A conditions the effect that validity has on A's expectations of authorization by A' and endorsement by B' . Actual dissensus decreases validity . A decrease in validity has five effects : First, it decreases the frequency of sanctions by A' and B' . Second, it decreases the association between validity and authorization by A' . Third, it decreases the association between validity and endorsement by B' . Furthermore, it also decreases the effect that validity has on the strength of the association between propriety and authorization by A' and, fifth, the effect that validity has on the strength of the association between propriety and endorsement by B'-as consensus decreases, both A' and/or B' are more likely to act on their own sense of what is proper, whether or not backed by validity . A decrease in the effect of validity on authorization and endorsement is one way in which actual dissensus undermines the presupposition of consensus by A . Whether by this or other means, the perception of dissensus by A decreases the effect that validity has on expectations by A of authorization by A' and/or endorsement by B' . The effect of perceived dissensus on the strength of the association between validity and expectations of authorization and endorsement, in
The Normative Regulation of Power
1 73
turn, decreases the effect of expected authorization and endorsement on the use of power by A . It also decreases the effect that validity has on the association between A's sense of propriety and the use of power by A . If A believes the norms, values, beliefs, practices, and procedures supposedly governing A's actions are not shared, A is more likely to act on his or her own sense of what is proper even if it is not backed by validity . Density of Structural Constraints on A
But even if there is consensus, the scope of the Dornbusch-Scott theory of authority presupposes accountability of A to others : In organizations, to boards of directors, to peers who execute directives and sanction noncompliance, to subordinates on whose performance A depends for outcomes valued by the organization ; in communities, by extension, to those on whom selection of authorities, mobilization of resources, and enforcement of authority depend . Anything that weakens accountability increases the structural autonomy of A . Structural autonomy of A decreases external constraints on A (cf . Burt 1992 ; Markovsky, Willer, and Patton 1988) . Given the frailty of internal constraints, the abuse of power is therefore proportional to the structural autonomy of A . The structural autonomy of A decreases the frequency of sanctions by A' . But it also decreases the association between validity and expected authorization (or nonauthorization) by A' . It therefore decreases the association between validity and the use of power by A . It also attenuates the effect validity has on the association between A's sense of propriety and the use of power by A . Because redundancy of the network of ties to A decreases structural autonomy (Burt 1992 ; Markovsky, Willer, and Patton 1988), external constraints on A therefore depend on the density of the network of ties in which A is embedded . The greater the redundancy of these ties, the greater the association between validity and expected authorization by A', the greater the association between validity and the use of power by A, and the greater the effect of validity on the strength of the association between propriety and the use of power by A . The normative regulation of power is therefore proportional to network density at A . Power Dependence
But even if A is not structurally autonomous, the effect of external constraints on A depends on the extent to which A is dependent on others for resources valued by A (Emerson 1962, 1972) . If density is held constant, the strength of the effect of sanctions by A' and B' increases as A's dependence on them increases . As A's dependence on them decreases, external constraints are enfeebled and neither validity nor expected support constrains the use of power by A . The greater the dependence of A on A', the greater the effect of expected authorization . The greater the dependence of A on B', the greater the effect of expected endorsement .
1 74
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
The greater the effect of either expected authorization, expected endorsement, or both, the greater the association between validity and the use of power by A and the greater the effect of validity on the strength of the association between A's sense of propriety and the use of power by A . Structural Constraints at A' But who guards the guardians? If the possibility of an independent counsel constrains the president, what constrains the independent counsel? Even if A is constrained by dependence on A' and/or B', the frailties in constraint regress if A' or B' is autonomous. (This seems less likely in the case of B' who we neglect for the rest of this section .) Where there is only one A' on whom constraint of A depends, any eccentricity of A' is itself unconstrained . 8 The normative regulation of power therefore depends as much on density at A' and the dependence of A' on others as it does on density at and dependence of A . Redundancy of ties to A', and dependence by A' on peers and/or superiors other than A, increases the association of validity with authorization by A' and the effect validity has on the strength of the association between what A' believes is proper and authorization by A' . To the extent that agents of social control are densely interconnected, the eccentricities of any one agent's propriety is constrained and normative consensus in fact constrains the abuse of power by authority.
CONCLUSIONS The first conclusion we came to was that internal constraints are not sufficient to normatively regulate the use of power by authority : Some uses of power by authority remain self-interested ; even if they are proper, propriety may be self-serving ; even if propriety is not self-serving, it may be idiosyncratic-not only is propriety not always the solution, it is often the problem . External constraints are therefore a necessary condition of the normative regulation of power . The second conclusion we came to was that an elaboration of the Dornbusch-Scott theory of authority is a satisfactory theory of the mechanisms of the normative regulation of power. The evidence supported all the hypotheses of the theory concerning the effects of external constraints on A . Validity had a direct effect on the use of power by A . It had indirect effects not only through propriety but also through expectations of authorization by peers or superiors of A and endorsement by subordinates of A-though in the case of expected endorsement, only after strengthening the power of the subordinate, B . Furthermore, the effect of propriety on the use of power by A was stronger if it was backed by validity . But the most important hypothesis of the theory is that it is validity that drives external constraints on the use of power by A. And support of this hypothesis was mixed . In support of the theory, independent of propriety, authorization by A' of
The Normative Regulation of Power
1 75
change by B was directly proportional to validity . The effect of propriety on the authorization by A' of division of team earnings by A was stronger when backed by validity . Endorsement by B' of change by B was also directly proportional to validity, as well as to endorsement by others . And validity had a direct effect on sanctions by either A' of A or B' of B . But contrary to hypothesis, in one of two experiments on the normative regulation of authorization, validity affected authorization of team earnings only indirectly, through propriety . And in one of two experiments on the normative regulation of endorsement, endorsement by the majority, though it had a direct effect on endorsement of change, had no effect on sanctions . But these anomalies cast doubt on the initial conditions of the experiments, not the basic concepts and laws of the theory : structural constraints on A in the first case, group consensus in the second case . They raised questions not about the mechanisms of the process but about the conditions under which norms regulate power . Similar questions were raised by the third conclusion to which we came : That the frailties we had found in the internal constraints on the use of power by A regress, if not infinitely, at least to the external constraints used by A' and/or B' . Interest in gain had an independent effect on authorization by A' of change by B . In the two-team setting, when validity and propriety were inconsistent, a third of A's peers followed their conscience rather than the rules . And (again in the two-team setting), propriety had its own independent effect on sanctions of A by A' . With respect to the conditions under which norms regulate power, we came to the conclusion that four are necessary : Consensus, a dense network of ties to A, dependence of A on either A', B', or both ; and a dense network of ties among agents of social control . Absent consensus, its presupposition, on which the effects of validity depend, is undermined . Absent a dense network of ties to A, accountability, on which the entire structure of the argument that norms regulate power depends, is undermined . If A does not care about sanctions by A' and/or B', the process of social control in which the norms regulating power are embedded is undermined . Undermining any of these three conditions (1) decreases the effect of validity on actual and expected support by A' and B' and therefore (2) decreases the effect of validity and expected support by A' and B' on the use of power by A . In addition, (3) it decreases the effect of validity on the strength of the association between propriety and support by A' and/or B' . Finally, (4) it decreases the association between A's sense of propriety and the use of power by A . But regress of the frailties in constraint depends also on the density of ties among agents of social control . The sparser the ties, especially to A', the weaker the effect of validity on support and on the strength of the association between propriety and support . It is only to the extent that agents of social control are densely interconnected that the eccentricities of any one agent's propriety is constrained and normative consensus in fact regulates the use of power by authority .
176
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
ACKNOWLEDGMENT We would like to acknowledge the support of NSF grants SOC 7817434 for research on "Group Determinants of Agenda Setting," SES 8420238 for research on "Legitimacy and the Stability of Authority," and SES 8712097 for research on "Agenda Gatekeeping."
NOTES 1 . This is an intentionally very abstract, hence inclusive, expression for any kind of "element" of the external social order of a group, whether norms, values, beliefs, practices, or procedures . 2 . This is as true of values, beliefs, and practices as it is of norms . Whether or not e is a prescriptive element of the pre-given social framework that structures a particular encounter, if it is valid it is prescriptive, hence "binding," in any particular encounter (Berger and Zelditch 1993) . 3 . In a post-session questionnaire, Ss in the control group rated the mean efficiency of the wheel 1 .57 on a scale from 1 (very efficient) to 5 (very inefficient) . Approval of the wheel was used to measure its propriety . On a scale from 1 (very highly approve) to 5 (very highly disapprove), the mean propriety of the wheel was 2 .33 . 4. Though we did not intend to have a second dependent variable, Cs were quite imaginative about ways to redistribute the bonus . They found ways to split it, despite the fact that E instructed them not to do so, or to rotate it, or to delay their own answer until each other P in turn had had a chance to submit an answer first . About 25 percent of Cs in the baseline experiment redistributed the bonus by these means . Furthermore, in the five experiments in which S is at the center of the wheel, there is a negative correlation between the probability of redistributing by other means and the probability of forwarding a change-proposal (Phi =- .18, L 2=12 .2, P < .001) . But the percent of the variance explained is not large enough to account for the effects of the treatment variables manipulated in these experiments . 5 . In general, the forwarding rate was correlated with measured propriety (see Table 1, row 2) . This result was obtained by aggregating over five experiments, including the baseline experiment . But the strength of the correlation was not strong enough to significantly differentiate the forwarding rate of the two bonus conditions in the baseline experiment. 6 . The odds ratio in row 5 of Table 1 indicates that, despite the indirect effect of endorsement on P(F), there was no zero-order association between endorsement and P(F) in this experiment . This was due to the fact that the effect of endorsement on propriety was positive while the effect of propriety on forwarding was negative . In this experiment, the opposing effects masked each other when the 2 x 2 x 2 table was collapsed across categories of propriety . 7 . We follow Emerson (1962, 1972) in assuming that the dependence of p on o for resource R is directly proportional to the value of R to p but inversely proportional to the number of alternative sources of R available to p . 8 . This paper was written about the time of the investigation of Clinton by Staff and sometimes sounds as if we were actually writing about them-especially, perhaps, Starr-but in fact the original proposal for the research dates from 1987 .
REFERENCES Barnard, C . 1938 . Functions of the Executive . Cambridge, MA: Harvard. Bavelas, A . 1950 . "Communication Patterns in Task-Oriented Groups ." Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 22 : 725-30 . Berger, J ., and M . Zelditch. 1993 . "Notes on a Theory of Institutionalization ." Unpublished manuscript . Stanford, CA : Stanford University .
The Normative Regulation of Power
177
Burt, R . 1992 . Structural Holes . Cambridge, MA : Harvard . Dornbusch, S . M., and W. R. Scott. 1975 . Evaluation and the Exercise of Authority . San Francisco, CA : Jossey-Bass . Emerson, R . 1962 . "Power-Dependence Relations ." American Sociological Review 27 :31- 41 . Emerson, R . 1972 . "Exchange Theory." Pp 38-87 in Sociological Theories in Progress, Vol 2, edited by J . Berger, M . Zelditch, and B . Anderson . Boston, MA : Houghton Mifflin . Ford, J . B ., and M . Zelditch . 1988 . "A Test of the Law of Anticipated Reactions ." Social Psychology Quarterly 51 : 164-71 . Linz, J. 1978 . The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes .' Crisis, Breakdown, and Re-equilibration . Baltimore, MD : Johns Hopkins . Lipset, S . M . 1959 . "Some Social Requisites of Democracy : Economic Development and Political Legitimacy ." American Political Science Review 53 : 69-105 . MacKenzie, K . 1976 . A Theory of Group Structures . New York: Gordon and Breach . Markovsky, B ., D . Willer, and T. Patton . 1988 . "Power Relations in Exchange Networks ." American Sociological Review 53 : 220-36. Tetlock, P. 1992 . "The Impact of Accountability on Judgment and Choice: Toward a Social Contingency Model ." Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 25 : 331-376 . Thomas, G ., H . Walker, and M . Zelditch, 1986 . "Legitimacy and Collective Action ." Social Forces 65 : 378-404 . Walker, H ., L . Rogers, K . Lyman, and M . Zelditch . 1990 . "Legitimacy and the Support of Revolutionary Coalitions." Unpublished manuscript . Ithica, NY : Cornell University . Walker, H ., L . Rogers, G . Thomas, and M . Zelditch. 1991 . "Legitimating Collective Action : Theory and Experimental Results ." Pp 1-25 in Research in Political Sociology, Vol 5, edited by P . Washburn . Greenwich, CT : JAI . Walker, H., L . Rogers, and M . Zelditch . 1988 . "Legitimacy and Collective Action : A Research Note ." Social Forces 67 : 216-228 . Walker, H., and L . Smith-Donals . 1985 . "Gender or Status : The Effects of Differences in Sex on Behavior Under Certain Conditions of Disadvantage ." Working Paper No . 85 .2 . Stanford University, Center For Sociological Research . Walker, H ., G . Thomas, and M . Zelditch, 1986 . "Legitimation, Endorsement, and Stability ." Social Forces 64 : 620-643 . Walker, H., and M . Zelditch . 1993 . "Power, Legitimacy, and the Stability of Authority : A Theoretical Research Program ." Pp 364-381 in Theoretical Research Programs : Studies in the Growth of Theory, edited by J . Berger and M . Zelditch . Stanford, CA : Stanford. Walker, H ., M . Zelditch, P. Taylor, and V . Montoya . 1997 . "Choosing Standards: Validity, Propriety, and Pay Equity ." Unpublished manuscript . Ithica, NY : Cornell University . Weber, M . [1918] 1968 . Economy and Society, edited by G . Roth and C . Wittich and translated by E . Fischoff et al. New York: Bedminster. Zelditch, M . 1999 . "Legitimacy, Expected Value, and the Strength of Peripheral Power ."Paper presented at the West Coast Conference on Group Processes, Stanford University, Stanford, CA . Zelditch, M ., and A . Floyd. 1998 . "Consensus, Dissensus, and Justification ." Pp 339-368 in Status, Power, and Legitimacy, edited by J . Berger and M . Zelditch . Stanford, CA : Stanford . Zelditch, M ., and J . Ford . 1994 . "Uncertainty, Potential Power, and Non-decisions ." Social Psychology Quarterly 57 : 64-73 . Zelditch, M ., E. Gilliland, and G . Thomas . 1984 . "The Legitimacy of Redistributive Agendas ." Working Paper # 84-9 . Center For Sociological Research, Department of Sociology, Stanford, CA, Stanford University. Zelditch, M., W . Harris, G . Thomas, and H . Walker. 1983 . "Decisions, Non-decisions, and Meta-decisions ." Pp 1-32 in Research in Social Movements, Conflict, And Change, Vol 5, edited by L. Kriesberg . Greenwich, CT: JAI .
178
MORRIS ZELDITCH and HENRY A . WALKER
Zelditch, M ., and H. Walker. 1984. "Legitimacy and the Stability of Authority ." Pp 1-25 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol 1, edited by E . Lawler. Greenwich, CT : JAI.
BEYOND THE CONCEPT OF VALUE IN POWER-DEPENDENCE THEORY EXPANDING A MODEL OF THE "WHOLE ACTOR"
John F . Stolte
ABSTRACT Emerson's (1987) theory suggests that some notion of "the whole actor" is axial to a comprehensive understanding of value in social exchange . Building from this notion, the present paper explores four pathways along which the theory might be clarified and extended . First, it explores the intricate connections that exist among need, uncertainty, and value, bringing to bear the operant conditioning and the rational choice perspectives . Second, it examines the complex interplay among extrinsic motivation, intrinsic motivation, and value . Third, it considers the dynamic oscillation that may occur between rational/cognitive and mindless/emotional processes in behavioral decision making . Fourth, it distinguishes socially intrinsic from socially extrinsic environmental value domains . The present analysis provides a basis for continued theoretical refinement and focused empirical research on Emerson's potentially important theory of value .
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 179-202 . Copyright © 2000 by JAI Press Inc . All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 179
180
JOHN F . STOLTE
INTRODUCTION In an unfinished but intriguing formulation, Emerson (1987) advanced the core of a social psychological theory of value . The formulation is ambiguous at points, because it is a preliminary statement, a work in progress, left unfinished due to the author's untimely death in 1982 . It is intriguing, because it provides hints of what may turn out, with further refinement, to be fundamental insights about the determinants and consequences of value in the context of social exchange relationships . Central contributors to the social exchange approach in social psychology have strongly advocated the need to build from and refine Emerson's value formulation (Cook 1987 ; Molm and Cook 1995) . The basic purposes of this paper are : (a) to summarize some of the important insights in Emerson's value theory-in-progress, and (b) to raise and briefly explore some questions about how those insights might be refined and extended . The present analysis suggests directions for further theoretical refinements and encourages focused empirical research . The following analysis (1) reviews key ideas in Emerson's value theory, (2) discusses links among need, uncertainty, and value, (3) discusses intrinsic and extrinsic motivation and value, (4) explores rational and emotional bases of decision making, (5) examines the sociocultural delineation of value domains, and (6) briefly summarizes the preceding conceptual material .
EMERSON'S THEORY OF VALUE : SELECTIVE REVIEW AND INTERPRETATION The "Whole Actor" In discussing the nature and determinants of value, Emerson introduced the idea of the "whole actor," noting that a theory of value must be a theory of actorshow they are put together and what makes them work" (Emerson 1987, p . 14) . The person, as a whole actor, is conceptualized as a complex action production system. To continue producing actions, the actor must regularly obtain "needed inputs" (valued outcomes) from various value domains in his environment . For example, perhaps an actor supplies affection to a spouse, guidance to a child, sales to an employer, and companionship to a friend . To continue producing these and a myriad of other actions, he must regularly obtain valued outcomes from various value domains composing his environment . Some domains are biological : food, water, rest, exercise, and so on . Some are social : affection from spouse and child, companionship from a friend, respect from a supervisor, and so on . Some are economic : salary from an employer and such .
Expanding a Model of the "Whole Actor"
181
Delineating Value Domains The "and so on" in the sentences above suggests, of course, that an exhaustive, concrete list of a given actor's value domains would be a practical impossibility . Yet, a general theory of the way an actor weighs the value of a satisfying meal against the value of a spouse's warm smile against the value of a bonus check provided by an employer "must somehow incorporate this entire list into the framework" (Emerson 1987, p . 15) . Emerson's solution to this problem is to employ an abstract criterion for demarcating distinct value domains in a person's environment : "Any two valued things are in the same value domain if acquisition of one reduces the unit value of the other" (p . 15) . This criterion allows a general theory to recognize and deal manageably with the multitude of possible value domains (and outcomes) for any "whole actor." Perhaps one value domain contains warm smiles from a child and a spouse, while an alternative domain contains a bonus check, a large annual pay increase, and weekend use of the company yacht . Multiple value domains imply multiple needs . "Any organized system has needed inputs, meaning that (a) continued operation of the system (actor) is contingent, in some degree, upon those inputs ; and (b) the system is so organized that action is allocated by principles that tend to insure those inputs" (p . 28) . Perhaps an actor values warm smiles and other gestures of affection from family members, because he needs them, just as he values a sign of respect from a boss because he needs that . Within Emerson's theory, internal needs that define an actor's value domains are displayed through the consequential action (e .g ., behavioral energy or time) allocated toward specifiable domains in the external world . Under certain conditions, such action results in units of valued outcome . Dynamic Variation in Outcome Value As units of a given kind of outcome fall, for an actor, below an optimum' level, their value increases . Conceivably, an actor who is away from home on business for an extended period of time, and deprived of family affection, will come to value such affection more highly . Conversely, as units of a given kind of outcome rise above an optimum level, their value decreases for an actor . Back home routinely for an extended time, and having experienced many recent positive encounters with family members, perhaps an actor will come to value family affection less highly, and maybe he will seek an opportunity to take a business trip . Within-Domain Versus Between-Domain Behavior In Emerson's value theory, an actor who currently places relatively high value on outcomes in a given domain will be motivated to expend effort (i .e ., allocate behavioral time and energy) toward obtaining such outcomes . Given that he is
182
JOHN F . STOLTE
acting within a given value domain, his behavior is predicted to conform to the traditional rational choice2 model: he will make planful decisions intended to maximize expected value . A high level of cognitive calculation will precede decisions, so that an instrumental selection can be made among alternative means, thus minimizing costs (in behavioral time and energy) and maximizing outcomes (the number of valued units achieved) . Suppose, for example, that an actor is currently deprived of work-related status, (e .g., bonus checks, visibility in the company newsletter, recent promotion) because he has, for a time, devoted much effort in the family domain while merely "getting by" at work . The theory predicts that this actor will place a heightened value on work-status outcomes and will begin acting rationally to achieve such outcomes . Becoming preoccupied with work, he may focus explicit cognitive attention on various possible instrumental means that might aid in the attainment of status outcomes, choosing those that seem most efficient, that promise to minimize the expenditure of action time and energy and maximize the number of valued work-status outcome units achieved . Suppose the actor sells insurance . He might attempt to make a sale whenever and wherever possible : at a PTA meeting, at a neighborhood barbecue, when friends drop over for dinner . But the "whole actor" in Emerson's theory is seen as having multiple value domains, among which he is predicted to optimize . In this theory, action resources (e .g ., behavioral time and energy) are inherently scarce : an actor who uses such resources to pursue outcome units within a given value domain cannot simultaneously use those same resources to pursue outcome units within an alternative value domain . A value-based choice between domains must be made . According to the theory, optimization between domains usually regulates maximization within any given domain . The "whole actor," says Emerson, is an intricate production (rather than consumption) system . In this context, optimization connotes such synonyms as "accelerate, enhance, boost ." The acquisition of an outcome unit in one domain (e .g ., work status) will not lead to a decrease in the value of an outcome unit in an alternative domain (e .g ., family affection) . Indeed, a unit in one domain might increase (enhance, optimize) the value of a unit in the alternative domain . The basic point is that valued outcomes often interact in complex ways for the "whole actor," mutually reinforcing one another to influence his ability to function as a complex action-production system . Further, Emerson contends that between-domain choices are not based on highly rational deliberation . "They do not enter. . . through the actor's prefrontal lobe" (Emerson 1987, p . 16) . Such choices, instead, are located "in the metaphorical gut" (p . 16), that is, they are based in emotional signals and feelings rather than in refined, abstract thoughts and plans . For example, as an actor is rationally pursuing status outcomes within the work domain, he might suddenly feel the need to cancel a crucial meeting with a potential customer and leave work early in order to attend his daughter's dance recital, thus achieving a valued outcome lying
Expanding a
Model of the "Whole Actor"
183
in an alternative domain . Hardly rational, (in the traditional sense) such a between-domain choice is made on felt impulse, not on calculated costs and benefits . Opportunities : Limits On an Actor's Control
In Emerson's value theory, an actor is constrained by the objective causal environment in which he lives and moves . Regardless of internal needs, the actor is subject to the factual availability or non-availability of opportunities . Before he can pursue work-status outcomes rationally, the actor must have a job, and before he can strive for outcomes of family affection, the actor must have a family . "The concept of opportunity describes the limit of an actor's control over his environment" (p . 21) . It is the external environment that "schedules" opportunities, not the actor . The existence of an objective domain opportunity sets the occasion for an action by the actor that has some probability (above zero) of being successful in obtaining a valued outcome unit from a given domain . Having a job in sales is an opportunity that grants an actor some likelihood of realizing status-outcome units (e .g ., pay increases or recognition), given work-related effort . Having a friend is an opportunity that grants an actor some probability of obtaining friendship-outcome units (e.g ., camaraderie and an enjoyable golf game), given friend-related effort . Uncertainty and Value : A Crucial Proposition
Given an objective structure of value domain opportunities, a central question centers on how probable valued outcome units are, given effort expended to achieve them . Emerson advances an extremely important concept, perhaps "the" central determinant of value in his theory : uncertainty (U) . U = xy, where x = the probability that a given action by an actor will successfully result in a unit of outcome within a specified value domain, and y = 1 - x . This variable ranges between 0 and .25 (p . 42) . Elsewhere, Emerson (1972, p . 53) multiplied the equation by a factor of 4, presumably in order to allow uncertainty to vary between 0 and 1 .0, making it a more convenient metric for possible empirical research . Uncertainty, in this value theory, is construed as both an objective and subjective phenomenon . Objectively, it describes the actual behavioral contingency linking an actor to a given value domain in the environment . Subjectively, it describes that actor's "sense" of that contingency . 3 As sensed by the actor, uncertainty may be low in a positive direction (optimism), in which case the actor senses that action expended to achieve a unit of outcome in a given domain will be nearly certain to meet with success . Or, as subjectively grasped, uncertainty may be low in the negative direction (pessimism), in which case the actor senses that action expended to obtain a unit of outcome in a given domain will be nearly certain to meet with failure . Between these two poles will be a zone of uncer-
184
JOHN F . STOLTE
tainly . The theory posits that the value of a domain or outcome unit will be directly proportional to an actor's level of uncertainty in reference to that domain or outcome . For example, an actor that is virtually sure of success in obtaining understanding support from a spouse, no matter what level of effort is expended, will tend to be very optimistic about attaining this kind of outcome, and he will tend to place relatively low value on it . On the other hand, an actor who is almost certain of failure in getting understanding support from a spouse, no matter what level of effort is expended, will tend to be very pessimistic about achieving this kind of outcome, and he will tend to place relatively low value on it . In contrast, an actor who senses that success in obtaining understanding support from a spouse is "problematic," will tend to be uncertain with respect to this kind of outcome, and the theory predicts he will devote considerable action resources (i .e ., will allocate substantial amounts of behavioral time and energy) toward the attainment of it . Uncertainty is a key element of subjective value, which is a key element of actions toward environmental value domains . A person will tend to be drawn most intensely to (i .e ., be observed expending the highest levels of behavioral time and energy toward) those value domains that are relatively the most uncertain, most problematic . For instance, an actor currently optimistic about obtaining positive interaction outcomes with family members, but currently being ignored by the boss at work, may sense that status outcomes at work are uncertain, and he may begin expending greater effort in pursuit of such status outcomes . Perhaps after a series of successes in achieving work-relevant outcomes, that actor might find it becoming problematic to achieve satisfying outcomes with family members . Consequently, the value of work domain outcomes may diminish, while the value of family domain outcomes might increase : he might start spending more time and energy initiating family transactions (e .g ., more picnics, beach outings, ball games, etc .) . In Emerson's theory, the structure of an actor's values (the preference order among value domains) is a dynamic system . The relative value of domains shifts with the changing vicissitudes of the relative uncertainty of domains . Uncertainty and Value in Low-Need and High-Need Situations Human actors, we suspect are by nature "problem solvers," meaning that outcomes obtained in problematic situations have enhanced value . This value component is most clearly displayed in play, games, and sport, where other bases of value, such as need, are very low . It is in the nature of sport that the outcome is uncertain and rules of the game form to preserve that condition . It is that condition, we assert, that arouses motivation and gives value to this category of successful outcome . . . . But the principle operates in non-play situations . . . also (Emerson 1987, p . 42) .
Reading somewhat "between the lines," this quote raises several important additional implications of Emerson's value theory . To explore these implications,
Expanding a Model of the "Whole Actor"
1 85
it is necessary to draw a sharp contrast between and elaborate a bit the "low-need" and "high-need" situations alluded to in the quote . A "low-need" situation might be illustrated by a child attempting to hit a target with a water-balloon at a midway attraction . This situation, or any situation of "play, game, or sport " is one where some measure of uncertainty is purposefully created as a way of enhancing the value of the outcome . If the child can accomplish the goal too easily, he will rapidly lose interest and if he cannot accomplish it easily enough, he will also rapidly lose interest . Maximum uncertainty leads to maximum interest and involvement in the game . This (or any similar) play, game, or sport example provides an opportunity for an actor to pursue satisfaction of what White (1959) called "the effectance urge," the motivational push to explore the limits of one's current level of competence and become more competent . As White made clear in his classic analysis, the effectance-competence principle tends to operate only or primarily when the actor is currently free of pressing deprivation-based ("drive-like") needs (e .g ., hunger, thirst, fatigue, worry, anxiety, etc .) . During such times, as he is engrossed in an effectance-based task, it seems likely the actor will experience what Csikszentmihalya (1978, p . 213) described as "the flow of experience ." That is, the actor "will experience a contraction of the perceptual field, a heightened concentration on the task at hand, a feeling of control leading to elation and finally to a loss of self-awareness that sometimes results in a feeling of transcendence, or a merging with the activity and the environment" (p . 213) . In stark contrast, a "high-need" situation might be illustrated by a person lost and wandering in the desert in search of water . Clearly, the actor does face an important deprivation-based "drive," thirst, a discomforting condition that impels actions aimed at finding water . In Emerson's terms, this actor requires units of a "needed input," and the greater the discrepancy between an actor's current state and a point of optimum (i .e ., the greater her/his thirst,) the greater the value that actor will place on an outcome unit in this (biological) value domain . Doing without sufficient (optimal) numbers of units of this valued outcome (drinks of water) will lead this "whole actor" to suffer objective impairment : his ability to continue producing actions (walking, searching, whatever) will soon diminish and eventually cease altogether Beyond and above the biological basis of value, however, uncertainty might also operate. If this actor, in his desert wanderings, locates enough water to survive and, indeed satisfy thirst, but the successes are variable and quite uncertain, making the "felt need" for water a common experience, Emerson's theory predicts that the actor will place even higher value on water as a domain than is dictated by biological need alone . That is, a biological need and a persistent action-environment contingency of uncertainty combine to augment the value of water . However, unlike a low-need situation of "play, game, or sport," uncertainty in this instance is not purposefully sought or created to enhance interest or involvement in the task at hand .
186
JOHN F . STOLTE
There are many other value domains besides water that might serve as a basis for deprivation-based value (food, money, love, respect, help, etc .) . Not getting sufficient (optimal) quantities of outcomes in these domains would also lead to the non-arbitrary, objective impairment of the "whole actor ." Frequently in social life, being deprived of optimal outcomes in such domains is an experience associated with occupancy of a disadvantaged position in a structure of power dependence (Emerson 1972 ; Cook 1987 ; Stolte 1990 ; Molm and Cook 1995) . If an employee is more dependent upon his employer than the employer is upon him, the employer is in a position to overcome resistance in the employee . The employer has the objective capacity to require actions that the employee might not want to emit . But such actions might be emitted to attain sufficient units of the valued outcome, money . And the employer might enhance the value this actor places on money by making employment seem quite uncertain . From the employee's point of view, work is a high-need situation, not "play," and uncertainty is not purposely created to enhance interest or involvement . From the employer's perspective, on the other hand, work might well be a low-need situation, indeed a game, where uncertainty and enhanced interest might be sought! 4 In summary, Emerson's framework is complex and rich with insights about an important realm of social psychology . But, as Cook (1987, p . 46) notes : "It remains to be finished and refined by those intrigued by the task of developing a `theory of value' ." 5 As a step toward clarifying and extending this interesting theory, we now raise and explore some questions that point to several promising pathways of possible development .
NEED, UNCERTAINTY, AND VALUE : OPERANT CONDITIONING VERSUS RATIONAL CHOICE Can the complex links among need, uncertainty, and value in Emerson's theory be clarified? As an initial step, we now examine how (a) operant conditioning and (b) rational choice bear on issues of value in social exchange . These frameworks helped to shape the very different formulations of social exchange constructed by both Emerson (1969, 1972) and Homans (1974) . In regard to these two theories, we limit the focus here to issues of value and choice behavior . Homans explicitly uses the "deprivation-satiation" principle from the operant behavioral approach as a major basis of value . As Homans (1974, p. 29) puts it : "The more often in the recent past a person has received a particular reward, the less valuable any further unit of that reward becomes for him ." Likewise, the behavioral principle underlying this statement also is entailed in Emerson's exchange theory, explaining why an actor seeks to stay above "optimum" in regard to various "needed" outcomes . The greater the "deprivation" in Homan's sense, the higher the "need" in Emerson's sense . Deprivation versus satiation, unmet needs versus met needs, are key components of the notion of value in both
Expanding a Model of the "Whole Actor"
187
VALENCE
A
B
uncertainty LOW
uncertainty HIGH C,
D
C2
VALENCE
Note:
*It is assumed that deprivation/need is constant and greater than zero
Figure 1 .
The Relationship Between Uncertainty And Value*
exchange theories . Also, for both Homans and Emerson deprivation/need is a strong determinant of choice behavior . Depending on deprivation/need, an actor might well allocate choices toward the attainment of outcomes from domain X (e .g . family affection) rather than domain Y (e .g ., work prestige) . Homans also explicitly uses the rational choice framework as a basis for his analysis of value . As he puts it, "In choosing between alternative actions, a person will choose that one for which, as perceived by him at the time, the value, V, of the result, multiplied by the probability, p, of getting the result, is greater" (P . 43) . Similarly, as noted above, Emerson's (1987) value theory clearly acknowledges that the rationality principle will govern the choice behavior of the whole actor under certain conditions . Beyond these basic similarities, however, Emerson's theory pursues issues of value much further than Homans' theory does, especially issues involving the intricate connections among deprivation/need, rationality, and uncertainty . To explore these issues, consider Figure 1 . Before discussing the conditions designated by letters (A-D) in Figure 1, we digress to examine some important background . Consider a hypothetical experiment involving higher primates as subjects . 6 Each animal is placed in a highly controlled laboratory situation . The environment is designed carefully to control the contingencies of reinforcement confronted by the animal, including the contingencies under which it can obtain food . Also, the environment is designed so as to allow the careful and precise recording of the animal's behavior, including its choice behavior. Imagine that each animal is initially trained within the experimental environment. During training, the animal is allowed to explore its environment and soon
1 88
JOHN F . STOLTE
learns that there are two lights (of different color) X and Y above two doors . When and only when the lights are illuminated, a button becomes operable on each door below each light, which, if pushed, opens the door and allows entry and access to a standard portion of food to eat . Assume that during the training period lights X and Y are repeatedly and simultaneously illuminated and in each case one button press on either door always makes food accessible in either room . Soon, in the language of operant conditioning, such training would establish the lights, X and Y, as equivalent "discriminative stimuli," with each light acquiring an equal capacity to signal the occasion for a response by the animal (a button press), which would open a door and would allow access to food (a reinforcing outcome) . In this context, each light, X and Y, can be said to have extrinsic/instrumental value for an animal . Under the conditions described, the value of light X would equal the value of light Y for the animal . Also, following the logic of the principle of deprivation/need, an animal will place greater value on both lights, the more deprived of food it has been in the recent past . Subsequent to such training, suppose that an experimental manipulation of environmental conditions is created . The environment is re-programmed, and each animal is placed in the environment for a specified number of discrete trials . During each trial, each light, X and Y, is simultaneously illuminated, but the button operation on the doors and thus the accessibility of food in the two rooms is systematically varied . That is the "reinforcement contingencies" for the two lights/rooms are varied by design . Light X and the room below it allow access to food on a fixed ratio = 4 schedule . That is, light X comes to signal a situation where every fourth button press opens the door and allows access to a standard portion of food . In contrast, light Y and the room below it allow access to food on a variable ratio = 4 schedule . That is, light Y comes to signal a situation in which, success in gaining room entry and access to food will occur randomly about a mean average offour button presses per success. Under these experimental conditions, at the end of the specified number of discrete trials, whether an animal has chosen X or Y, the button presses required and the number of standard food portions obtained will be equal . That is, both the behavioral effort required to get food and the deprivation/need for food will have been kept constant and equal . However, under these conditions, light X will have come to signal a very predictable situation of high certainty regarding access to food, while light Y will have come to signal a quite "problematic" situation of high uncertainty regarding access to food . ? With this hypothetical experiment as background, let us now return to Figure 1 and consider each condition in the two-dimensional space . Condition A in the Figure is most relevant to rational choice theory, which argues that an actor (whether human or primate) will attempt to maximize expected value whenever a choice must be made . Holding deprivation/need constant and greater than zero, subjects in the hypothetical experiment would be expected to place relatively greater value on domain X, the relatively more certain outcome domain, as compared with
Expanding a Model of the "Whole Actor"
1 89
domain Y, the relatively more uncertain domain . Thus, at the end of a set of discrete choice trials, rational choice theory would predict that the choice ratio X/Y < 1 .0 . By contrast, condition B in the Figure is most pertinent to Emerson's value theory, which argues that an actor will come to value a problematic outcome domain as a source of the intrinsic reward associated with satisfaction of the "effectance urge" (White 1959) . Holding deprivation/need constant and greater than zero, subjects in the hypothetical laboratory study would be expected to place relatively greater value on domain Y, the relatively more uncertain outcome domain, as contrasted with domain X, the relatively more certain domain . Therefore, at the conclusion of a set of discrete choice trials, Emerson's formulation predicts that the choice ratio X/Y > 1 .8 Condition C 1 in the Figure involves low uncertainty and low valence . One possible circumstance that might lead to this condition would be the extreme "optimism" described in Emerson's value theory . For example, an animal in the hypothetical experiment whose direct experience has provided a clear sense that success is assured on the door under light X might be supremely confident about action that can be undertaken in order to obtain food when hungry . Light X, its button, and door are, from a subject's perspective, a "solved problem ." Under the motivational logic of Emerson's theory, such a problem (assuming stability of the environmental situation) will gradually become less "interesting," more "routine," even more "boring" across time . Such feelings seem likely to emerge as correlates of this kind of decline in value . Again, contrary to expectations suggested by rational choice theory, the predicted choice ratio is X/Y > 1 .0 . Condition C2 in the figure also involves low uncertainty and low valence, but due to a quite different circumstance, one entailing the extreme "pessimism" covered in Emerson's theory . To capture this point, imagine a slightly different scenario in the hypothetical experiment . Suppose that the protocol is changed mid-way through the trial series so as to impose an "extinction" schedule on light/ door X . That is, a fixed ratio = 4 schedule of reinforcement is reprogrammed so that all reinforcement abruptly ceases . At that point, when light X becomes illuminated, no matter how many times an animal presses the button, the door fails to open, and no food is obtainable . Quite soon, under the logic of Emerson's value formulation, subjects would be expected to stop allocating choices to alternative X . Light/door X would decline in value, because, according to Emerson's motivational approach, an organism (whether primate or human) eventually stops wanting what it cannot obtain . Consequently, the choice ratio would, under such conditions, come to clearly favor option (light/door) Y (that is X/Y > 1 .0) . 9 Finally, consider condition D in Figure 1, which describes a circumstance of high uncertainty but low valence . This would be a condition quite contrary to the logic of Emerson's value theory . Accounting for this condition probably would entail individual difference/personality variables . Perhaps biological tempera-
190
JOHN F . STOLTE
ment (e .g ., general "energy" level or overall "vigor") would explain why a particular actor would not be as responsive to an opportunity to achieve effectance feedback as actors normally would be. Or, instead of biological factors, perhaps an actor's past learning history might explain a particular actor's low interest in an effectance-arousing environment . For example, a particular learning history might have created a generalized sense of "learned helplessness" (Seligman 1975) or low "self-efficacy" (Bandura 1977), diminishing an actor's interest in an "optimal challenge ." Condition D would predict a choice ratio of X/Y < 1 .0, as rational choice theory would, but due to individual difference factors rather than to a general tendency to maximize expected value . Clarifying the zone of uncertainty and its relationship to deprivation/need in the determination of value and choice behavior is, then, one important direction for the refinement of Emerson's theory. We now turn to a second important direction for refinement.
VALUES : INTRINSIC AND EXTRINSIC MOTIVATION How are both high-need and low-need situations involved within the dynamics of a "whole actor's" value system? This question concerns the cognitive, affective, behavioral, and interactional causes and consequences of both kinds of value situation considered together. Perhaps Emerson's insights can be extended by connecting his "high-need" situation with extrinsic motivation and his "low-need situation" with intrinsic motivation, as these two concepts are used in the framework on social motivation studied by Deci and Ryan (1987) . In this framework, the essential focus is the initiation and regulation of an actor's intentional behavior . Such behavior may be autonomous or it may be controlled . Autonomous actions connote to the actor "an inner endorsement . . . a sense that they emanate from oneself and are one's own" (Deci and Ryan 1987, p . 1025) . Being self-determined, autonomous actions are "done freely for the inherent satisfactions associated with certain activities and with undertaking optimal challenges" (p. 1033) . In contrast, controlled actions are resisted by the actor but reluctantly enacted to accommodate strong demands of an external situation or an intrapersonal factor (e .g ., conscience, addiction, personality trait) . Such actions are "characterized by greater rigidity and the experience of having to do what one is doing" (p . 1005) . An external context may support autonomy or it may impose control on an actor, depending upon the "functional significance" of that context for the actor (i .e ., depending on how the actor construes the meaning of the context [p . 1025]). 10 Considerable research has been done to clarify the conditions of context that lead an actor to interpret his actions as being either autonomous or controlled . The research has shown that an external reward contingency, threats, evaluations, deadlines, and surveillance tend to be construed by an actor as controlling rather
Expanding a Model of the "Whole Actor"
191
than as autonomy-supportive . Controlled actions are seen as extrinsically motivated in this approach . On the other hand, opportunities for personal choice or positive competence feedback tend to be construed as autonomy-supportive rather than controlled . Autonomous actions are seen as intrinsically motivated by Deci and Ryan . Finally, a body of research has shown that an actor whose autonomy is supported by external context or intrapsychic factors tends to have greater interest in and enjoyment of his actions, is more creative and cognitively flexible in such actions, expresses a more positive emotional tone and is less aggressive in such actions, has more trust in those who supervise such actions, and has better overall health (p . 1030). Linking Emerson's value theory with Deci and Ryan's research on motivation leads to other questions . From a motivational standpoint, is there an optimum combination of high-need/extrinsic/controlled value domains and low-need/ intrinsic/autonomous value domains for the "whole actor?" The consequences of autonomy outlined by Deci and Ryan suggest that the actor is likely to prefer to maximize low-need autonomy . On any given day, that actor might well be motivated to rise early for a game of golf with a good friend, move on to a relaxing picnic at the beach with family, and end the day tending a rose garden or surfing the Internet . And it seems likely that a less than optimal supply of opportunities for attaining such low-need/intrinsic outcomes would impair (or at least drastically diminish the quality of) the "whole actor's" ability to act . On the other hand, does the actor also objectively require some non-arbitrary quantity of outcomes available only within a high-need/extrinsic/controlled context? While an actor might prefer to maximize low-need autonomy, his long-term welfare in the real social world may depend on sufficient pursuit of outcomes in situations entailing high-need and control . An actor must pay his bills, and to do so must spend rather large amounts of time engaged in work actions involving an external reward contingency, pressure, evaluation, deadlines, and so on . Many such work actions are likely to be construed as mainly instrumental means rather than as experiences of "flow" to be pursued "like optimal challenges" "as an ends-in-themselves ." Yet, the "whole actor," depending upon many factors, might well be accommodated to the need to engage in actions which are merely means, not ends . In fact, it might be the case that confronting less than an optimal supply of challenges to pursue the attainment of high-need/extrinsic outcomes would also impair the "whole actor's" ability to act . Just what combination of the two kinds of value situation, high-need/extrinsic/ controlled and low-need/intrinsic/autonomous are optimal, is of course, not clear at present . Exploring this motivational question further might break new theoretical ground. At present, however, we turn to another related but distinct pathway that might be pursued in developing Emerson's value theory .
192
JOHN F . STOLTE
DECISION MAKING : RATIONAL VERSUS EMOTIONAL How are both "rational/cognitive" and "mindless/emotional" processes entailed in the behavioral decisions of the "whole actor?" As noted above, Emerson's theory suggests that within-domain behavior conforms to the traditional rational choice model of economics, while between-domain behavior conforms to some other model driven much less by cognitive deliberation and much more by unthinking emotion . The interplay between the two kinds of decision making seems crucial. Emotion-based value decisions, involving dimly understood reasons or a complete lack of consciousness, says Emerson, impel the actor to optimize across non-arbitrary, objectively necessary value domains . Such decisions serve as an adaptive brake on maximization, when maximization would impair the actor as a system . "Without an optimizing process an organism could die of thirst while maximizing on food ; a person could perish from society for want of social approval, while maximizing wealth" (Emerson 1987, p . 28) . Can this fascinating insight be elaborated? Perhaps so, when considered in light of an important approach to thinking and feeling advanced by Zajonc (1980) . Cognition and emotion may be linked in a dual system . As Zajonc sees it, these two sides of an actor's psyche derive from independent, parallel, interacting psychological systems (p . 154) . 11 An actor can feel in a certain way (positive or negative) about some stimulus (or social context), without having any cognitive awareness of or reportable thought about that stimulus (or context) . And the actor can act on that feeling (approach, avoid, exhibit some other action) without having any explicitly understood reason for such action . However, according to Zajonc, an actor cannot think about a stimulus (context) without having some discernible feeling about the stimulus (context), mild or strong . In short, feelings have primacy over thoughts . "In nearly all cases, however, feeling is not free of thought, nor is thought free of feelings" (p . 154) . As Zajonc states, "while feelings and thoughts both involve energy and information, the first class of experiences is heavier on energy, whereas the second is heavier on information" (p . 154) . As a system, feelings "transform sensory energy into autonomic or motor output," while thoughts "transform given information into new information" (p . 154). In a given experience, where there is a mix of feeling and thought, the heavier the feeling component, the "hotter" the cognition, and the heavier the thinking component, the "colder" the cognition . Within this dual system theory, Zajonc's description of decision-making bears a striking resemblance to the model hinted at by Emerson especially in reference to between-domain behavior . Decisions are another area where thought and affect stand in tension to each other . It is generally believed that all decisions require some conscious or unconscious processing of pros and cons . Some how we have come to believe, tautologically, to be sure, that if a decision has been made, then a cognitive process must have preceded it . Yet there is no evidence that this is
Expanding a Mode/ of the "Whole Actor"
193
indeed so. In fact, for most decisions, it is extremely difficult to demonstrate that there has actually been any prior cognitive process whatsoever. One might argue that these are cases in which one alternative so overwhelmingly dominates all the others that only a minimum of cognitive participation is required . . . . Quite often, "I decided in favor of X" is no more than "I liked X" . Most of the time, information collected about alternatives serves us less for making a decision than for justifying it afterward (p . 155) .
In Zajonc's framework, feelings (as opposed to thoughts) are often "inescapable," that is, very difficult to control voluntarily, "holistic," that is, aroused by very broad and crude rather than precise and fine features of a stimulus (context), and "irrevocable," that is, trusted as inherently valid rather than being open to question . Finally, and importantly, feelings (as opposed to thoughts) are "difficult or impossible to accurately verbalize" to oneself or to others, although they can be and usually are very efficiently communicated to others through nonverbal means (facial expressions, posture, stance, voice inflection, etc .) . In other words, feelings, in contrast to thoughts, derive from a psychological system that is "pre-linguistic ." Drawing a connection between Emerson's value theory and Zajonc's dual system approach raises other questions . From a decision-making standpoint, is there an optimal oscillation between "rational/cognitive" and "mindless/emotional" choice behavior for the "whole actor?" Emerson's theory quite clearly implies that the actor will become impaired in a non-arbitrary, objective way, unless he can sense when it best to rationally maximize within a value domain and when it best to emotionally optimize across alternative value domains . An actor diligently at work in sales, perhaps, would be expected to make decisions among alternatives in an effort to maximize expected value in that domain . Decisions among alternative means are likely to be "information heavy" choices, based on much deliberation, and a concern for instrumental expedience . As he oscillates to a different model of decision making, one in which the choice is "energy heavy," based on no cognitions or relatively "hot" cognitions, this diligent, rational salesperson might defy rationality, cancel a potentially lucrative meeting with a customer, and rush from the office to the dance studio to capture a proud family moment, a daughter's last dance performance of the season . 12 Perhaps acquiring the ability to oscillate in an optimal way between these two modes of decision-making is at the heart of being socially well-adapted . We need to know far more about this issue than we do at present . But at this point we turn from this issue to a final pathway that seems promising to explore in an effort to extend Emerson's value theory .
DELINEATING VALUE DOMAINS : A SOCIOCULTURAL SPECIFICATION As noted above, a theory of value must deal systematically with the demarcation of the value domains composing the environment of the "whole actor." One way
194
JOHN F . STOLTE
to do so is to employ the abstract criterion that states : "Any two valued things are in the same value domain if acquisition of one reduces the unit value of the other" (Emerson 1987, p . 15) . While using this criterion does make the task of general theory construction manageable, its exclusive use raises a question : Is this criterion so abstract that it leaves out detail a social psychological theory of value needs to include? Emerson elsewhere noted that "as propositions become more general they tell us less and less about more and more" (Emerson 1969, p . 382) . And the "less and less," pushed beyond a certain point, might be considered an informational cost too great to pay . Is there a way to descend the ladder of abstraction a step or two, thus including sociological detail too important to leave out, while still allowing the domain delineation problem to be dealt with in a manageable way? An affirmative answer to this question is entertained here . This answer emerges from speculative ruminations on a theory of elementary psychological models proposed by Fiske (1991) considered in light of several ideas about exchange discussed by Blau (1964) . These ruminations suggest that Emerson's abstract criterion may be supplemented with a sociocultural specification of value domains . Fiske : Four Elementary Psychological Models
In an impressive review of a vast, diverse body of work drawn from psychology, sociology, and anthropology, Fiske (1991, pp . 13-39) identifies four very fundamental psychological models, communal sharing, equality matching, authority ranking, and market pricing . He argues that these models are endogenous templates or schemas, pre-wired like Chomsky's "generative grammar" into the human brain . People tend universally to structure their sociocultural experiences (tend to think, feel, act, and interact) in ways dictated by these models . Obvious cross-cultural variations merely represent influences of unique historical conditions of time and place, shaping how people create distinctive combinations and concatenations of the four models, as they construct social relationships, groups, and institutions . But even across dramatically different social systems, preliterate or modern, Western or Eastern, Fiske sees the same underlying models at work. Communal sharing defines a social context best illustrated by kinship or kinship-like relationships (e.g ., families, certain religious or political groups) . When people are socially united in communal sharing, they mutually display a very high level of solidarity, unity, belonging, and identification . They tend to think, feel, act, and interact with kindness and generosity . The overriding collective concern is that the needs of the individual be met by the group . The unity of the communal sharing group is so great that individuals' unique personalities more or less disappear : the "I" becomes the "We ." Equality matching defines a social context best illustrated by a relationship between two friends . Individuals thus linked tend to think, feel, act, and interact
Expanding a Model of the "Whole Actor"
195
in ways that insure "one-to-one reciprocity ." A helpful favor done by Ralph for Margaret on one occasion, will be returned more or less in kind by Margaret for Ralph on a later occasion . The overriding concern of an equality matching relationship is to ensure that balanced compensation, the mutual receipt of exactly equal benefits, is preserved between peers . Fiske notes that the personalities of friends linked in an equality matching relationship remain distinct, rather than being blended into a single unity as in communal sharing . But such distinctions do not imply "better and worse" or "higher and lower ." Authority ranking, by contrast, does define a social context of legitimate, transitive, asymmetry, and unequal social relations . Such a context can be well illustrated by the ways that people think, feel, act, and interact in a work setting . The flow of command and control is from an actor located in a relatively higher status position to another actor(s) located in a relatively lower position . Benefits (e .g ., influence, prestige, pay) are distributed in proportion to the status of one's position. In Fiske's view, individuals in higher and lower positions all accept the hierarchical structure of authority ranking as legitimate . Subordinates willingly obey and defer to superiors, and superiors enthusiastically help, protect, and guide subordinates . The unequal flow of benefits is taken by all to be fair . Market pricing defines a social context in which people are related impersonally, guiding their thoughts, feelings, actions, and interactions rationally in reference to an external, objective standard of economic value, such as money price or economic utility . The standard of value is determined by a relevant market . The relationship between an automobile buyer and seller well illustrates this kind of social context . There is very little of a mutual personal nature in such a relationship . Each actor jointly focuses instead on what the car is objectively worth in money, as determined by the wider automobile market . The essential shared purpose pursued by actors in this kind of relationship is to settle on an agreement to transfer the car for a specified amount of money . Fiske orders the four models described above "ontologically," that is, in terms of a postulated invariant order of appearance in normal human personality development . The inexorable, unfolding stages of growth he posits are as follows : first, communal sharing, second, authority ranking, third, equality matching, and fourth, market pricing . The normally developing human being, in short, will tend to become able gradually to enact the thoughts, feelings, actions, and interactions governed by each model in this sequence . While Fiske's proposed principle of ordering the four models is important in its own right, we now consider an alternative way in which the four models might be ordered : socioculturally . Blau : Universalistic/Extrinsic Benefits and Particularistic/Intrinsic Benefits in Exchange
In one of the early classics on exchange, Blau borrows from Parsons's (1950) work on "universalism-particularism" to distinguish :
1 96
JOHN F . STOLTE
between associations that are intrinsically rewarding and those that furnish extrinsic benefits, which are, in principle, detachable from the association itself (Blau 1964, p. 35) . He notes that "intrinsic attachments fundamentally alter the social transactions in interpersonal relations . The basic difference is between associations that are considered ends-in-themselves by participants and those they consider means for some further ends . Blau (1964, p. 36) expands this distinction, noting : "Extrinsic benefits constitute objective criteria for comparing associates, choosing between them, and abandoning one in favor of another . They are independent standards for determining whether a person's choice of associates is rational or not ." And Blau (1964, p . 36) proceeds : "Associations that are intrinsically rewarding, however, are unique in the sense that they cannot be compared except in purely subjective terms of the gratification they provide.
On the basis of Blau's distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic benefits in exchange, one can sort Fiske's models into two basic categories with two ordered sub-domains in each. Socially Intrinsic Value Domains : Communal Sharing and Equality Matching One category of sociocultural value domain can be described as socially intrinsic. In this category, an actor can usually obtain outcomes from other people whose value is inseparable from those other people . In a basic way, the people are the valued outcomes, and their value stems from a "particularistic" basis, being anchored in unique, idiosyncratic personal qualities . Further, emotion probably has primacy over cognition in a socially intrinsic value domain . The thoughts actors have about one another are likely to be heavier on energy than information (i .e ., likely to be Zajonc's "hotter" cognitions), and the decisions actors make toward one another are likely to be more "mindless/emotional" than "rational/ cognitive ." Thus, Fiske's "communal sharing" model, as represented by kinship or kin-like relationships would clearly fall into this category . An actor's transactions with members of his family (or members of a family-like group) result in outcomes whose value is an inextricable part of those others as unique individuals . For example, a son's academic and athletic performances may be outcomes valued by a contemporary father, not because they are rationally appraised against objective standards of excellence that apply universally to all male students at the son's school . Rather, they are valued by the father as inherent qualities of the son as a unique person . Also, Fiske's "equality matching" model, as represented by a friendship, reasonably seems to fall into this socially intrinsic category . An actor's transactions with a friend result in outcomes whose value cannot be separated from the friend as a particular person . For example, an actor may be delighted by the humorous banter he receives from a friend, not because such behavior is rationally assessed against an objective standard of comedic competence, but rather because the
Expanding a Model of the "Whole Actor"
197
funny banter is socially intrinsic to the friend, part of the friend as "an end, not a means ." Given the primacy of emotion over cognition within the socially intrinsic kind of value domain, the two domain sub-types can also be ordered . Generally, one would expect that communal sharing outcomes will tend to have a greater value than equality matching outcomes, with the variation being determined by the relative emotional significance of the people who are the source of the outcomes . Academic and athletic performances provided by a son are likely to be of higher value to a father than humorous banter provided by a friend, because the son is more emotionally significant to the actor in question than the friend . Socially Extrinsic Value Domains : Authority Ranking and Market Pricing
A second category of sociocultural value domain can be described as socially extrinsic, that is, a category in which an actor can usually obtain outcomes from other people whose value is separable from those other people . Quite detachable from other people as sources, such outcomes can be rationally assessed against objective, impersonal ("universalistic") standards of worth . Also, cognition probably has primacy over emotion in a socially extrinsic value domain. The thoughts actors have about one another are likely to be heavier on information than energy (i .e ., likely to be Zajonc's "colder" cognitions), and the decisions actors make toward one another are likely to be more "rational/cognitive" than "mindless/ emotional ." Fiske's "authority ranking" model would probably fall into this socially extrinsic category . The outcomes achieved through transactions with other people with whom an actor is linked in an authority ranking relationship can usually be rationally appraised against universalistic standards of value . For example, a contemporary teacher or coach (in contrast to a father) may value a student's academic or athletic performance . But, in this instance, the performance can be easily detached from the person who provides it, and can be assessed against an external standard of scholastic or athletic excellence, which applies universally across all similar students . Finally, Fiske's "market pricing" seems to fit quite neatly into the socially extrinsic type of value domain . Par excellence, market pricing transactions entail a separation of the outcomes from the individuals who mediate them . Thus, for example, a prospective automobile buyer may value the car he is considering for purchase, but the car can be easily detached from the salesperson who is attempting to sell it, and can be evaluated quite rationally in terms its objective market value . Because of the primacy of cognition over emotions within the socially extrinsic value domain, the two domain sub-types are also ordered . Ordinarily, one would expect that market pricing outcomes will tend to have value that is more precise
198
JOHN F . STOLTE
and explicit than authority ranking outcomes, with the variation being determined by the level of measurement that usually distinguishes the two domains . As Fiske (1991) notes, issues arising in an authority ranking relationship are usually reckoned in terms of an ordinal scale (more or less, higher or lower, better or worse), while issues arising in a market pricing relationship are considered in light of an interval (usually ratio) scale (i .e ., exactly how much money is some object worth). The higher the level of measurement, the more information provided . Linking Emerson's value theory with these ideas borrowed from Fiske and Blau, leads to several additional questions . In reference to an objective structure of sociocultural opportunities, is there some non-arbitrary optimum combination of socially intrinsic and socially extrinsic outcomes required by the "whole actor?" Again, it seems plausible, as Emerson suggested, that an actor may become objectively impaired without sufficient outcome units from both kinds of domains . Does an actor make rational work decisions of higher quality, if he has obtained a sufficient amount of family affection? Can an actor transact more affectionate exchanges with family members, if he has obtained optimal amounts of work prestige and money income? For those who seek to finish and refine Emerson's theory of value, it seems worthwhile to pursue questions like these .
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS Several goals were pursued in the above analysis . First, essential ideas contained in Emerson's (1987) paper on value were selectively reviewed . The review was not only selective (leaving out many intricate conceptual and mathematical details), it was also quite interpretive . It argued that Emerson's concept of the "whole actor" is axial to a comprehensive theory of value, and it contended that this concept prompts extension of the theory along several specific pathways . Second, the operant conditioning and rational choice frameworks were brought to bear on the complex issues surrounding the links between need, uncertainty, and value in an attempt to explicate several central but obscure ideas in Emerson theory of value . Third, it was suggested that while Emerson's value theory, especially as it bears on power-dependence/exchange, emphasizes extrinsic value, the theory can and should incorporate intrinsic value also . A line of theory and research by Deci and Ryan on motivation was discussed as a source of key ideas that might be usefully related to Emerson's value framework . It was argued that the "whole actor" is energized by both intrinsic and extrinsic value concerns, and that theoretical progress toward clarifying how these concerns jointly operate to approach or depart from optimum needs to be pursued . Fourth, it was noted that Emerson's value theory provides implicit clues regarding the outlines of a complex model of behavioral decision making . This model seems to entail both rational/cognitive and mindless/emotional choice behavior . It
Expanding a Model of the "Whole Actor"
199
was contended that this model can and should be elaborated in light of crucial insights proposed in Zajonc's dual system approach to thinking and feeling . It was asserted that the "whole actor" might well oscillate between "rational/cognitive" and "mindless/emotional" decision making, and that what is now needed is a clarification of how these two complex facets of behavioral decision making jointly operate to approach or depart from optimum . Fifth, Emerson's criterion for delineating distinctive environmental value domains was considered . The aptness of this highly abstract device as a simplifying tool for building a general theory was acknowledged. However, it was argued that a sociocultural specification of value domains would still allow for a general theory but would bring in important and necessary substantive detail . The specification proposed here was based on Fiske's four psychological models considered in light of Blau's and Parsons' distinction between extrinsic/universalistic benefits and intrinsic/particularistic benefits of exchange . Questions were entertained about how an actor might achieve outcomes jointly across both socially intrinsic and socially extrinsic domains to approach or depart from optimum . In conclusion, this paper has sought to raise and explore some broad questions in an effort to chart several important directions for clarifying and extending Emerson's theory of value . If successful, these questions will lead to further specification and clarification of the central concepts and principles only hinted at in the formulation . Also, if successful, the work undertaken here will provide a basis for future empirical research . A promising initial focus of such work is study of the relationship between uncertainty and value . Obviously, there is much additional work to be accomplished . But Emerson's formulation of value is social psychologically important, and the present analysis suggests promising directions for such work .
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This is a revised and expanded version of a paper presented in the Social Psychology Section Miniconference: Social Exchange and Rational Choice at the meetings of the American Sociological Association meetings, San Francisco, August 1998 .
NOTES 1 . The concept of "optimum" is tautological . But, tautologies, concepts that are true by definition, often play a useful, even essential, role in theories . Their use, however, lies in the help they provide in spelling out key theoretical ideas . Such tautologies only become problematic if they are advanced as if they were testable propositions, which they are not . However, even if the notion of optimum is not itself testable, the value theory of which it is a part is testable . Note the link posited below between uncertainty and value . 2. Since Emerson wrote his paper, which was published posthumously in 1987, a massive literature has developed around the rational choice model . Arguably, at present this model dominates
200
JOHN F . STOLTE
social science research . Still, some scholars have argued convincingly and shown empirically that the rational choice model is severely limited as a descriptive (i .e., empirical) theory of human choice behavior (see, for examples, Herrnstein 1990 ; Green and Shapiro 1994) . 3 . Although Emerson does not explicitly say so, one wonders whether this "sense" might vary between a cognitively elaborate (even formally calculated) estimate of the contingency to a non-articulated (largely emotional) apprehension of the contingency . 4 . Although Emerson is known almost exclusively for his power-dependence theory of exchange (Cook 1987 ; Molm and Cook 1995), which emphasizes high-need value situations, he had a definite interest in low-need (effectance-competence) situations as well (Emerson 1966, 1970) . 5 . Eight years after Cook's observation, there was a renewed call for a refinement of Emerson's behavioral theory of value : "One impediment to research . . . on these fundamental exchange processes has been the lack of a fully developed theory of value" (see Emerson 1987 for a rudimentary effort) (Molm and Cook 1995, p . 229). 6 . This hypothetical illustration is a highly simplified and selective adaptation drawn from procedures proposed by Emerson (1970) for experimental research on value . A copy of the technical paper in which these procedures are proposed is available from the present author upon request . 7 . Emerson (1972, pp. 52-53) cites some of the vast body of operant research on the effects of "intermittent (fixed or variable ratio and interval) schedules" of reinforcement that influenced his ideas on exchange and value . See also Dragoi and Staddon(1999), Davis and colleagues (1993) and Williams (1994) for more recent operant research relevant to the dynamics of conditioning and to recurrent choice behavior. Also relevant to issues raised about rationality, considered from the operant point of view, Herrnstein (1990) focuses on an operant conditioning situation of a "distributed choice," in which an animal has two sources of valued outcome between which it can alternately choose across a longitudinal series of discrete trials . The alternative outcome sources are governed by two distinct schedules of reinforcement, a variable-interval schedule, and variable-ratio schedule . Research has consistently shown that animals do not choose so as to rationally maximize reinforcement, but, instead, choose in a pattern that produces "sub-optimal" levels of reinforcement . Herrnstein explains such "irrational" choice behavior in terms of (a) "melioration," that is, a tendency to shift the allocation of effort expended in making choices to the alternative source that is more immediately lucrative (has a higher rate of reinforcement), and (b) "matching," that is, " . . .behavior is distributed across alternatives so as to equalize the reinforcements per unit of behavior invested in each alternative" (Hermstein 1990, p . 360) There is much yet to be learned about the effects on choice behavior of various schedules of alternative value domains . Emerson's theory is interested in a much simpler part of the process of choice than is Herrnstein, focusing on the role of uncertainty as operationalzed by a variable versus fixed ratio schedule. 8 . Following White (1959), intrinsic motivation spurred by the "effectance-competence" urge is high when deprivation/need ("drive" or "homeostatic crisis"), hunger in the hypothetical experiment, is relatively low. 9 . Interestingly, research shows that a pattern of operant behavior, such as an allocation of choices, which was developed on a schedule of high certainty (e .g ., a fixed ratio schedule) will tend to "extinguish" much more rapidly than one developed on a schedule of high uncertainty (e .g ., a variable ratio schedule) . This well-established operant research finding seems to provide at least some indirect empirical support for the Emerson's notion that uncertainty and value are related as asserted by the theory . 10. Deci and Ryan's concept of "functional significance" seems closely congruent with many ideas and assumptions in certain versions of symbolic interaction theory (Stryker 1980) . 11 . We emphasize Zajonc's (1980) analysis here, recognizing, as he does, that Paivio (1978) independently arrived at an approach ("dual-coding theory") sharing many of the same basic ideas as those put forward by Zajonc .
Expanding a Mode/ of the "Whole Actor"
201
12 . Quite consistent with Zajonc's (1980) work, is a recent surge of interest in dual process theories in social psychology (Chaiken and Trope 1999) . An interesting variant among these theories is Epstein and Pacini's (1999) "cognitive-experiential self-theory ." Like Zajonc, Epstein pictures an actor as responding in terms of (a) a relatively affective experiential system driven by concrete considerations of pleasure and pain, and (b) a relatively abstract, analytic rational system guided by logic, reason, and language . A line of experimental research conducted by Epstein and his colleagues has shown that the two systems, experiential and rational, exist, mutually interact, and often conflict . Thus, even though a person may "know" rationally that a belief is superstitious, he may nevertheless have such a belief. Most of the experimental research reported thus far by Epstein and his colleagues has focused on demonstrating that the two systems exist and operate in a complex interrelationship . A comprehensive account of the conditions under which either system will have primacy has not yet been developed . Clearly, an important topic for future research will be to specify the conditions which stimulate the predominance of experiential/affective processing and the conditions which stimulate the predominance of rational/analytic processing . An intriguing task for future work will be to explore how features of social life, as pictured through the lens of exchange theory, might be involved in triggering the ascendance of either the affective/experiential or the rational/logical system .
REFERENCES Bandura, A . 1977 . "Self-Efficacy : Toward a Unifying Theory of Behavioral Change ." Psychological Review 84 : 191-225 . Blau, P. 1964. Exchange and Power in Social Life . New York : John Wiley and Sons. Chaiken, S ., and Y . Trope, eds . 1999 . Dual-Process Theories in Social Psychology . New York: Guilford Press . Cook, K . 1987 . Social Exchange Theory. edited by K . Cook. Newbury Park, CA : Sage . Csiksyentmihalyi, M . 1978 . "Intrinsic Rewards and Emergent Motivation ." In The Hidden Costs of Reward : New Perspectives on the Psychology of Human Motivation, edited by M . Repper and D . Greene . Hillsdale, NJ : Lawrence Erlbaum Associates . Davis, D . G . S ., J. E . R . Staddon, A . Machado, and R. G . Palmer. 1993 . "The Process of Recurrent Choice ." Psychological Review 100 : 320-341 . Deci, E., and R . Ryan . 1987 . "The Support of Autonomy and the Control of Behavior ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 53 : 1024-1037 . Dragoi, V ., and J. E. R . Staddon . 1999 . "The Dynamics of Operant Conditioning ." Psychological Review 106 : 20-61 . Emerson, R . 1966 . "Mount Everest : A Case Study of Communication Feedback and Sustained Group Goal Striving ." Sociometry 29 : 213-227 . Emerson, R . 1969 . "Operant Psychology and Exchange Theory ." In Behavioral Sociology, edited by R . Burgess and D. Bushell . New York : Columbia University Press . Emerson, R. 1970. "Effectance and Uncertainty : Studies of Motivation in Problematic Situations ." University of Washington, Institute for Sociological Research . Technical Paper ISR:70-10. Emerson, R . 1972 . "Exchange Theory : Part I ." In Sociological Theories in Progress, edited by J . Berger, M . Zelditch, and B . Anderson . New York: Houghton Mifflin . Emerson, R. 1987 . "Toward a Theory of Value in Social Exchange ." In Social Exchange Theory, edited by K. Cook . Newbury Park, CA: Sage . Epstein, S ., and R. Pacini. 1999 . "Some Basic Issues Regarding Dual-Process Theories from the Perspective of Cognitive-Experiential Self-Theory ." In Dual-Process Theories in Social Psychology, edited by S. Chaiken, and Y . Trope . New York : Guilford Press. Fiske, A. 1991 . Structures of Social Life : The Four Elementary Forms of Human Relations. New York : The Free Press .
202
JOHN F . STOLTE
Green, D ., and I. Shapiro . 1994 . Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory. New Haven, CT : Yale University Press. Herrnstein, R. 1990. "Rational Choice Theory : Necessary But Not Sufficient." American Psychologist 45 : 356-367 . Homans, G . 1974 . Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms. New York : Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich, Inc . Molm, L ., and K. Cook. 1995 . "Social Exchange and Exchange Networks ." Pp . 209-235 in Sociological Perspectives on Social Psychology, edited by K. Cook, G . Fine, and J . House . Boston, MA: Allyn and Bacon . Parsons, T. 1950. The Social System . Glencoe, IL: The Free Press . Paivio, A. 1986 . Mental Representations: A Dual Coding Approach . New York: Oxford University Press. Seligman, M . 1975 . Helplessness: On Depression Development and Death. San Francisco : Freeman . Stolte, J. 1990 . "Power Processes in Structures of Dependence and Exchange ." Pp . 129-150 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol . 7, edited by E . Lawler, B . Markovsky, C . Ridgeway, and H. Walker. Greenwich, CT : JAI Press. Stryker, S . 1980 . Symbolic Interactionism . Menlo Park, CA : Benjamin/Cummings . White, R . 1959 . "Motivation Reconsidered : The Concept of Competence ." Psychological Review 66: 297-330 . Williams, B . 1994 . "The Role of Probability of Reinforcement in Models of Choice ." Psychological Review 101 : 704-707 . Zajonc, R. 1980 . "Feeling and Thinking : Preferences Need No Inferences ." American Psychologist 35 :151-175 .
CULTURAL CONTEXTS AND DEVELOPMENTAL PROCESSES IN ADOLESCENT-PARENT RELATIONSHIPS
Judith G . Smetana
ABSTRACT Social psychologists interested in the study of group processes have largely ignored social interactions in the context of the family . In contrast, much of the research in developmental psychology has focused on parent-child interactions and how they facilitate children's and adolescents' social and emotional development and adjustment. This chapter focuses on one aspect of family interactions, parent-adolescent conflict, and describes the results of an ongoing program of research that investigated adolescents' and parents' interpretations of conflicts, or the meaning different family members ascribe to their disputes . Research employing middle-class European-American and African-American families and lower-class Chinese adolescents in Hong Kong is used to illustrate cultural differences and similarities in types of conflicts, conflict frequency and intensity, reasoning about conflicts, and conflict resolution. The proposition advanced here is that adolescent-parent conflict helps to transform and restructure family relationships and to facilitate adolescent develop-
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 203-227 . Copyright © 2000 by JAI Press Inc . All rights of reproduction in any form reserved. ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 203
204
JUDITH G . SMETANA
ment . These findings challenge researchers interested in group processes to develop models that describe how groups change and evolve in response to conflict .
The study of group processes has a long history in social psychology . Social psychologists typically have examined group processes in laboratory settings among groups that have been experimentally constituted, usually to examine some power structure or social arrangement that exists in the broader society . In much of this research, groups exist only for the short duration of the experiment, and group processes are studied among individuals with no prior history of social interaction (Heise 1995) . Although there have been some early attempts, most notably by Parsons and his colleagues (1955), to develop models of group processes in the family and to describe separate family subsystems such as parent-child and sibling interactions in terms of task groups and roles, research and theorizing about the family as a social interaction setting has not progressed much beyond this early work (but see Grusky, Bonacich, and Peyrot 1988 and Steelman and Powell 1996 for exceptions) . In contrast, developmental psychologists examine naturally constituted groups such as the family . Families differ from the task groups examined in most social-psychological research in that they are enduring and have emotionally complex histories of social interactions-features that are considered to be confounds in the context of small groups research (Steelman and Powell 1996) . Recent social-psychological research has indicated that when experimental research participants in an ad-hoc group are told that they will meet again, these instructions change the nature of the interactions . Thus, the available research on ad-hoc groups may not have much applicability to family processes . Much of the research on social development is concerned with how family interactions facilitate children's and adolescents' social and emotional development (see Grusec and Goodnow 1994 ; Maccoby and Martin 1983 for reviews) . In particular, parent-child interactions have been demonstrated to be of particular importance to children's social development and long-term adjustment. Although much of this research has focused on emotionally positive interactions, there is a long tradition in the social development literature of studying affectively negative interactions, such as conflict . Conflict also has been central to sociologists interested in group processes (e .g., Deutsch 1958) . Positive equilibrium models, which dominate the field, propose that group members either leave the group or work to reestablish equilibrium in response to conflict . But these models may have limited utility in explaining how conflict is addressed in families . The physical proximity and long-term commitments of family members make conflicts difficult to escape, and as discussed in detail in this chapter, although families do work to resolve conflicts, the processes involved and resolutions achieved do not necessarily reflect a return to the preexisting equilibrium . Because social and emotional development occurs primarily in the context of the family, particularly for young
Cultural Contexts and Processes
205
children, family conflict (considered here in terms of parent-child conflict) may have important consequences for both individual development and relationship change (Emery 1992) . In this chapter I discuss adolescent-parent conflict from a developmental perspective . As a researcher interested in adolescent-parent interaction, my research has examined adolescent-parent conflict from a developmental social-cognitive perspective that focuses on children's reasoning and knowledge about different facets of their social world . In particular, I have focused on adolescents' and parents' interpretations of conflict, or the meaning they ascribe to their disputes . In contrast to the positive equilibrium models just discussed, my view is that adolescent-parent conflict helps to transform and restructure (rather than preserve the existing structure of) family relationships and to facilitate adolescent development . This proposition is elaborated in the following sections . The chapter begins with an overview of how adolescent-parent relationships have been viewed within developmental psychology . Then, I present findings from my research on adolescent-parent conflict in different cultural and subcultural settings . Findings pertaining to different components of conflict, including the incidence, frequency, and intensity of conflict, the content of adolescent-parent disputes, and conflict resolution strategies are discussed . Next, findings pertaining to how adolescents and parents discuss, negotiate, and interpret their disputes are presented, and the implications of these findings for understanding adolescent development and family relationship change during adolescence are discussed . Finally, the implications of this research for understanding group processes are discussed .
CHANGING VIEWS OF ADOLESCENT-PARENT CONFLICT Researchers interested in adolescent development long have considered conflict to be an important feature of adolescent-parent relationships . Stemming from work by early psychoanalytic and neo-psychoanalytic theorists (Blos 1982 ; A . Freud 1937), adolescence has been depicted as a normative period of rebellion (referred to as "storm and stress") entailing frequent and intense conflicts with parents . According to this view, healthy adolescence is seen to entail challenge, defiance, turbulent adolescent-parent conflict, and ultimately, detachment from parents, and conflict and rebellion are seen as normative and adaptive responses to the biological changes of puberty . This destructive view of adolescent-parent conflict continues to inform popular views of adolescence . However, empirical support for the neo-psychoanalytic view was based primarily on samples comparing normal families with clinic-referred families or with families experiencing behavior problems . Empirical research on much more representative samples of adolescents, conducted largely in response to the psychoanalytic view, has indicated that for the majority
206
JUDITH G . SMETANA
of adolescents, intense conflict and rebellion are the exception . The current consensus among researchers is that although adolescence does not normatively entail extreme psychological turmoil, it may be marked by disagreements, bickering, emotional tensions, and minor conflicts with parents over the everyday details of family life (see Collins and Laursen 1992 ; Holmbeck 1996 ; Laursen and Collins 1994; Laursen, Coy, and Collins 1998 ; Paikoff and Brooks-Gunn 1991 ; Steinberg 1990 for reviews) . According to this more pacific view, emotional bonds between parents and children are maintained during adolescence, and conflict is seen as a temporary perturbation in parent-adolescent relationships . Nevertheless, adolescent-parent conflict continues to be a topic of great interest among researchers, perhaps because conflict has been described both as a natural component of close relationships (Collins and Laursen 1992 ; Holmbeck 1996) and as a normative response to the rapid biological and cognitive changes of early adolescence (Holmbeck 1996 ; Holmbeck, Paikoff, and Brooks-Gunn 1995 ; Steinberg 1990) . Although different explanations have been offered for the underlying processes, conflict is seen to transform the unilateral parent-child relationships of middle childhood to the more mutual relations of late adolescence and young adulthood (Youniss and Smollar 1985) . For instance, Hill and his colleagues (Hill 1988 ; Hill and Holmbeck 1987) have asserted that increased conflict is adaptive because it changes the power balance of the family by making disagreements overt, which in turn, leads to readjustments in family relationships . Much of the available research has focused on describing the frequency and intensity of conflict in families with adolescents . Although adolescent-parent conflict occurs over mundane, everyday issues, ample evidence indicates that it has much larger significance in parents' and adolescents' lives . As Offer (1969) stated in an early investigation, "We emphasize that the rebellion has vital and important meaning to the adolescent in this stage of his development . . . . The great majority of parents say that the early adolescent years (12 to 13) are the most difficult time they have in raising their children" (p. 186) . Yet little research has examined the meaning of conflict to parents and adolescents . Social psychologists interested in close relationships have asserted that to understand individuals' behavior, it is necessary to find out how they represent their circumstances to themselves (Duck and Pond 1989 ; Kelly 1955) . Social-cognitive analyses can be particularly useful in illuminating the way different family members conceptualize their relationships and were the focus of the research described here . Briefly stated, the proposition elaborated here is that due to their different social positions in the family and divergences in the developmental tasks they face, adolescents and parents have different and incompatible perspectives on a variety of everyday issues . Their inability to agree or to coordinate these perspectives leads to disagreements and conflicts over the everyday details of family . Conflict is seen as providing a context for parents and children to articulate and discuss their divergent perspectives, which in turn, leads to changes in those perspectives and transformations in family relationships .
Cultural Contexts and Processes
207
These propositions have been developed and examined in research conducted over the past 15 years . As is the case with much developmental research (Graham 1992), the initial studies focused primarily on European-American, middle-class families (Smetana 1988 1989, 1995d ; Smetana and Asquith 1994 ; Smetana, Braeges, and Yau 1991 ; Smetana, Yau, Restrepo, and Braeges 1991) . However, developmental psychologists increasingly have recognized the importance of the cultural contexts of development (Cooper 1999 ; Garcia Coll and Magnuson 1999 ; Shweder, Goodnow, Hatano, LeVine, Markus, and Miller 1998) . Likewise, my research has broadened to consider adolescent-parent relationships in different cultural and intracultural contexts, including Chinese adolescents in Hong Kong (Yau and Smetana 1996) and more recently, China (Yau and Smetana in preparation), as well as middle-class African-American families (Smetana in preparation ; Smetana and Gaines 1999) . This research is highlighted here to illustrate both broad themes and cultural variations in adolescent-parent relationships .
CULTURAL VIEWS OF ADOLESCENT-PARENT CONFLICT One widely employed conceptualization of culture has been to distinguish cultures along the global dimensions of individualism and collectivism (Markus and Kitayama 1991 ; Shweder 1990 ; Shweder et al . 1998 ; Shweder and Sullivan 1993 ; Triandis 1989, 1990) . Individualistic cultures are seen to stress self-sufficiency, personal goals, autonomy, and detachment from others . In further elaborations, Markus and Kitayama (1991 ; see also Shweder et al . 1998) have proposed that individualistic cultures promote the development of independent construals of the self, which entail a view of the self as separate from the social context, unique, and able to express oneself and promote one's own goals . Contemporary American society has been described as a prototypically individualistic culture . Indeed, recent commentators have gone further and described mainstream American society as suffering from a radical individualism that is characterized by isolation, separation, and a focus on personal fulfillment over the needs of the larger community (Bellah, Madsen, Sullivan, Swidler, and Tipton 1985) . Collectivist cultures, in contrast, are seen as oriented toward authority, tradition, and duty and as stressing interdependence and harmony in interpersonal relationships . Collectivist cultures also promote interdependent construals of the self, which are described as entailing connectedness with the social context, indirectness in social interactions, a focus on statuses, roles, relationships, and a concern with fitting in and promoting others' goals (Markus and Kitayama 1991) . Collectivist cultures are seen as the norm worldwide and as predominating in much of Asia, South America, and Africa . This dichotomy between individualism and collectivism suggests that adolescent-parent conflict might be characteristic primarily of individualistic cultures, where autonomy, separation from others, and personal goals predominate .
208
JUDITH C. SMETANA
According to this perspective, intergenerational conflict might be less likely in cultures that stress interdependence and harmony in interpersonal relationships . Others have criticized the individualism/collectivism view, however, as providing an overly simplistic view of culture (Greenfield and Cocking 1994 ; Turiel 1998 ; Wainryb and Turiel 1994) . According to this more critical view, cultures are heterogeneous and entail a coexistence of different orientations . Individuals may be interdependent and focused on roles, duties, and statuses in some contexts, but they may assert their independence and focus on personal goals in other contexts . Consistent with this latter view, a recent analysis of anthropological descriptions of over 160 cultures, drawn from the Harvard Culture files, suggests that adolescent-parent conflict is widespread, even in more traditional or collectivist cultures (Schegel and Barry 1991) . According to Schlegel and Barry, cultural variations in adolescent-parent conflict can be accounted for by considering the structural arrangements of society, including the means of production, the structure of the household, and control over property . They propose that conflict occurs in all cultures where adolescents are required to become independent from their families in their establishment of separate households . Thus, in their view, the structural features of society (rather than the degree of independence or interdependence in interpersonal relationships and thus a more general cultural orientation) determine whether there is conflict in adolescent-parent relationships . Schlegel and Barry's (1991) sociological analysis is consistent with the more psychological analysis offered here . One of the most important developmental tasks of adolescence is individuation and the development of independence . Independence may assume a variety of forms, including more autonomous decision making (for instance, deciding what clothes to wear, how to spend allowance, or how to allocate time), assuming more responsibility within the household (for instance, being expected to do more chores, performing tasks with less adult supervision, or having more responsibility for younger siblings), or adopting more adult-like roles (for instance, having later bedtimes or curfews, being able to drive or go out on dates) . As these examples are meant to suggest, adolescents may desire greater independence, even in cultural contexts where interdependence is seen as the desired developmental outcome . And even in cultures that stress independence, research has indicated that individuality is best achieved in the context of connectedness and that healthy development involves a balance between the two (Cooper 1999) . Across cultural contexts, adolescents and parents may disagree or have conflicts as to the pace or content of age-related changes in roles, rights, and responsibilities . At the same time, culture may inform how and the extent to which conflicts are expressed . Thus, the proposition advanced here is that conflict reflects normative developmental processes of individuation and should be evident across a range of cultures, including those that emphasize interdependence and strong family ties . According to this view, adolescents and par-
Cultural Contexts and Processes
209
ents across cultural contexts would be expected to have conflicts and disagreements in their relationships . Emery (1992) has distinguished between what he refers to as the surface meaning of conflict, which is its literal content, and the deep meaning of conflict, or what the conflict conveys about the relationship . Because the surface meaning refers to the topics (content) of conflicts, it is relatively straightforward and easily observed, even if conflicts are intense or not easily resolved . In contrast, the deep meaning or "deep structure" of conflict is the meta-communication or the underlying issue at stake in the dispute . Although adolescent-parent conflicts may occur over mundane, everyday issues, the affective intensity of conflict comes from its deep meaning . In my view, the deep structure of adolescent-parent conflict pertains to adolescents' attempt to gain autonomy and independence . Although there may be cultural variability in the expression of conflict (e .g., how frequent or intense the conflicts are), the issues that cause conflict (e .g ., the surface meaning of conflicts), and how conflicts are negotiated and resolved, the proposition advanced here is that there are similarities across cultures in the deep structure of adolescent-parent conflict . The social-cognitive analyses presented here were designed to help illuminate this deep meaning .
THE CULTURAL CONTEXTS OF THE RESEARCH In the past, much of the cross-cultural research, as well as research on ethnic minority children and families, has been comparative in design . In cross-cultural studies this has led to a focus on outcomes without particular regard to the cultural processes that may lead to differences in outcomes (Garcia Coll and Magnuson 1999) . In studies of ethnic minority children, comparative designs typically have led researchers to adopt a deficit perspective . Ethnic minority children have been compared to white middle-class children on a wide range of psychological variables and outcomes (for instance, academic achievement or rates of problem behaviors) and differences, if found, were viewed as deficiencies without attention to the confounding effects of socioeconomic status, family structures, or community or neighborhood factors (Garcia Coll and Magnuson 1999 ; McLoyd 1990, 1998 ; Phinney and Landin 1998) . Furthermore, most research on AfricanAmerican children has been conducted with families living in poverty, and thus, race, ethnicity, and socioeconomic status typically have been confounded (Garcia Coll et al . 1995 ; Graham 1992 ; Hoff-Ginsberg and Tardif 1995 ; McLoyd 1998) . More recently, researchers have advocated for the importance of within-group designs, so that ethnic minorities or cultural groups can be studied on their own terms, and within-group differences and processes can be examined (Cauce and Gonzales 1993 ; Garcia Coll and Magnuson 1999 ; McLoyd 1990, 1998 ; Phinney and Landin 1998) . In accordance with this trend, each of the studies discussed here was conducted as an independent investigation . Samples were recruited sep-
210
JUDITH G . SMETANA
arately, at different times and using different recruitment strategies . There were some differences in study methods, and in each case, analyses focused on within-group comparisons (for instance, of parents versus children and age, gender, and marital status differences) . Although findings from different studies are contrasted in the following sections, it should be clear that these comparisons are illustrative, not definitive, as the samples are not strictly comparable and were not statistically compared. Nevertheless, an examination of adolescent-parent conflict in European-American, African-American, and Chinese families affords an interesting window on cultural continuities and differences in adolescent-parent relationships and more broadly, on how culture is conceptualized . Many of the characteristics ascribed to African-American culture bear strong similarities to the collectivism ascribed to Chinese culture . For instance, African-American families place a high value on communalism and harmony in interpersonal relationships (Boykin 1983 ; Boykin and Toms 1985 ; Garcia Coll et al . 1995 ; Parke and Buriel 1998), are strongly hierarchical in structure, and demand obedience and respect toward elders (Garcia Coll et al . 1995) . Thus, in many ways, African-American families are described in more similar terms to Chinese families in Hong Kong than to the EuropeanAmerican families with whom they share a wider cultural milieu . Furthermore, although Hong Kong is more Westernized than other Chinese cultures such as Taiwan, research has indicated that Chinese parents in Hong Kong differ significantly in parental values (Feldman, Rosenthal, Mont-Reynaud, Leung, and Lau 1991) and Hong Kong adolescents differ in their expectations for behavioral autonomy from their American counterparts (Feldman and Rosenthal 1990) . The middle-class European-American sample consisted of 102 white preadolescents and adolescents ranging in age from 10 to 18 years and their married parents (all two-parent families) . These families were recruited from a suburban middle-class school district near Rochester, New York and were primarily middle- and upper-middle class, as assessed by parental incomes, educational backgrounds, and occupations (see Smetana 1989 for more details) . The Chinese sample consisted of 120 lower-class Chinese adolescents ranging in age from 12 to 19 years of age who were recruited from three urban secondary schools in Hong Kong and interviewed in Chinese . Lower socioeconomic status adolescents were sampled on the assumption that lower-class families would be less Westernized and more traditional than more middle-class families (Yau and Smetana 1996) . Chinese parents did not participate, but the majority of parents had only an elementary level education and were employed as skilled or semiskilled laborers. The African-American sample was recruited from black churches, professional organizations, and community groups in Rochester, New York and consisted of 95 African-American adolescents and their parents (93 mothers and 57 fathers) who were followed longitudinally for two years . Adolescents were between the ages of 11 and 14 at intake into the study and between 13 and 16 at the longitudi-
Cultural Contexts and Processes
21 1
nal follow-up . The majority were two-parent families and were heterogeneously middle-class, ranging from lower-middle-class production line workers to uppermiddle-class professional families (see Smetana and Gaines 1999 for further description of the sample) .
THE INCIDENCE OF CONFLICT Our data support the assertion that European-American and African-American middle-class adolescents and their parents, as well as lower socioeconomic status Chinese adolescents, would have conflicts in their relationships . Chinese and European-American adolescents and European-American parents were asked in individual interviews to generate lists of actual conflicts with parents or adolescents, and their responses also were probed using a standard probe list . AfricanAmerican families indicated their conflicts on the Issues Checklist, a frequently-used instrument where participants were presented with 37 different areas of day-to-day decision making (Prinz, Foster, Kent, and O'Leary 1979 ; Robin and Foster 1989) . Adolescents in all three samples and middle-class American parents (both black and white) reported having conflicts in their relationships . The number of conflicts reported over the previous two weeks ranged from a low of 1 .95 (among Chinese adolescents) to a high of 6 .75 conflicts (among African-American parents) . Previous research with European-American adolescents typically has found that adolescents view their relationships as more contentious than do their parents, and similar findings were obtained here . European-American adolescents reported more conflicts than did their parents . However, this was not the case in African-American families ; African-American parents reported more conflicts than did their adolescents (although African-American adolescents and parents both reported more conflicts than did European-American adolescents and parents) . Although these findings suggest that African-American families are more conflictive than are other families (which, in turn, appears inconsistent with the communalism attributed to African-American families), this may, in part, reflect a measurement artifact, as African-American family members were selecting conflicts from a predetermined list, whereas European-American and Chinese families were asked to generate conflicts . Yet, others have noted that the vitality and verve that is characteristic of African-American expressive behavior translates into an interaction style that is more openly expressive and affectively charged than is characteristic of European-American families (Kochman 1981) . Thus, African-American families may be more tolerant of conflict and disagreement than are other families . In contrast, using similar methods and consistent with descriptions of Chinese culture as stressing harmony in interpersonal relations, fewer conflicts were reported by Chinese than European-American adolescents .
212
JUDITH G . SMETANA
In each of these studies, conflicts were rated for frequency and intensity . The general picture that emerges is that conflicts are frequently occurring but generally quite low in intensity . This is consistent with the previous literature in indicating that adolescents' conflicts with parents generally are in the form of bickering, squabbling, and minor disagreements (Laursen et al . 1998), but the findings also suggest that the previous findings generalize beyond EuropeanAmerican middle-class families . Moreover, the frequency and intensity ratings demonstrate surprisingly little cultural variability in the expression of conflict .
CONFLICTIVE ISSUES What do adolescents and parents fight about? As has been found in mainstream American samples and as shown in Figure 1, conflict in parent-adolescent relationships in all three cultural contexts occurred over the everyday details of family life, such as the adolescents' choice of activities, doing the chores, doing school work, and getting along with siblings, or what Hill and Holmbeck (1987) have referred to as "hair, garbage, dishes, and galoshes ." Moreover, a consistent finding in our studies is that adolescents and parents generally agree on the issues that cause conflict in their relationships . Yet Figure 1 suggests that despite the overall similarities, there are also cultural (and contextual) differences . For instance, Chinese adolescents have far more conflicts over choice of activities than do American families, black or white . This
Activitles
Homework
Chores
Figure 1 .
Interpersonal
Curfew/Bed
Issues of Conflict
Looks/Health
Cultural Contexts and Processes
21 3
most likely reflects setting rather than cultural differences, as Hong Kong is a very dense, urban city . With diverse activities available outside the home and very limited living space at home, Chinese adolescents expressed desires to stay outside after school or over the weekend, which was in conflict with their parents' concern for their safety and for having their schoolwork done . Chinese adolescents also had more conflicts than did American adolescents over schoolwork and academic achievement, reflecting the value Chinese families place on achievement and academic success . In contrast, the importance of responsibility and contributing to the collective unit in African-American families (Garcia Coll et al . 1995) was evidenced here in the greater frequency of conflicts over doing the chores in African-American families than in other families .
CONFLICT RESOLUTION As shown in Figure 2, the modal response across cultural contexts was that, according to the converging reports of both adolescents and their parents, conflicts were resolved by giving in to parents' views . However, cultural variability in modes of conflict resolution also was evident . Chinese families appeared to engage in more frequent joint resolutions than did European-American families . Although this finding may reflect the collective nature of Chinese families, it is
Parent Wins
Figure 2.
Teen Wins
Joint
Modes of Conflict Resolution
214
JUDITH G . SMETANA
inconsistent with the strongly hierarchical structure of Chinese families, which suggests that respect for parental authority (rather than allowance of joint decision making) might predominate in situations of disagreement . In contrast, African-American families demonstrated fewer joint resolutions and parental concession (where the adolescent wins the disagreement) than in other families . Moreover, in African-American families, parents' views on disputes prevailed considerably more than in European-American and in particular, Chinese families . Although this finding may reflect the strongly hierarchical structure of African-American families, this does not explain the striking difference between African-American and Chinese families, as Chinese families are also strongly hierarchical . Another interpretation is that these findings reflect the pervasive effects of racism and discrimination, which makes the transition to adolescence especially perilous for African-American youth (particularly males), regardless of socioeconomic status . African-American parents may fear the consequences of adolescents' greater independence and thus attempt to retain control over their adolescents' behavior . Age-related shifts in conflict resolution (not depicted in Figure 2) also emerged. Across cultural contexts, adolescents gained more power in the family as they grew older, although the patterns also reflected cultural differences in how power in the family is shared . The proportion of conflicts that were resolved by adolescents getting their way remained small across adolescence, particularly in African-American families . In African-American and Chinese families, joint resolutions increased significantly with age, from 26 percent in early adolescence to 43 percent in late adolescence in Chinese families and from 5 percent in early adolescence to 11 percent in mid-adolescence in African-American families . Reflecting their hierarchical structures, the proportion of conflicts that were resolved by adolescents giving in to parents did not decrease significantly across adolescence in either Chinese or African-American families ; parents' views continued to prevail . Thus, although Chinese and African-American parents did not directly yield their authority to their adolescents, they increasingly took their adolescents' views into consideration The process differed somewhat in European-American families . The proportion of conflicts resolved by European-American adolescents giving in to parents declined significantly as adolescents got older, and these declines were paralleled by increases in adolescents' winning the disputes (e .g ., parents' giving in to their adolescents), with the greatest increases occurring in late adolescence . In other words, in European-American families there was a more direct transfer of authority from parents to adolescents and from parent-unilateral to adolescent-unilateral solutions . Moreover, the reported decline in adolescent concession, which was obtained through self-reports in individual interviews, also was observed more directly in a structured family interaction task (Smetana, Yau, and Hanson 1991) . In these studies, adolescents' and parents' reports of conflict resolutions were scored for outcomes-who won the dispute . But their descriptions also illumi-
Cultural Contexts and Processes
21 5
nated some strategic differences that were not captured in the coding and that bear further investigation . The transcripts of the interviews with Chinese adolescents are striking in that many adolescents described elaborate ways of getting around their parents . For instance, one adolescent reported that she waited to raise issues when her father returned from an 18-hour workday, certain that he would be too tired to object to her wishes . Moreover, in addition to assessing how conflicts actually were resolved, Chinese adolescents also were asked who they thought should make the decisions . The Chinese adolescents in our sample consistently desired more control over decision making than they were granted . Thus, although adolescents may desire greater control and independence from parents, these results demonstrate that there is cultural variability in how conflict is expressed and the extent to which adolescents may directly challenge and confront their parents . However, the variability observed here in the incidence and topics of conflict and modes of conflict resolution is more complex than characterizations of cultures as individualistic versus collectivist might suggest .
JUSTIFICATIONS FOR CONFLICTS The major focus of these studies was to examine adolescents' and parents' interpretation of disputes, or the meaning of the conflicts to the participants . Adolescents in all three cultural contexts and American parents (white and black) were individually interviewed to obtain their justifications for their perspectives on disputes . Across cultural contexts, the findings indicate striking differences in adolescents' and parents' interpretations of conflicts . Adolescents' justifications
Across ages and cultural contexts, adolescents reasoned that their behavior was acceptable or permissible, that the acts in question did not harm or affect others, that the acts were important for their developing autonomy or identity, or that the acts should be their choice or under their personal control . This is illustrated by the following three examples . 1.
2.
"It's my room and it's nobody else's business what it looks like . WHY DO YOU THINK YOUR MOM THINKS YOU SHOULD CLEAN IT? Because she says the room is part of the house, and she thinks it should look nice . WHAT DO YOU THINK OF THAT? It's not like there's anything gross in there . If my mom doesn't like it, she can just close the door!" "WHY DO YOU THINK IT'S OK TO WATCH TV? I watch TV when I'm bored, when I have nothing to do . Besides, there's nothing wrong with watching TV. WHY DOES YOUR MOTHER ASK YOU NOT TO WATCH SO MUCH TELEVISION? She thinks it's a waste of time just
216
3.
JUDITH G . SMETANA
sitting there and nothing to do . She would rather have me doing more reading, studying more . . . . She says I could watch TV after I have finished my homework and studying ." "WHEN YOU HAVE A CONFLICT WITH YOUR MOTHER ABOUT CLEANING UP YOUR BEDROOM, WHAT IS IT THAT YOU WANT TO DO? . . .I just don't want to do it sometimes . Sometimes I'm just too tired or I feel it's pointless . WHY DO YOU THINK IT'S OK FOR YOU NOT TO DO IT? Because no one else is going to be in my room . This is my room . It's James' room for the way it wants to look. Not like what anyone else wants it to look . WHEN THIS COMES UP, WHAT IS IT THAT YOUR MOTHER WANTS YOU TO DO? She wants me to get off my butt and clean the room and be done with it ."
The characterization of cultures as individualistic or collectivist, as well as Markus and Kitayama's (1991 ; Shweder et al . 1998) descriptions of different construals of self, might lead to the conclusion that these responses are primarily from middle-class European-American individualists . But they are not . Only the first example is from a European-American adolescent . The second is from a Chinese adolescent, and the third is from an African-American adolescent . Moreover, these responses are not unrepresentative ; they are prototypical of adolescents in these groups . These justifications exemplify what I have called "appeals to personal jurisdiction" or personal choice justifications . Approximately half of European-American, African-American, and Chinese adolescents' justifications pertained to personal choice . These responses could be seen as reflecting hedonistic desires for personal fulfillment or the selfish achievement of personal needs and goals . But they also can be interpreted within the context of a larger body of research employing a domain-specificity model of children's social-cognitive development (see Smetana 1995c ; Turiel 1983, 1998 for an elaboration of this theoretical framework), which informed the choice of categories used to code justification responses . According to this model, children develop different types (or what are referred to as domains) of social knowledge through their social experiences with different types of acts, events, transgressions, and rules . Different knowledge domains, in turn, are seen to form separate, self-regulating developmental systems . According to this model, judgments regarding personal issues are seen as an aspect of children's understanding of self and others as psychological systems, which forms a distinct domain of social knowledge . Personal issues have been defined as the set of actions that are beyond the bounds of justifiable social regulation and moral concern . Personal issues comprise the private aspects of one's life and pertain to issues of preference and choice pertaining to friends or activities, the state of one's body, and privacy . Within this model, the right to make autonomous decisions is described as an aspect of the self that forms the boundary between the self and the social world .
Cultural Contexts and Processes
217
Thus, control over the personal serves to establish the boundary between the self and others . Evidence from a variety of studies has demonstrated that from early ages on (Killen and Smetana 1999 ; Nucci 1981 ; Nucci and Weber 1995), children judge a set of issues as personal and up to the child to decide . This definition of the personal domain is consistent with what William James (1899) described as an awareness of the "I", that aspect of the self that organizes and interprets experiences as reflective awareness of one's agency, continuity, and distinctness . Theorists from a variety of theoretical perspectives (Baldwin 1906 ; Damon and Hart 1988 ; Erikson 1968 ; Kohut 1978 ; Mahler 1979 ; Selman 1980) have argued for a close connection between personal autonomy and the formation of the individual . Likewise, although there are variations in how personhood is defined across cultures (Geertz 1975 ; Markus and Kitayama 1991 ; Shweder and Bourne 1984), it has been asserted-and surveys of the anthropological literature have supported (LeVine and White 1986)-that notions of self and personhood are basic human concepts (Damon and Hart 1988 ; Geertz 1975) . This suggests that although there may be cultural variations in the boundaries that constrain or define the personal domain (Nucci 1996 ; Nucci and Lee 1993), and thus, what is considered to be under the individual's personal jurisdiction, all cultures treat some issues as fundamentally within the boundaries of the self and personal agency . Based on this literature, Nucci (1996 ; Nucci and Lee 1993) has asserted that the establishment of an arena of personal freedom and concepts of personal control are necessary for the establishment of the self and the formation of the social individual . Thus, considered within this broader context of theorizing and research, adolescents' appeals to personal jurisdiction can be seen as an aspect of children's developing autonomy and reflective of their attempts to assert personal agency and construct a coherent self. Moreover, despite claims regarding the collectivist nature of Chinese culture and the more communalistic nature of African-American families, Chinese and African-American adolescents articulated the same desires for control over decision making and autonomy seeking that were observed among European-American youth . These findings are quite robust . Similar findings have been obtained when examining European-American adolescents' reasoning in the more contentious context of a family interaction task (Smetana, Braeges, and Yau 1991), in a more experimental study of adolescents' and parents' judgments (Smetana and Berent 1993), and in divorced, mother-custody families (Smetana, Yau, Restrespo, and Braeges 1991) . Furthermore, personal justifications for conflicts were found to increase with age in AfricanAmerican adolescents (Smetana in preparation) and predominated in the justifications of Chinese youth in China, as well as replicated in an independent sample of adolescents in Hong Kong (Yau and Smetana in preparation) . Adolescents also appealed to psychological characteristics to justify their perspective on conflicts . Psychological justifications pertained to personality characteristics, psychological development, and behavioral styles, for instance, "I'm just
218
JUDITH C . SMETANA
lazy, I guess ." It is interesting to note that approximately one-quarter of adolescents' justifications in all three samples were of this type . Other types of justifications (explained in more detail below) were much less frequent . In my view, the remarkable similarity in adolescents' justifications across the cultural contexts examined here provides support for the notion of a deep structure of adolescent-parent conflict. Adolescents' appeals to personal jurisdiction reflect attempts to increase their agency or enlarge their sphere of personal action, and thus can be seen to serve an individuating function in adolescent development.
Parents' Justifications Do parents affirm adolescents' appeals to personal jurisdiction? The following examples illustrate some typical parental responses expressed in individual interviews . 1.
"WHY DO YOU THINK SHE SHOULD CLEAN UP HER ROOM? For several reasons . First, her room is part of the house, and it's her responsibility to keep it clean . We all live here, and we all have to do our part . I'm not asking for much, just for her to straighten up a bit . WHY IS THAT IMPORTANT? Well, I'd be really embarrassed for anyone to see her room looking like that . . ." 2 . "WHAT'S WRONG WITH THE WAY SHE DRESSES? Well, it's really provocative, for one thing. She says that's the way everyone dresses, and that it isn't my decision . But as long as I buy the clothes, it is my decision . She just wants to fit in . But I'm afraid that other kids-especially the boys-will get the wrong idea . And I see other kids-they don't all dress that way . But she tells me that I'm just old-fashioned and that if she wore the clothes I pick out for her, all the other kids would laugh ." 3 . "WHEN YOU HAVE A CONFLICT WITH YOUR CHILD ABOUT HELPING AROUND THE HOUSE, WHAT IS IT THAT YOU WANT HER TO DO? I want her to participate in the clean-up . And that's something she never showed much interest in . WHY DO YOU THINK SHE SHOULD DO THAT? Because then the house won't stay a big mess because she knows how to pick up her mess . She needs to pick up her stuff just like her father picks up his stuff and like I pick up mine . So its' just responsibility . She needs to know that she don't have maids and butlers to go after her ." 4 . "WHY IS IT WRONG FOR JESSICA TO TALK BACK TO YOU? Well, because I think . . . when you talk back to your parents, you're being disrespectful . We expect her to show respect even when she disagrees with us . And I think that's just a common courtesy because that is something that she needs to learn because if she goes out into the world, she's going to run
Cultural Contexts and Processes
21 9
into bosses that she might disagree with. . . and she needs to learn how to respond to a person who she is not in agreement with . She can't just sass them ." As these examples indicate, European-American parents' justifications (as exemplified by the first two responses) and African-American parents' responses (as exemplified by the second two responses) are quite similar, but they differ qualitatively from adolescents' responses . Parents justified their perspectives on disputes by referring to family rules, parental authority, contrasting social norms and standards, adolescents' responsibility as a member of the family, the need for social coordination in dividing labor, and the perceived social costs of adolescents' social nonconformity (for instance, parents' embarrassment over adolescents' behavior or appearance, concern about others' misperceptions of the adolescent, and adolescents' fear of ridicule from peers) . All of these responses are considered social-conventional . Social conventions also can be understood within the broader context of the domain model of social-cognitive development (Smetana 1995c ; Tisak 1995 ; Turiel 1983, 1998) . According to this model, social conventions are an aspect of individuals' understanding of social systems and social organization . They have been defined as socially constituted and consensually agreed-on shared uniformities that coordinate the interactions of individuals within different social systems, such as societies, schools, and families (Turiel 1983, 1998) . Conventions are symbolic elements of social organization and represent shared knowledge among members of society or a social unit . Conventions are relative to the social context, arbitrary in the sense that alternative actions could serve the same function, and provide individuals with a set of expectations regarding appropriate behavior (see Smetana 1995c ; Turiel 1983, 1998 for reviews) . Social-conventional justifications were the modal response among both African-American and European-American parents, accounting for nearly 50 percent of their justifications . The remainder of parents' responses were divided among other justification categories . In my view, these similarities in parents' justifications for conflicts reflect their common goals in conflict situations . In communicating societal laws, cultural conventions, and family rules and expectations, parents are attempting to maintain social order, promote social interaction, and facilitate adolescents' effective participation in society . In other words, parents' appeals to social conventions serve a socializing function in adolescent development. It should be noted that the analyses of adolescents' justifications revealed that they, too, justified their perspectives on disputes with references to social conventions . However, in contrast to the societal conventions and family rules and expectations that their parents promoted, adolescents typically appealed to peer group conventions .
220
JUDITH G . SMETANA
Although social conventions pertain to social regulations, all social regulations are not of one type . According to social domain theory (see Smetana 1995c ; Tisak 1995 ; Turiel 1983, 1998) and consistent with analytic distinctions made by moral philosophers (Gewirth 1978 ; Rawls 1971), social conventions have been distinguished both conceptually and developmentally from morality . Whereas social conventions are seen as arbitrary, consensually determined, and relative to social contexts, moral issues are described as prescriptive, categorical, generalizable judgments of right and wrong pertaining to others' welfare, rights, and the fair distribution of resources . Only a small proportion of parents' justifications for conflicts were moral, and they pertained primarily to interpersonal issues such as sibling conflicts or getting along with others . Nearly a quarter of parents' justifications for conflicts were prudential, which were defined as pertaining to safety, harm to the self, comfort, and health (Smetana 1995c ; Tisak 1995) or to pragmatic concerns, which pertained to practical needs or consequences . Thus, conflicts over going to bed late or choice of activities typically were justified on prudential grounds ("he'll be tired in school"), whereas homework and academic achievement typically was justified pragmatically, in terms of the practical consequences of not studying or lower achievement for success in later life . A smaller proportion of justifications pertained to the psychological characteristics of their adolescents . Thus, taken together, these findings indicate that adolescents and parents consistently have different interpretations of the issues that cause conflict, and intergenerational discrepancies are far more pervasive than cultural differences . Across samples, adolescents primarily appealed to personal jurisdiction, whereas parents primarily viewed conflicts as social conventions .
CONCEPTIONS OF PARENTAL AUTHORITY Another related line of research on adolescents' and parents' conceptions of parental authority further clarifies the interpretation of these findings . In several studies using these samples (Smetana 1988, in press), as well as in independent samples (Smetana 1995d ; Smetana and Asquith 1994), African-American and European-American adolescents and parents also assessed the legitimacy of parental authority . More specifically, they judged whether parents had the legitimate authority to regulate different types of hypothetical acts, as defined within social domain theory . Both European-American and African-American adolescents and parents nearly unanimously affirmed parents' legitimate authority to regulate moral and conventional issues ; parents and adolescents did not differ in their judgments that parents have the legitimate authority to regulate these issues . However, adolescents and their parents consistently differed in their judgments of personal issues (Smetana 1988, in press ; Smetana and Asquith 1994) . Across studies, more than half of all parents endorsed the view that they had legitimate
Cultural Contexts and Processes
221
jurisdiction over actions that adolescents viewed as within their personal domain . Moreover, judgments that parents have legitimate authority over personal issues consistently have been found to decline with age from preadolescence to late adolescence in European-American middle-class families (Smetana 1988 ; Smetana and Asquith 1994) and longitudinally from early to mid-adolescence in AfricanAmerican families (Smetana in press) . The research discussed in the previous sections on adolescent-parent conflict as well as the social-cognitive research on the development of young children's judgments of personal issues indicate that although the boundaries of personal jurisdiction are enlarged or expanded during adolescence, personal concepts do not first arise during adolescence ; rather, they are salient from early ages on . Moreover, the research on parental authority indicates that adolescents do not necessarily reject parental conventional regulation, even in late adolescence . Across ages, adolescents strongly affirmed parents' legitimate authority to regulate social conventions in the family . The studies of parental authority also indicate that parents of adolescents acknowledge the validity of at least some of adolescents' appeals to personal jurisdiction, at least outside the contentious realm of adolescent-parent conflict . Thus, the shifts from unilateral to mutual authority noted by others (Damon 1977 ; Youniss and Smollar 1985) and found in the analyses of conflict resolution presented here appear to occur primarily at the intersection between conventional authority and personal jurisdiction . My research suggests that adolescent-parent conflict occurs over where these boundaries should be drawn. This hypothesis was examined explicitly in the studies of adolescents' conceptions of parental authority . In these studies, adolescents and parents also evaluated an additional category of items, referred to as multifaceted . Multifaceted items were defined as issues that contained both personal and conventional components and that thus overlapped the boundaries between the conventional and personal domains . For instance, the adolescent's room is a frequent source of conflict in adolescent-parent relations (Smetana 1989) . It is a prototypically multifaceted issue in that to the extent that the room is defined as the adolescent's private space, it is clearly a personal issue . However, to the extent that the room is seen as part of the house, it is a clearly conventional issue that is subject to parents' legitimate authority . Indeed, the personal and conventional aspects of this issue exist in a figure-ground relationship . One view must predominate ; they cannot be easily reconciled . The findings from these studies suggest that multifaceted issues comprise the zone where shifts from unilateral to mutual authority occur . Across studies, parents consistently viewed multifaceted issues as legitimately regulated by parents and contingent on parental authority, based on concerns with social convention, whereas adolescents consistently viewed these issues as under their personal jurisdiction, based on personal reasons (Smetana 1988, in press ; Smetana and Asquith 1994) . Friendship issues (such as who and when to date) also are multi-
222
JUDITH G . SMETANA
faceted and may entail competing conventional, personal, and psychological concerns . Thus, multifaceted issues constitute the dynamic region where the development of autonomy proceeds . The studies of parental authority provide evidence that shifts from dependence to individuation occur primarily over the boundaries of adolescents' personal jurisdiction and that adolescent-parent conflict provides one mechanism for enlarging those boundaries . As I have proposed elsewhere (Smetana 1995a, 1995b, 1996), adolescents and parents have different interpretations of conflicts because the rules, expectations, or events that cause conflict are seen as multifaceted, and adolescents' and parents' competing goals in social situations lead them to focus on, or subordinate, different concerns (Smetana 1988, 1995a, 1995b) . Whereas parents are attempting to socialize their adolescents into societal rules and cultural conventions and to acquire the culturally prescribed psychological competencies required by their societies to lead productive lives, adolescents are attempting to forge their own identities, increase their personal agency, and construct a meaningful self. The conflict between adolescents' appeals to personal jurisdiction over issues that parents consider to be social-conventional entails the renegotiation of the boundaries between parental authority and individual authority over the self . In a dialectical process, adolescent-parent conflict forces parents to reevaluate the limits of their authority and the boundaries of adolescents' personal jurisdiction, which leads to transformations in the boundaries of parental authority . Parents shift from viewing a variety of conflicts as conventional and legitimately subject to their authority to granting the adolescent increasing personal jurisdiction over these issues . Although other types of social interactions also may facilitate these shifts in parental authority, conflict may provide one mechanism for this to occur . Thus, in the view outlined here, autonomy (in the personal domain) develops from constraint (in the conventional domain), as the boundaries of personal jurisdiction are continually redrawn and renegotiated in dialectical relations with parents in ontogenesis . Of course, the hypotheses advanced here about the role of conflict in adolescent development need to be examined and elaborated in a wider range of cultures . Furthermore, gender differences were not discussed here, although how autonomy and independence are perceived and develop differs by gender, perhaps in distinct ways in different cultures . Nevertheless, the view advanced here is consistent with a recent trend in cultural anthropology away from viewing cultures in terms of their coherence and consistency (and uniform orientations, such as those implied by individualism or collectivism) and toward viewing cultures in terms of their diversity, oppositions, and conflicts (Abu-Lughod 1993 ; Strauss 1992 ; Turiel 1998, 1999) . A number of researchers have begun to describe individuals within cultures-including traditional ones-in terms of their conflicts, struggles, and attempts to transform social practices, or how cultural understandings "may be conflicting, contested, and resisted by members of society" (Holloway 1999, p . 61) . In elaborating this argument, it has been said that cultural psychology has
Cultural Contexts and Processes
22 3
focused too much on individuals in dominant positions, to the neglect of individuals in subordinate positions (Tun el 1999) . Although these critiques have focused primarily on the subordinate role of women and their attempts to challenge cultural practices, this view can be fruitfully applied to parent-adolescent relationships as well . I have asserted here that the challenges to parental authority that are at the heart of adolescent-parent conflict enlarge the boundaries of adolescents' personal jurisdiction and thus may lead both to individual development and family relationship change . However, these conflicts also provide a mechanism for change in cultural practices and conventions as well . In negotiating, challenging, and resisting adult authority, adolescents do not just reproduce their cultures . They reconstruct and transform their cultures, and in doing so, construct a coherent self. These findings have implications for social-psychological research on group process . Although social psychologists have recognized that conflict may serve constructive as well as destructive purposes (Deutsch 1958), the available models view groups as attempting to resolve conflicts and return to the preexisting equilibrium . The research and theorizing presented here suggests that processes of conflict in adolescent-parent relationships lead to reorganization and change in both family functioning and individual development . The findings represent a challenge to social psychologists to develop models of groups and conflict resolution that can adequately describe these processes . ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am grateful to the National Institute of Mental Health for their support of the research discussed here on European-American families and to the William T . Grant Foundation for their generous and ongoing support of the research discussed here on African-American families . REFERENCES Abu-Lughod, L . 1993 . Writing Women's Worlds: Bedouin Stories . Berkeley: University of California Press . Baldwin, J . M . 1906 . Thought and Things (Vol . I) . London : Swan Sonnenschen . Bellah, R. N., R. Madsen, W . M. Sullivan, A . Swidler, and S . M . Tipton 1985 . Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life . New York: Harper & Row . Blos, P. 1962 . On Adolescence . New York : Free Press . Boykin, A . W . 1983 . "The Academic Performance of Afro-American Children ." Pp . 321-371 in Achievement and Achievement Motives, edited by J . Spence . San Francisco : Freeman. Boykin, A . W ., and F . D. Toms.1985 . "Black Child Socialization : A Conceptual Framework ." Pp. 33-51 in Black Children : Social, Educational, and Parental Environments, edited by H . P . McAdoo and J . L . McAdoo . Newbury Park, CA : Sage . Cauce, A . M ., and N . Gonzales . 1993 . "Slouching Towards Culturally Competent Research : Adolescents of Color in Context ." Focus : Psychological Study of Ethnic Minority Issues 7 : 8-9 .
224
JUDITH G . SMETANA
Collins, W. A ., and B . Laursen. 1992 . "Conflict and Relationships During Adolescence ." Pp . 216-241 in Conflict in Child and Adolescent Development, edited by C. U. Shantz and W . W . Hartup . Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press . Cooper, C . R . 1999 . "Multiple Selves, Multiple Worlds : Cultural Perspectives on Individuality and Connectedness in Adolescent Development ." Pp . 25-57 in 29`h Minnesota Symposium on Child Psychology: Cultural Processes in Child Development, edited by A. S . Masten. Mahwah, NJ : Erlbaum . Damon, W. 1977 . The Social World of the Child . San Francisco : Jossey-Bass . Damon, W ., and D . Hart . 1988 . Self-understanding in Childhood and Adolescence . Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press . Deutsch, M . 1958 . The Resolution of Conflict. New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Duck, S ., and K . Pond. 1989 . "Friends, Romans, and Countrymen, Lend Me Your Retrospections : Rhetoric and Reality in Personal Relationships." Pp. 17-38 in Close Relationships, edited by C . Hendrick . Newbury Park, CA : Sage . Emery, R . E. 1992. "Family Conflicts and Their Developmental Implications : a Conceptual Analysis of Meanings for the Structure of Relationships ." Pp . 270-298 in Conflict in Child and Adolescent Development, edited by C . U. Shantz and W . W . Hartup . Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press. Erikson, E. H . 1968 . Identity, Youth, and Crisis . New York: Norton . Feldman, S . S ., and D . A . Rosenthal . 1990 . "The Acculturation of Autonomy Expectations in Chinese High Schoolers Residing in Two Western Nations." International Journal of Psychology 25 : 259-281 . Feldman, S . S ., D . Rosenthal, R . Mont-Reynaud, K . Leung, and S . Lau . 1991 . " 'Ain't Misbehavin' : Adolescent Values and Family Environments as Correlates of Misconduct in Australia, Hong Kong, and the United States ." Journal of Research on Adolescence 1 : 109-134. Freud, A . 1937 . The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense. London: Hogarth . Garcia Coll, C ., and K. Magnuson . 1999 . "Cultural Influences on Child Development : Are We Ready for a Paradigm Shift?" Pp . 1-24 in 29`h Minnesota Symposium on Child Psychology : Cultural Processes in Child Development, edited by A . S . Masten . Mahwah, NJ : Erlbaum. Garcia Coll, C ., E . C. Meyer, and L . Brillon . 1995 . "Ethnic and Minority Parenting ." Pp. 189-209 in Handbook of Parenting, Vol. 2 : Biology and Ecology of Parenting, edited by M . H. Bornstein . Mahwah, NJ : Erlbaum . Geertz, C. 1975 . "On the Nature of Anthropological Understanding ." American Scientist 63 : 47-53 . Gewirth, A . 1978 . Reason and Morality . Chicago : University of Chicago . Graham, S . 1992 . "Most of the Subjects Were White and Middle Class: Trends in Published Research on African-Americans in Selected APA Journals, 1970-1989 ." American Psychologist 47 : 629-639. Greenfield, P. M ., and R. R. Cocking, eds. 1994. Cross-cultural Roots of Minority Child Development . Hillsdale, NJ : Erlbaum . Grusec, J . E ., and J . J . Goodnow . 1994 . "Impact of Parental Discipline Methods on the Child's Internalization of Values : a Reconceptualization of Current Points of View ." Developmental Psychology 30: 4-19. Grusky, 0 ., P. Bonacich, and M . Peyrot . 1988. "Group Structure and Interpersonal Conflict in the Family ." Pp . 29-51 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol. 5, edited by E . Lawler and B . Markovsky. Greenwich, CT : JAI Press, Inc . Heise, D . 1995 . "Review of Group Processes : Sociological Analyses ." Social Forces 73 : 1120-1121 . Hill, J . P. 1988 . "Adapting to Menarche : Familial Control and Conflict ." Pp . 43-78 in 21" Minnesota Symposium on Child Psychology : Development During the Transition to Adolescence, edited by M . R . Gunnar and W . A . Collins . Hillsdale, NJ : Erlbaum .
Cultural Contexts and Processes
225
Hill, J . P ., and G . Holmbeck. 1987 . "Familial Adaptation to Pubertal Change During Adolescence ." Pp . 207-223 in Biological-psychosocial Interactions in Early Adolescence : a Life-span Perspective, edited by R. M. Lerner and T. Foch. Hillsdale, NJ : Erlbaum . Hoff-Ginsberg, E., and T . Tardif. 1995 . "Socioeconomic Status and Parenting ." Pp. 161-188 in Handbook of Parenting, Vol. 2 : Biology and Ecology of, edited by M . H . Bornstein . Mahwah, NJ : Erlbaum . Holloway, S . D . 1999 . "Divergent Cultural Models of Child Rearing and Pedagogy in Japanese Preschools ." Pp . 61-75 in New Directions for Child Development, Vol. 83 : Development and Cultural Change : Reciprocal Processes, edited by E . Turiel. San Francisco : Jossey-Bass . Holmbeck, G . N . 1996 . "A Model of Family Relational Transformations During the Transition to Adolescence : Parent-Adolescent Conflict and Adaptation." Pp . 167-199 in Transitions Through Adolescence : Interpersonal Domains and Context, edited by J . A . Graber, J . Brooks-Gunn, and A . C . Petersen. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum . Holmbeck, G . N ., R . L. Paikoff, and J . Brooks-Gunn . 1995 . "Parenting Adolescents ." Pp. 91-118 in Handbook of Parenting, Vol. 1 : Children and Parenting, edited by M . H. Bornstein . Mahwah, NJ : Erlbaum . James, W . 1899 . The Principles of Psychology . London : Macmillan . Kelly, G . A . 1955 . A Psychology of Personal Constructs . New York : Norton . Killen, M ., and J . G . Smetana . 1999 . "Social Interactions in Preschool Classrooms and the Development of Young Children's Conceptions of the Personal ." Child Development 70 : 486-501 . Kochman, T . 1981 . Black and White Styles in Interaction . Chicago: University of Chicago Press . Kohut, H. 1978 . The Search for the Self. Selected Writings (1950-1978) . New York: International University Press . Laursen, B ., and W . A . Collins. 1994 . "Interpersonal Conflict During Adolescence ." Psychological Bulletin 115 : 197-209. Laursen, B ., K . C . Coy, and W . A. Collins. 1998 . "Reconsidering Changes in Parent-child Conflict Across Adolescence : a Meta-analysis ." Child Development 69 : 817-832 . LeVine, R ., and M . White . 1986. Human Conditions: the Cultural Basis for Educational Development. New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul . Maccoby, E. E ., and J . A . Martin. 1983 . "Socialization in the Context of the Family : Parent-child Interaction ." Pp . 1-102 in Handbook of Child Psychology, Vol . 4. Socialization, Personality, and Social Development, edited by E . M . Hetherington. New York : Wiley . Mahler, M . S . 1979 . The Selected Papers of Margaret S . Mahler: Vols. I & II . New York : J . Aronson. Markus, H. R., and S . Kitayama. 1991 . "Culture and the Self : Implications for Cognition, Emotion, and Motivation." Psychological Bulletin 98 : 224-253 . McLoyd, V . 1990. "Minority Children : Introduction to the Special Issue ." Child Development 61 : 263-266 . McLoyd, V . 1998 . "Changing Demographics in the American Population : Implications for Research on Minority Children and Adolescents." Pp . 3-28 in Studying Minority Adolescents: Conceptual, Methodological, and Theoretical Issues, edited by V . C . McLoyd and L . Steinberg. Mahwah, NJ : Erlbaum . Nucci, L . P . 1981 . "The Development of Personal Concepts : a Domain Distinct from Moral or Societal Concepts ." Child Development 52 : 114-121 . Nucci, L . P. 1996 . "Morality and the Sphere of Personal Actions ." Pp . 41-60 in Values and Knowledge, edited by E . S . Reed, E . Turiel, and T . Brown. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum . Nucci, L . P ., and J . Lee . 1993 . "Morality and Personal Autonomy ." Pp . 123-148 in The Moral Self: Building a Better Paradigm, edited by G . G . Noam and T. Wren . Cambridge, MA : MIT Press. Nucci, L . P., and E . Weber. 1995 . "Social Interactions in the Home and the Development of Young Children's Conceptions of the Personal ." Child Development 66 : 1438-1452 . Offer, D . 1969 . The Psychological World of the Teenager . New York : Basic Books.
226
JUDITH G . SMETANA
Paikoff, R . L ., and J . Brooks-Gunn . 1991 . "Do Parent-child Relationships Change During Puberty?" Psychological Bulletin 110 : 47-66. Parke, R. D ., and R. Buriel. 1998. "Socialization in the Family: Ethnic and Ecological Perspectives ." Pp . 463-552 in Handbook of Child Psychology, 5th Edition, Volume 3: Social, Emotional, and Personality Development, edited by N . Eisenberg ; W. Damon, series editor . New York : Wiley . Parsons, T. 1955 . Family, Socialization, and Interaction Processes . New York: Free Press. Phinney, J . S ., and J . Landin . 1998 . "Research Paradigms for Studying Ethnic Minority Families Within and Across Groups ." Pp . 89-109 in Studying Minority Adolescents : Conceptual, Methodological, and Theoretical Issues, edited by V. C . McLoyd and L. Steinberg. Mahwah, NJ : Erlbaum . Prinz, R . J ., S . L. Foster, R . N . Kent, and K. D . O'Leary . 1979. "Multivariate Assessment of Conflict in Distressed and Nondistressed Mother-adolescent Dyads ." Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis 12 : 691-700 . Rawls, J . 1971 . A Theory of Justice . Cambridge : Cambridge University Press . Robin, A. L ., and S . L . Foster. 1989. Negotiating Parent-adolescent Conflict : A Behavioral Family Systems Approach. New York: Guilford . Schlegel, A ., and H . Barry 3 rd . 1991 . Adolescence : An Anthropological Inquiry . New York : Free Press. Selman, R . 1980. The Growth of Interpersonal Understanding : Developmental and Clinical Analyses . New York: Academic Press . Shweder, R . A . 1990 . "Cultural Psychology-What Is It?" Pp . 1-43 in Cultural Psychology: Essays on Comparative Human Development, edited by J. W. Stigler, R . A . Shweder, and G . Herdt . Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press . Shweder, R . A., and E . J. Bourne . 1984 . "Does the Concept of the Person Vary Cross-culturally?" Pp . 158-199 in Culture Theory : Essays on Mind, Self and Emotion, edited by R. A. Shweder and R . A . Levine . Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press. Shweder, R . A ., J . Goodnow, G . Hatano, R . A . LeVine, H . Markus, and P . Miller. 1998 . "The Cultural Psychology of Development : One Mind, Many Mentalities ." Pp . 865-937 in Handbook of Child Psychology, 5th Edition, Volume 1 : Theoretical Models of Human Development, edited by R . M . Lerner ; W. Damon, series editor. New York : Wiley. Shweder, R. A ., and M . A, Sullivan 1993 . "Cultural Psychology : Who Needs It?" Annual Review of Psychology 44 : 497-523 . Smetana, J. G. 1988 . "Adolescents' and Parents' Conceptions of Parental Authority ." Child Development 59 : 321-335 . Smetana, J . G. 1989. "Adolescents' and Parents' Reasoning about Actual Family Conflicts ." Child Development 60: 1052-1067 . Smetana, J . G . 1995a. "Conflict and Coordination in Adolescent-parent Relationships." Pp. 155-184 in Close Relationships and Socioemotional Development, edited by S . Shulman . Norwood, NJ : Ablex. Smetana, J. G . 1995b . "Context, Conflict, and Constraint in Adolescent-parent Authority Relationships." Pp . 225-255 in Morality in Everyday Life, edited by M. Killen and D . Hart . Cambridge : Cambridge University Press . Smetana, J. G . 1995c . "Morality in Context: Abstractions, Ambiguities, and Applications." Pp . 83-130 in Annals of Child Development, Vol . 10, edited by R . Vasta. London: Jessica Kingsley Publishers, Ltd. Smetana, J. G . 1995d . "Parenting Styles and Conceptions of Parental Authority During Adolescence ." Child Development 66: 299-316. Smetana, J . G . 1996. "Adolescent-parent Conflict : Implications for Adaptive and Maladaptive Development ." Pp . 1-46 in Rochester Symposium on Developmental Psychopathology, edited by D . Cicchetti and S . Toth. Rochester, NY : University of Rochester Press .
Cultural Contexts and Processes
227
Smetana, J . G. In press. "Middle-class African American Adolescents' and Parents' Conceptions of Parental Authority and Parenting Practices ." Child Development . Smetana, J . G . in preparation . "Clean Your Room!" : A Longitudinal Investigation of Adolescent-parent Conflict in Middle-class African American Families . Unpublished manuscript, University of Rochester. Smetana, J . G ., and P. Asquith. 1994 . "Adolescents' and Parents' Conceptions of Parental Authority and Adolescent Autonomy ." Child Development 65 : 1147-1162 . Smetana, J . G ., and R . Berent. 1993 . "Adolescents' and Mothers' Evaluations of Justifications for Disputes ." Journal of Adolescent Research 8 : 252-273 . Smetana, J . G ., J. L . Braeges, and J . Yau . 1991 . "Doing What You Say and Saying What You Do : Reasoning about Adolescent-parent Conflict in Interviews and Interactions ." Journal of Adolescent Research 6: 276-295 . Smetana, J . G ., and C . Gaines . 1999. "Adolescent-parent Conflict in Middle-class African American Families ." Child Development 70 : 1447-1463 . Smetana, J. G ., J . Yau,, and S . Hanson 1991 . "Conflict Resolution in Families with Adolescents ." Journal of Research on Adolescence 1 : 189-206 . Smetana, J . G ., J . Yau, A . Restrepo, and J . Braeges . 1991 . "Adolescent-parent Conflict in Married and Divorced Families ." Developmental Psychology 27 : 1000-1010 . Steelman, L . C ., and B . Powell 1996 . "The Family Devalued: The Treatment of the Family in Small Groups Literature." Pp . 211-236 in Advances in Group Process, Vol . 13, edited by B . Markovsky, M . J . Lovaglia, and R. Simon . Greenwich, CT: JAI Press, Inc . Steinberg, L . 1990. "Interdependency in the Family : Autonomy, Conflict, And Harmony in the Parent-adolescent Relationship ." Pp. 255-276 in At the Threshhold: The Developing Adolescent, edited by S . S . Feldman and G . R . Elliot. Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press . Strauss, C . 1992 . "Models and Motives ." In Human Motives and Cultural Models, edited by R . G . D'Andrade and C . Strauss . New York : Cambridge University Press . Tisak, M . 1995 . "Domains of Social Reasoning and Beyond ." Pp . 95-130 in Annals of Child Development, Vol . 11, edited by R . Vasta . London, Jessica Kingsley . Triandis, H . C . 1989 . "The Self and Social Behavior in Differing Cultural Contexts ." Psychological Review 96 : 508-520 . Triandis, H . C. 1990 . "Cross-cultural Studies of Individualism and Collectivism ." Pp . 41-133 in 1989 Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, Vol 37: Cross Cultural Perspectives, edited by J . J . Berman . Lincoln : University of Nebraska Press . Turiel, E . 1983 . The Development of Social Knowledge : Morality and Convention. Cambridge : Cambridge University Press. Turiel, E. 1998 . "Moral Development." Pp. 863-932 in Handbook of Child Psychology, 5th Edition, Volume 3 : Social, Emotional, and Personality Development, edited by N . Eisenberg; W . Damon, series editor . New York: Wiley . Turiel, E . 1999 . "Conflict, Social Development, and Cultural Change ." Pp. 77-92 in New Directions for Child Development, Vol. 83: Development and Cultural Change : Reciprocal Processes, edited by E . Turiel . San Francisco : Jossey-Bass . Wainryb, C ., and E . Turiel . 1994 . "Dominance, Subordination, and Concepts of Personal Entitlements in Cultural Contexts ." Child Development 65 : 1701-1722. Yau, J ., and J . G . Smetana . 1996 . "Adolescent-parent Conflict among Chinese Adolescents in Hong Kong ." Child Development 67 : 1262-1275 . Yau, J., and J . G. Smetana . in preparation. Reasoning about Adolescent-parent Conflict and Dilemmas : Comparisons Between Chinese Adolescents in Hong Kong and China . Unpublished paper, University of Rochester . Youniss, J ., and J. Smollar. 1985 . Adolescents' Relations with Mothers, Fathers, and Friends . Chicago : University of Chicago Press .
CONTAGION OF STRESS
Elaine Wethington
ABSTRACT The purpose of this paper is to address recent theoretical and methodological developments relating to social and organizational aspects of stress . Further advances are dependent on a more thorough exploration of stress contagion processes . Contagion is defined as a cascade of demands and consequent emotional arousal from one area of life into another, between closely related individuals, and across the life course . Stress originates in the daily course of life as a consequence of social interaction in dyads and groups, opportunities and challenges shaped by social structure, and constraints and demands channeled by organizations and institutions . The paper focuses on three types of stress contagion as social aspects of the stress process, spillover, crossover, and stress trajectories. The review raises new questions to address in this area, and reviews data and methodological work that sheds light on the three types of contagion . In the view of the author, the most fruitful path for advancing research on stress contagion is to combine the insights of more qualitative research with data derived from empirically rigorous quantitative designs and analytic strategies . Researchers should combine careful theoretical analysis of stress processes with measurement technologies capable of distinguishing individual personality factors from situational, socially created factors . The paper also examines the relative strengths and shortcomings of several different research design strategies to advance
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 229-253 . Copyright © 2000 by JAI Press Inc . All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 229
230
ELAINE WETHINCTON
theory and measurement : (1) life event measurement techniques more sensitive to stress contagion, (2) life history data collection, measuring stress contagion over time, (3) longitudinal prospective studies of stress contagion, (4) paired-informant and group-level designs, (5) daily diary techniques, and (6) experience sampling .
INTRODUCTION In recent years more advanced measurement of the experience of stress and the content of stressors originating in the environment have entered the social scientific literature (for a review see Wethington, Almeida, Brown, Frank, and Kessler forthcoming) . Yet much remains to be done to take advantage of this new sophistication in measurement . Development of theories of the stress process and its relationship to mental and physical health has not kept pace with measurement innovations (Thoits 1995) . The major argument of this paper is that medical sociology must integrate basic social theory on stress processes with more powerful measurement techniques . Fundamental to this process is a more thorough exploration of stress contagion processes . Contagion is defined as a cascade of demands and consequent emotional arousal from one area of life into another, between closely related individuals, and across the life course . I focus on stress contagion as an under-explored social aspect of the stress process . Traditional stress research, even in sociology, has focused on the individual . This characteristic alone has tended to marginalize stress researchers from the larger field of sociology . But as many sociological stress researchers have stated (e .g . Pearlin, Menaghan, Lieberman, and Mullan 1981) the process of stress is essentially social . Stress originates in the daily course of life as a consequence of social interaction in dyads and groups, opportunities and challenges shaped by social structure, and constraints and demands channeled by organizations . Research on stress as a process unites members of multiple disciplines, and recently has acquired increased prominence . Major research initiatives are underway to understand why mortality is inversely related to social status (Adler, Chesney, Cohen, Folkman, Kahn, and Syme 1994) . Many prominent researchers in public health, medicine, and psychology have asserted that stress processes may hold the key to understanding the persistence of this social gradient in health, despite decades of social policies aimed at eradicating it (McEwen and Stellar 1993 ; Williams 1990) . It is thus important for medical sociology to refocus theory and empirical research on the social causes of disease (e .g ., Link and Phelan 1995), an area where general sociology has much to contribute . Where is current sociological research on stress, and is it up to the challenge? Several prominent researchers in sociology have reviewed research on stress and its relationship to disease (e .g., Kessler 1997 ; Link and Phelan 1995 ; Thoits 1995) and have found it generally wanting for the enormity of this task.
231
Stress Contagion
Thoits (1995) identified five areas where stress research and theory requires new development . Prominent among these five areas is the study of contagion, or "carry-over" (p . 57) of stressors across different domains of life and between linked individuals . Another is the development of theory linking multiple physical and psychological outcomes in response to stress . The third is a theory of stressor "sequencing" (pp . 57-58), as events unfold in the short term (one stressor rapidly followed by another) or the long term (childhood stressors leading to a propensity to experience related stressors during adulthood) . This too, is a type of contagion, in that there is a considerable amount of evidence that social and personal history factors shape exposure to subsequent stressors (e .g ., Hammen 1992) . The fourth is the development of formal theory outlining the positive effects of stressors, which hints at why people might seek stress in some instances . The fifth is further specification of the sources of "meaning" in people's lives that cause them to experience something as very stressful or less stressful . I argue that stressor theory must build on a thorough understanding of hierarchies in social systems, including how hierarchies produce graded exposure to stressors, and provide the resources to deal with them (Pearlin and Schooler 1978). Contributions to theory in each of the five areas Thoits (1995) identified would represent a significant addition to social scientific theory on stress . The purpose of this paper is to address recent theoretical and methodological developments relating to the contagion of stress . The review raises new questions to address in this area, and reviews data and methodological work that sheds light on all of the aforementioned areas .
THE PHENOMENON OF STRESS CONTAGION The Real-World Importance of Stress Contagion
Stressor exposure across the life course and how it differs across individuals is hypothesized to underlie major social patterns in society, such as the gradient in mortality by social class (Elo and Preston 1996) . Neuropsychologists (e .g ., McEwen and Stellar 1993), epidemiologists (e .g ., Lynch, Kaplan, and Shema 1997), and mutidisciplinary research teams (e .g ., Marmot, Fuhrer, Ettner, Marks, Bumpass, and Ryff 1998) have applied theories of stress exposure and reactivity to explain the social gradient in health . Stress exposure is also a signficant contributor to social class differences in mental disorder (e .g ., Turner, Wheaton, and Lloyd 1995) . Increasingly, studies examining the impact of stress on health focus on chronic, long-term exposure to persistent and chronic sources of stress . Long-term exposure to persistently adverse conditions affects both physical and mental health . There is considerable evidence that chronic stress exposure compromises the immune system and overstimulates the cardiovascular system (e .g ., McEwen and
2 32
ELAINE WETHINGTON
Stellar 1993). Exposure to persistent stress also results in negative emotions, which are implicated in both physical health deterioration (e .g ., Karasek and Theorell 1990) and susceptibility to new stressors (Brown, Bifulco, and Harris 1987) . Contagion processes are intimately connected to the experience of chronic stress . Long-term relationships (e .g ., parenting, caregiving) are potent sources of stress, as well as support . For example, parenting and giving care increase exposure to demands and interpersonal conflict . These demands carry normative obligations, enforced by social practice, making them relatively difficult to escape when they escalate to a higher level (cf . Brown, Harris, and Hepworth 1995 ; Aneshensel, Pearlin, Mullan, Zarit, and Whitlatch 1995) . Role entrapment can prevent participation in other roles that may provide compensating rewards and support (e .g ., Marks 1998 ; Wethington and Kessler 1989) . Work can also be a potent source of stress contagion, over which one often has little control (Karasek and Theorell 1990) . Demands from work can also require physical and mental effort beyond the social reward a position offers (Siegrist 1998) . Definition of "Stress Contagion"
Stress contagion is a multidimensional construct . Thoits (1995) described three types of stress contagion, across domains of life within individuals, across individuals related by role or group, and within individuals across time. The three types of stress contagion, their distinguishing characteristics, and putative mechanisms are summarized in Table 1 . The first type of contagion consists of stressors that cross the boundary from one domain of a person's life to another, such as stress crossing the work-family boundary . Staines (1980) gave this phenomenon the label spillover, and I refer to this type of contagion as spillover throughout the remainder of this chapter . Staines theorized that spillover was likely to occur through processes of role con-
Table 1 . Subtype
Types of Stress Contagion
Distinguishing Factors
Spillover
Within person Across domains
Crossover
Across people
Stress Trajectory
Within person Across time
Mechanisms Objective conflict between roles Role overload Extended responsibility Preferences for activity Shared fate Obligations Commitments Stress reactivity Latency Cognitive schemata Developmental pathways
Stress Contagion
233
flict, role overload, extended responsibility, and individual preferences for one activity over another (assuming that less preferred activities are more likely to cause resentment that will carry over into other activities) . Many researchers have examined the spillover process using conventional retrospective survey methods (cf . Eckenrode and Gore 1990), examining the cross-sectional association of "stress" in two areas of life . A significant correlation is regarded as consistent with the presence of spillover . These studies are limited, however, because a significant correlation does not constitute evidence of cause . Correlations offer only indirect evidence that spillover accounts for the association, rather than characteristics of the person or measurement bias . In response to the methodological limitations of traditional survey research, a number of social psychologists have begun to examine spillover on a daily basis, relating the frequency of reports of daily stressors in one area of life to reports of daily stressors in another area of life . These researchers examine the within-person correlation of different types of daily stressors on the same day, or the persistence, or chronicity, of stressors occurring within the same person over time (see below, for a description of the various methods now being used .) Bolger, DeLongis, Kessler, and Wethington (1989, 1990) described spillover between work and family in a sample of married couples, documenting that the experience of overload in one role (e .g ., work) was likely to be associated, on the same day, with reporting overload in another . Arguments at work were correlated with arguments at home . Reports of arguments on one day, moreover, were likely to be related to arguments the next day, indicating a contagion effect across time in the same individual . Overall, stress in one role doubled the chances of experiencing stress in another role . The analyses suggested stress was as likely to spill over from home to work as it was to spill over from work to home . (They also documented that men were as likely as women to experience spillover of stress between work and home, and the more surprising finding that men were more likely than women to carry home stress to work the next day .) Several other groups of investigators have utilized short-term longitudinal designs to study spillover (e .g ., Almeida, Wethington, and Chandler 1999 ; Repetti and Wood 1997) . The second type of stress contagion involves stressors that cross from one linked person to another. Staines (1980) described this as the process of crossover (see Table 1) . Most formal study of this phenomenon takes place in the setting of the family . Bolger and colleagues (1989b, 1990) documented processes of crossover between husbands and wives in the same family on a daily basis . For example, they found that spillover of work stress sets into motion a set of responses and adjustments from other household members--crossover. Spouses, more often wives, appeared to be increasing their efforts at home to relieve work stress of the other spouse. Subsequently, Almeida and colleagues (1999) documented stress crossover between parents and children, specifically that marital arguments raise the probability of subsequent arguments with children . Repetti and Wood (1997)
234
ELAINE WETHINGTON
found that overload at work leads to withdrawal from family in the evening, a strategy that might shield children from parental tempers, but might also lead to emotional distance or isolation (see also Almeida, Wethington, and MacDonald forthcoming) . Crossover is a somewhat more complicated phenomenon than spillover, and that has made measurement more difficult. (The ideal documentation of crossover of stress would require gathering data from linked individuals, or from group members affected by the same stressor .) Crossover may occur through passive exposure, that is, exposure to another's troubles increasing one's own . (Hence the folk wisdom, "Don't marry someone who has more problems than you .") Examples of this process are stressful events that affect an entire household or group . I refer to this type of crossover as linked fate (see Table 1) . An example of the mechanism of linked fate is the impact of job loss on an entire household . Another type of crossover occurs through obligation . Obligations between closely related individuals lead to the transmission of negative emotion, and also the expectation that the non-affected person will provide comfort and support (e.g ., Wethington, McLeod, and Kessler 1987) . For example, in the case of job loss, the spouse might bear the burden of emotional burden of support, while also shielding the children from those emotional burdens . A third type of crossover may result from commitment . Commitment and involvement may produce more vulnerability to another person's stressors (e.g ., Kessler and McLeod 1984) . People may differ in their propensity to empathize, or become involved in a practical way . A close friend is more likely to become emotionally and practically involved in job loss, than a less-acquainted individual . The third type of stress contagion is the stress trajectory . The stress trajectory, unlike the processes of spillover and crossover, is defined more as a characteristic of the individual than as a characteristic of the environment . Researchers assume that the long-term effects of physical and psychological trauma and other major stressors may create a trajectory of increased stressor exposure and susceptibility to stressors across the life course (e .g ., Keane 1998 ; Kessler, Gillis-Light, Magee, Kendler, and Eaves 1997) . For example, abuse and neglect during childhood may produce emotional reactivity to social relationship stressors in adulthood, such as the heightened reactivity to severe events among women who experienced a lack of care during childhood (Harris, Brown, and Bifulco 1990) . Childhood experiences may create a sensitivity (or latency) to events during adulthood that require similar types of adjustment . Severe events that produce post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) may have a long-term impact on stress reactivity throughout the life course (e .g ., Keane 1998) . Events that occur early in life (even prenatally) may affect brain development and produce latent physical and psychological vulnerability to chronic stress later in life (see Kuh, Power, Blane, and Bartley 1997) . Another possible mechanism is cognitive schemata that frame action and reaction to events . Some reseachers have argued that schemata created by chronically stressful conditions in childhood, such as insecure relationships with parents, pro-
2 35
Stress Contagion
duce disordered or insecure relationships in adulthood (e .g ., Mickelson, Kessler, and Shaver 1997) . Others argue that stressful childhood environments produce a developmental pathway (or trajectory) that maximizes exposure to stressors (Power and Hertzman 1997) . Major Theoretical Perspectives on Stress Contagion
Consistent with the definitions used for stress contagion, and the wide variety of phenomena included under this umbrella, there is no single theoretical perspective that encompasses stress contagion . The models utilized are eclectic at best, combining sociological, psychological, biological, and sometimes organizational approaches . Most studies of stress contagion are inductive and descriptive, offering post hoc explanations for why stressors co-occur . Others rely primarily on personality or biopsychological explanations, rather than propositions derived from formal social psychological or sociological theory, to explain group differences in reactivity to stressors or group differences in the propensity to report stress contagion . In sociology, six major theoretical perspectives have contributed to studies of stress contagion . These are the social role perspective, the social ecological perspective, the transactional model of stress, the long-term contextual threat perspective, the life course perspective, and the feminist perspective . The Social Role Perspective
The major sociological perspective utilized to explain contagion of stress is the social role perspective (e .g ., Goode 1960) . This approach tends to focus on stress spillover across roles assumed to be in conflict with one another (Goode 1960) (see Table 1) . Staines (1980) summarized research on role-related spillover from work to private life, and introduced three additional ways to study spillover across role boundaries . One of the most widely used assesses degree of involvement in roles . Spillover is predicted to increase where there is greater objective involvement, such as long work hours, or energy-demanding activities . Cultural expectations (e .g ., those associated with gender) and skill level and preparation are assumed to produce individual differences in role involvement. Staines hypothesized that another type of spillover occurs when role expectations make demands that take up a significant amount of time, through extended hours of responsibility outside official "hours" at the task . For example, responsibility for a baby extends beyond waking hours, and even into hours when someone else may be watching the child . Scarce resources, for example, time, energy, and creativity, lead to spillover. A third mechanism for spillover, preference for a type of activity, is created by expectations . Preferences lead to personal decisions that may cause spillover . For example, despite a demanding job that requires travel and frequent absences, an employee may still desire to marry and have a family . Exercising the preference
236
ELAINE WETHINGTON
to marry and reproduce creates spillover . Individual preference for activity plays a strong role in stress exposure (e .g ., Marks 1977) and may even explain why, overall, population studies have not found consistently that stressor exposure differs by social class (see Thoits 1995) . The majority of this work concerns contagion between work and family (cf . Moen 1992), where all the suggested mechanisms hold sway . The social role perspective is also applicable to stress crossover between two connected individuals . Goode (1960) raised this possibility in his discussion of role involvement and commitment between role partners . Kessler and McLeod (1984), Kessler, McLeod, and Wethington (1985), and Wethington, McLeod, and Kessler (1987) argued that gender differences in the experience of stress crossover might explain some of the gender difference in psychological distress (for an empirical demonstration, see Bolger et al . 1989a) . Women's roles may expose them to more stressors experienced by significant others (Kessler and McLeod 1984 ; Almeida and Kessler 1998) . Women are obligated to provide services to family members, which increases burdens and demands (Wethington, McLeod, and Kessler 1987) . Finally, gender role training might produce more empathic responses in women (Kessler, McLeod, and Wethington 1985) The Social Ecological Perspective Bronfenbrenner's (1979) perspective on ecological development links social structural processes (macroprocesses) to individual behavior, experience, and development (microprocesses), mediated by mesoprocesses (e .g ., family structure and roles). Recently, Bronfenbrenner (1995) urged researchers to examine more fully the proximal processes that lead to long-term behavior outcomes . Proximal processes are defined as enduring and repetitive interactions in a given group or environment, that recur frequently and form the typical climate of a group . Typical stress contagion processes in families are an excellent example of proximal processes that affect long-term development at a group and individual level . Observations on everyday stress crossover suggest that stress transmits through many potential paths in a group setting . First, one person in a dyad (or larger group) can experience a life stressor that has objective impact on others . Events that have this quality are major changes in life such as job loss, which can affect everyone in the family through adjustments to financial hardship and family decision making . The pregnancy or illness of one member of a work group may increase demands on others . Second, crossover can occur through emotional transmission . There are two subtypes of emotional transmission . The first is when others in a group are affected by the emotional reaction of one of their members to a stressor . Organizational settings produce many opportunities for this, such as when other workers must accommodate or adjust to a co-worker with marital problems . The second subtype is when the emotional affect of a member not nec-
Stress Contagion
237
essarily linked to an event or objective change has a negative psychological impact on other members The social ecological perspective, like the social role perspective, contributes directly to testable propositions of stress contagion involving spillover and crossover (e .g ., Repetti and Wood 1997) . At the social level it does not make a major contribution to the study of stress trajectories . The person-environment-context model (Bronfenbrenner 1995) will probably provide a stronger framework for conceptualizing the stress trajectory as a contagion process . The Transactional Model of Stress Most sociologists view Lazarus's transactional model of stress (Lazarus and Folkman 1984) as an individual, even personality-based perspective on the stress process . Many applications of the model in psychology emphasize individual differences in response, at the expense of differences in stress exposure (at both the individual and group level) (e .g ., Peacock and Wong 1990) . The conceptualization of the transactional model, however, strongly emphasized social and environmental processes . Measurement of the social processes has not kept pace, and many believe it has sometimes confounded stressor exposure with psychological processes (e .g ., Dohrenwend, Dohrenwend, Dodson, and Shrout 1984) . In the transactional model, response to a stressor is conditioned by cognitive appraisal and coping . Cognitive appraisal is believed to underlie the emotional experience of stress . Measures of appraisal focus on the degree to which an event threatens well-being or threatens to overwhelm resources to cope (Lazarus and Folkman 1984) . The former is referred to as primary appraisal, the latter as secondary appraisal . Primary appraisal is hypothesized to determine short-term emotional response . Lazarus's measure of stakes delineates dimensions of well-being, or stakes, that comprise primary appraisal dimensions . Stakes include threats to health, losses of and threats to important relationships, and threats to physical safety (Folkman, Dunkel-Schetter, DeLongis, and Gruen 1986) . Stakes can apply not only to a threat to the focal respondents, but also to threats to the well-being of significant others . The "stake" in another's well-being is hypothesized to increase through all three "crossover" contagion processes : linked fate, role obligation, and commitment (see Table 1) . The transactional model of stress proposes a set of processes that may relate to spillover . The model assumes that spillover occurs through various connections that carry from one area of life to another . For example, a problem at home threatens a woman's financial future by distracting her from her job . The transactional model of stress also proposes mechanisms for stress trajectories : unsuccessful past experience coping with a stressor of a particular type can lead to perceptions of greater stressor threat (Lazarus and Folkman 1984) . As stated previously, the transactional model of stress does not permeate sociological analysis of stress, despite its conceptual breadth and its attendance to envi-
238
ELAINE WETHINGTON
ronmental and situational factors . This situation most likely stems from the fact that measures of stakes are self-report, and thus are feared to be confounded with mood (the outcome variable in most studies) . This situation may change in the future through advances in measurement . Almeida (1998) has developed investigator-rated, rather than self-report measure of dimensions of threat (see below) . Such measures reduce self-report bias in the reporting of dimensions of threat . Long-Term Contextual Threat
There is one other well-known perspective on the measurement of environmental processes believed to provoke stress . Long-term contextual threat (Brown and Harris 1978 ; Brown 1989) was developed to systematize observation of stressors, and their rating for likely impact on health . The perspective states that emotional or physical distress results when external stressors approach a highly unpleasant or disruptive level . There are three major components to this perspective . First, the emotional impact of a stressor is heightened or reduced by the ability of an individual to alleviate the consequences (similar to secondary appraisal [Lazarus and Folkman 1984], but rated by investigators rather than self-report) . Second, events involving relationships are more or less threatening to health, depending on the existence and availability of other network connections . Third, health-damaging events have unpleasant characteristics, such as objective threat and danger to continued life and health, and exposure to this unpleasantness is structured partially by social status and gender . Brown and Harris developed a system, the Life Events and Difficulties Schedule (LEDS : Brown and Harris 1978) to rate the contextual threat of events and chronic stressors, classifying severity and type of threat subsequent to the exposure . This is an investigator-based, rather than self-rated system, utilizing objective features of particular events believed to make the occurrence more disruptive, unpleasant, or threatening to future life and plans . One of the critical dimensions of the rating system is focus, defined as to whom the event occurs . Many events are classified as "jointly" occurring to the victim and the focal respondent, primarily because of the intense emotional and practical involvement of the respondent in the consequent course of the event . Events of the highest level of severity occurring to others are in many instances rated as posing severe threat, that is, likely to evoke an episode of illness . The system also rates chronic stressors ("difficulties") involving obligations to others. The rating of severity of difficulty is dependent on evidence of two types of contagion processes, spillover and crossover . If a chronic difficulty spills over from one area of life to another, the LEDS system may (dependent on other characteristics) rate it at a higher category of severity . Chronic stressors that affect entire families, for example, unemployment, would be rated as relatively more severe if their impact "crosses over" to affect children and spouse .
239
Stress Contagion
Not every severe event or difficulty involving another person is rated in the LEDS system . The other person must be a "key tie," someone who has been previously rated (by the investigators) as providing essential emotional or practical support to the respondent, or who is a close family member with whom the respondent maintains close emotional ties and very frequent contact . These are the relationships hypothesized to result in a higher probability of crossover . The LEDS system includes investigator-based measures of life-time adversity and exposure to stressors . Many investigations using the LEDS utilize an instrument asking for reports of critical events in childhood, such as family breakup, deaths of siblings, long-term poverty, separation from parents, and severe punishment or abuse, events hypothesized to produce developmental trajectories more likely to lead to stressor exposure (Power and Hertzman 1997) . In analyses of the risk of illness following life stress, investigators examine whether the impact of a stressor during adulthood is heightened when the individual has a history of similar, or related childhood events . Several investigators have criticized the LEDS rating system for confounding exposure to stressors with individual social and emotional vulnerability to stressors, concepts that many investigators prefer to keep separate (e .g., Dohrewend, Raphael, Schwartz, Stueve, and Skodol 1993 ) . It is fair to say that the severity summary ratings produced by the LEDS do in many cases confound the two processes . In the case of stress contagion, American investigators applying the theoretical insights of the LEDS perspective have tried to separate these aspects of the ratings . They have used LEDS questions to measure stress exposure more objectively, paired with conventional measures of vulnerability (e .g ., Mattlin, Wethington, and Kessler 1990 ; Kessler and Wethington 1991) . The Life Course Perspective
The life course perspective (e .g ., Elder, George, and Shanahan 1996) addresses the issue of contagion through stress trajectories more successfully than the majority of the perspectives reviewed above (long-term contextual threat is the exception) . Strictly speaking, the life course perspective has served as a sensitizing construct, rather than a formal theory, in research on stress contagion . Its role has been to remind researchers that time, position in the life course, and relationship history play a part in stress contagion, and subsequently health (Kuh, Power, Blane, and Bartley 1997) . For example, spillover of stress across domains of life is facilitated by commitments that develop across the life course (e .g ., parenthood), or which are significantly increased by position in the life course (e .g ., commitment to career in midlife) . The concept of "linked lives" (Elder et al . 1996) relates directly to crossover of stress between role partners . (Elder's description is not unlike the notion of "key ties" used in the rating of contextual threat .) There are many applications of the process in the literature . For example, numerous researchers using conventional
2 40
ELAINE WETHINGTON
survey techniques (Kessler and McRae 1982 ; McLanahan and Glass 1985 ; Ross, Mirowsky, and Huber 1983) have found that the relative psychological distress of husbands and wives in married couples is dependent not only on personal events, but also on the role stress, life events, and attitudes of their spouses . More intensive investigations of the phenomenon have yielded insight into the types of contagion processes involved in these findings . Weiss (1990) found that middle-aged men whose wives became more committed to work after the children reached adolescence were resentful of having to become more involved in their children's problems . Bolger and colleagues (1990) found that men married to women who worked more than 20 hours a week were more emotionally distressed by stressors at home than men whose wives worked fewer hours . The life course perspective contributes the most creatively to examining stress trajectories . Health epidemiologists have applied the life course perspective to hypothesizing pathway effects across the individual life course (e .g ., Kuh et al. 1997 ; Power and Hertzman 1997) . The life course perspective may hold particular promise for understanding the social gradient in adult health status and mortality . Epidemiologists now assume that the critical mechanisms causing the social gradient in health are related to stress contagion through individual health trajectories . For example, risk factors for disease later in life tend to accumulate differentially for individuals of different social origins and educational attainment (e .g ., Marmot et al . 1998) . Educational attainment may reverse or moderate these risk factors (e .g., Power and Hertzman 1997), while events negatively affecting socioeconomic status may increase health risk across time (e .g ., McDonough, House, and Williams 1997) . Many life event researchers (e .g ., Turner, Wheaton, and Lloyd 1995) now incorporate events across the lifetime in measurement of stressor exposure . Feminist Theoretical Perspectives
The life course perspective now holds sway as the major critique of traditional role and stress perspectives in examining contagion of stress . Before the life course perspective, however, the feminist theoretical perspective made major contributions to work on stress contagion (in fact, it has been almost entirely incorporated into applications of social role [e .g ., Simon 1995] and life course perspectives [e .g ., Moen 1992]) . It could be argued that feminist perspectives reoriented stress and role theory during the past 25 years . The three major theoretical feminist theorists whose work contributed to stress contagion theory were Bernard (1972), Chodorow (1978), and Gilligan (1982) . Investigators in the field of stress used their work to critique stressor measurement extant in the 1970s and 1980s . For example, the feminist perspective suggests that women are exposed to more stressors, and that those stressors emanate from women's caring roles (e .g ., Gilligan 1982), a source of stress not well represented on earlier measures of stressor exposure . Bernard
241
Stress Contagion
(1972) argued that social norms and institutions produce different types of stressors for men and women, resulting in consistent differences in the experiences of marriage, parenting, and work . Early measurement of stressor exposure paid much less attention to how the content, severity, and context of stressor exposure might differ across gender . Chodorow (1978) asserted that women are socialized to be more empathic toward the feelings of others, and thus reactive to requests for help and assistance . Researchers have used all three of these insights from the feminist perspective to explain why women report more psychological distress and depression than men . A frequently offered explanation for the gender difference is that women's traditional roles expose them to more stress spillover and crossover (e .g ., Belle, 1983 ; Eckenrode 1984 ; Kessler, McLeod, and Wethington 1985) .
ADVANCING RESEARCH ON STRESS CONTAGION In the view of the author, the most fruitful path for advancing research on stress contagion is to combine the insights of more qualitative research with data derived from empirically rigorous quantitative designs and analytic strategies (see also Thoits 1995) . The strategy is to combine careful theoretical analysis of stress processes with measurement technologies capable of distinguishing person factors from situational factors . The remainder of the chapter examines the relative strengths and shortcomings of (1) modified life event measurement strategies, more attentive to stress contagion, (2) life history data techniques, measuring stress contagion over time, (3) longitudinal prospective studies of stress contagion, (4) paired-informant and group-level designs, (5) daily diary techniques, and (6) experience sampling .
Life Event Measurement Strategies There are three major advances in life event measurement relevant to the measurement of stress contagion, asking about events occurring to others, inquiring about chronic stress contagion, and assessing life-time exposure to trauma and other major events . More recent life event measurement strategies almost always include questions about the stressors of closely related others (e.g ., Kessler and Wethington 1991 ; Turner et al . 1995) . Another major addition to life events measurement is including questions about stress contagion processes, such as the experience of work-family conflict and giving care to others . Increasingly, major studies incorporating life event and other stressor measures (e .g ., the National Comorbidity Study [Kessler 1994] and other comprehensive community surveys [Wheaton, Rozell, and Hall 1997]) include key events from childhood and exposure to traumas across the life course . These methods are designed for use in large-scale studies . Investigators have used them to examine stress crossover in
2 42
ELAINE WETHINGTON
family relationships (stressors occurring to spouses and children), work-family spillover, and long-term emotional impact of abuse, neglect, and family breakup during childhood or adolescence . Investigator-rated methods of stress exposure (e .g ., Brown 1989) and resources to buffer the impact of stress (e .g ., Brown 1992) include even more detailed measures of events and chronic stressors . For example, the LEDS scans for events that occurred to closely related others besides spouse and children . It can detect spillover between any two aspects of life, and also measures life-time stressor exposure more comprehensively . LEDS and LEDS-style techniques, however, rely on more intensive interviewing techniques and highly trained interviewers . Only a small proportion of these techniques have been standardized and shortened for large survey use (Wethington, Brown, and Kessler 1995) . The increasing practice of including measures of chronic stressors when assessing exposure to life events has increased the focus on stress contagion processes . Unfortunately, measures of chronic stressors raise serious methodological problems . The difficulty is due to the fact that traditional measures of chronic stress rely on appraisal of stressors . A typical measure of chronic stressors is a set of questions designed to measure the more frequently occurring stressors in important life roles, such as work and family (e .g ., Pearlin and Schooler 1978) . Thus in such measures it is unclear whether a report of more frequent or "chronic" exposure is due to objective demands from the environment or to the coping and appraisal evaluation process of the person reporting it, including prior psychological functioning (Kessler 1997 ; Lepore 1995) . Recency bias also affects the self-reported severity of chronic stressors . The most recent level of severity affects the self-rating of activity over a longer retrospective period (Herbert and Cohen 1996) . In general, all self-report measures of life event exposure suffer from these methodological problems, although they are more acute for measures of chronic stressors (Kessler 1997) . Retrospective Life History Data The use of life history data might prove particularly helpful for exploratory study of stress trajectories . Large, multivariate retrospective quantitative life history surveys are useful in identifying patterns or sequences of stress contagion over time in a person's life (e .g ., Wheaton et al . 1997) . Large surveys such as these have identified particular events in childhood that over time are associated with greater emotional vulnerability and stressor exposure during adulthood (see also Hammen 1992) . Retrospective research of this type can identify and describe patterns that are indicative of selection into more stressful or disruptive environments . However, it is not likely to identify the underlying causes of selecting one trajectory over another . Although respondents to such surveys can reliably recall major events and transitions (Kessler and Wethington 1991), even from the relatively distant past (Brown and Harris 1982), this applies only to the objective
Stress Contagion
243
characteristics of the events . Subjective states and aspects are most likely affected by recall or recency bias (Herbert and Cohen 1996) . They are also affected by selective processes in autobiographical memory (Rubin, Rahhal, and Poon 1998) and in the search for cause, or meaning, in past events (Ross and Newby-Clark 1998) . Thus, the data generated may be limited in important ways . Further research is needed on how autobiographical memory affects the recall of life history before stress contagion effects can be reliably estimated using retrospective techniques . Longitudinal Life History Data
Acknowledging the limitations of studying such a dynamic process as stress contagion in retrospective designs, researchers typically turn to longitudinal studies . Longitudinal studies are useful if they include groups predicted to be at very high risk of stress contagion . Examples of such groups are men and women making the transition to parenthood, and middle-aged daughters whose parents are becoming more physically and emotionally dependent on them . Stress contagion is likely to occur under conditions of high demand, or where new duties are apt to be very unpleasant or tension-inducing . Longitudinal studies are particularly effective if they have collected data over a very long period of time from the same individuals . Multiple-year panel surveys are more likely to observe long-term changes in people's lives (McDonogh et al . 1997) . They are also more likely to capture relatively rare role transitions, for example, such as divorce, remarriage, and widowhood, for more individuals . A challenge for users of the long-term studies, however, is that relatively few contain information that reflects more contemporary research questions on stress contagion . Moreover, most existing longitudinal surveys rely on retrospective assessment over periods of a year or more . Investigators can only conclude, post hoc, that stress contagion has occurred, not determine which processes produced the contagion . Longitudinal studies can effectively address some questions regarding contagion, if the studies have useful measures addressing its theoretical causes . The essence of the problem that a history of chronic difficulties poses to researchers is that chronic relationship stress cannot be assumed to be taking place independent of prior emotional health. There is considerable evidence that relationship difficulties and poor health in adulthood emanate from a history of relationship disorder (Mickelson et al . 1997) . In other words, exposure to the conditions that cause contagion may not be random with respect to the health outcome under investigation . For further information about this methodological problem, see Wethington and Kessler (1993) . Some of these issues can be effectively addressed through careful, prospective research concentrated on one transition at a time (e .g ., Kessler 1997) . These studies (e .g ., Aseltine and Kessler 1993) examine the long-term health consequences
244
ELAINE WETHINCTON
of severe events . Event effects are known to differ across individuals, and studies such as these have suggested that what makes the difference is whether the particular event puts into motion long-term chronic stressors that compound the emotional impact of the event on health . Paired-Informant Designs
Longitudinal study of stress contagion across relationships over the life course might be enhanced if relationships were studied over time, rather than individuals, and from the perspective of more than one person in the relationship . The relationship, multiple-informant design is most common for studies of married couples and families (e .g ., Bolger et al . 1989a), but it could be extended to include other dyadic or triadic relationships where stress contagion is likely . Multiple-informant designs can be used to help overcome some of the difficulties that arise from memory bias, such as forgetting events (e .g ., Kessler and Wethington 1991), and multiple interpretations of the phenomenon (e .g ., Ross 1989) . Another possibility is to combine longitudinal research with periodic observation of interactions (e .g., Repetti and Wood 1997) Methodological studies have used paired-informant designs as ways to estimate the reliability of life event reporting (e.g ., Kessler and Wethington 1991) . Lepore (1995) suggests that using an observational/informant design might yield better information about exposure to stress . A relationship based design may yield much more detailed findings about the processes of stress crossover (e .g ., Bolger et al . 1989a) . The major advance in paired-informant designs is that it allows the study of crossover from two points of view . For example, Bolger and colleagues (1989a) observed that there was a dynamic process of adjustment between husbands and wives, with spouses taking on extra work to compensate for spouses who were fatigued from work . In addition, they observed that other household members may have borne the brunt of the other's anger . A challenge, however, is that paired individuals do not always report the same event (Kessler and Wethington 1991), even on a daily basis (Bolger et al . 1989b) . This may come about because one forgets it happens (more likely if it is a minor event that occurred some time ago), but it may also be due to deliberate concealment (Kessler and Wethington 1991) . Spouses may also have different, and self-serving memories of their exchanges (Ross and Newby-Clark 1998) . Resolving these discrepancies may be difficult, especially considering that there are multiple, and sometimes conflicting explanations for why the discrepancy exists . Paired-informant designs are probably more useful when utilized in a daily diary study, when recall bias may be less critical, although not absent (see Stone, Kessler, and Haythornthwaite 1991) . They are also probably more useful in a research design that includes experimental observation, such as periodic observa-
Stress Contagion
245
tion of parents and children combined with questionnaire data (e .g ., Repetti and Wood 1997) and experience sampling . Daily Diary Designs
Daily diary designs allow investigators to collect data on naturally occurring interactions in the environment, across time for the same individuals . Daily event measures are self-report instruments . In the typical study, participants are asked to fill out a mood and health assessment, followed by a checklist measure of small life events and hassles . Because the recall period for daily stressors is only about 24 hours (since the last collection of data), promoters suggest that daily measurement reduces the recall biases that plague self-report in studies that rely on event recall (e .g., Eckenrode and Bolger 1995) . This technique is particularly useful for the study of chronic stressors, where it is well known that recency of relevant incidents or severity of recent incidents affects recall of how severe persistent stressors are (e .g ., Herbert and Cohen 1996) . Thus, the use of daily diaries has the potential to improve studies of stress contagion . As mentioned above, many processes of contagion involve studying chronic stress processes . In fact, Eckenrode (1984) found that chronic stress predicts the report of subsequent daily events . For example, a simple hypothesis seen often in the stress contagion literature is that stress carries over from one area of life to another, because a bad event in one area of life increases the probability of having a bad event in another ("they always come in threes") . Bolger, DeLongis, Kessler, and Wethington (1989) did a simple test of this hypothesis by examining the co-occurrence of daily events in work and family . They found that having any event increased the probability of having a second event by 50 percent on a given day . The study was limited, though, because all data were derived from self-report questionnaires . For example, it was not clear whether the same events were double-counted (e .g ., both a "lot of stress at work" and also as "work-family conflict") (Bolger et al . 1989b) . Double-counting could lead to overestimates of spillover . A new method for studying daily events attempts to address threats to the validity of studying spillover via self-report . The new method is the Daily Inventory of Stressful Experiences (DISE : Almeida 1998), a semi-structured telephone survey instrument that assesses a wide variety of types and dimensions of daily stressors . The DISE applies investigator-based methods to rate daily events and hassles, modeled on Life Events and Difficulties Schedule techniques (Brown and Harris 1978) . The interview consists of a series of questions asking whether certain types of events have occurred over the past 24 hours, along with a set of guidelines for probing responses to the questions . The interview method obtains a short narrative description of each event, evoked by probes that ask about specific objective circumstances surrounding the event . Coders then rate the narratives for several dimensions of event content and threat . Coders can also determine whether event
2 46
ELAINE WETHINGTON
reports from respondents refer to the same, or related events . These features can improve the assessment of stress spillover . The DISE may also improve measurement of stress crossover . One of the innovations of the DISE is the rating of focus of the event . Daily events are rated as either respondent-focused, other-focused (occurred solely to someone else), or "joint-focused" (involving both respondent and another person ) . This feature makes it possible to test whether certain types of contagion (active versus passive) are more related to mental mood or physical symptoms (cf . Larson and Almeida 1999) . Daily diaries promise great advances, but they are used less frequently than they could be . These methods are expensive, time-intensive for both respondents and investigators, and relatively difficult to analyze (see Stone et al . 1991) . Expense and time are real deterrents for investigators, particularly when research questions are still exploratory . For example, a multi-year, longitudinal, daily diary study, modeled on longitudinal studies of time use, might provide useful insight into the chronic stress processes involved in stress trajectories . But it is very expensive and time-consuming to collect data from the same individuals over a long enough period of time to observe very long-term chronic stress processes . Sustained, persistent chronic work stress most likely has deleterious effects on cardiovascular health, but these effects unfold over the process of years, rather than days or months (e .g ., Karasek and Theorell 1990) . Despite their limitations, daily diary measures have great potential . They can get to the heart of important theoretical issues related to spillover and crossover that are less-effectively addressed by traditional cross-sectional survey design (e .g ., Larson and Gillman 1999) . Experience Sampling
Although the use of the life history or daily diary approaches is likely to result in gathering much useful qualitative and quantitative naturalistic data on stress contagion, these approaches are still inadequate in several important ways. The major problem is that, to make strong arguments that stress contagion is a significant source of stress in society, a researcher needs to be able to say that stress contagion is a "random" event . The trouble derives from the standard selection problem when comparing "adaptation" across individuals . Busier people are given more opportunities or have more skill to acquire productive and prestigious roles from which role theorists hypothesize the most benefits . These roles also expose them to stress contagion . An example of the difficulty relates to the interconnection of family roles and work roles across the life course . Women (and men) select the level of workfamily stress to which they expose themselves, to some degree (Wethington and Kessler 1993) . This selection operates at many levels . Selection into occupation is not a random event, and depends in part on the skills acquired through education
Stress Contagion
247
and family modeling . Nor is the selection of social relationships in adulthood random . For example, the acquisition of a demanding job may lead to foregoing parenthood altogether, and even marriage . Attitudes toward the relative importance of work versus family may have an impact on career or relationship trajectory (Gerson 1985) . Thus any given stress reaction, even the report of a "stressful" everyday event, may result from some unknown combination of person factors and exposure factors . Daily diary researchers respond to this challenge by analyzing adaptation within individuals across time, rather than focusing primarily on differences across individuals (see Larson and Almeida 1999) . When focusing on within-individual differences across time, "personality" factors can be held constant . Many researchers have used hierarchical modeling techniques to enable them to estimate between- and within-individual diffferences separately (Almeida and Kessler 1998) . Another response to interpretive difficulties has been to use quasi-experimental design for observing stress exposure . Some researchers (e .g ., Csikszentmihalyi and Larson 1987) recommend the use of experience-sampling methods . The technique involves beeping participants at random intervals, who at the beep record what they are doing and describe (or have measured) their emotional and physical states . The use of this technique, coupled with a beeping schedule designed to maximize encounters at work or at home, would allow for instantaneous measurement of stress crossover effects . For example, an investigator could ask participants to record who was with them at the time of the beep, along with a description of that interaction. Then, the investigator could compare reports of mood across different types of encounters (e .g ., an interruption, a request for work, or seeking help) or between times when the respondent was working alone, rather than in the presence of another . Experience sampling promises a way to avoid some of the recall bias involved in the recording of chronic stressors and contagion . For example, it is easy to imagine that people with chronic relationship stress are more likely to report crossover from another person . But experience sampling has important limitations . Because sampling is random, it is probably not an efficient way to study important instances of relatively rare instances of crossover, such as an argument with an overworked spouse (see Bolger et al . 1989b) . Participants can skip responding to beeps, and may be more likely to do so when they are in the presence of others . Thus, the daily diary design, or daily diary combined with periodic observation by investigators, may be a more practical way to study stress contagion . These "selection" issues may be critical for the population study of spillover and crossover, but they are not so critical for the study of stress trajectories . This is because the study of trajectories of events and behavior across the life course encompasses the study of "selection," and in fact may provide testable hypotheses regarding how selection operates in every day life .
248
ELAINE WETHINGTON
FUTURE THEORETICAL DEVELOPMENTS Going Beyond Work-Family Contagion Studies Most of the studies cited above have concentrated on work and family contagion, either within individuals, or across individuals paired in a family . This stems from useful theoretical work that posed family and work as conflicting institutions, with social norms in the United States placing the burden of resolution on the resources of individuals . But much work could be done extending these techniques to other areas of life that involve exposure to stressors and may address other big issues, such as the persistence of the social gradient in health . Careful studies of stress processes, undertaken with care to represent social hierarchy and other forces leading to stress exposure, could help make an important link between macro social processes and micro-level phenomena . Other settings where contagion is likely include occupations characterized by emotional labor (Hochshild 1983) . Most studies of emotional labor are based on qualitative, rather than systematic observation . It remains untested whether emotional labor occupations actually expose workers to more demanding conditions for concealing and controlling emotions, and whether such demands outweigh the resources of many to cope-or pose long-term health risks . Similarly, studies of contagion could target work settings and workers who must, by reason of their positions, meet multiple, sometimes conflicting demands . Contagion studies might also focus on contagion from the wider social network, rather than the close network, in groups where demands and obligations are more widely distributed . Examples of such groups are small, enclave immigrant groups whose members are economically dependent on one another, or people in neighborhoods where crime and poverty make everyday stress more dangerous and threatening to health . Studies of stress trajectories might be extended to include contagion across generations, rather than within persons . Finally, techniques developed in studies of stress contagion might provide some insight into the debate on how work hours may be affecting leisure hours . "Contextual izing" the Study of Stress Another potential contribution from studies of stress contagion is to "contextualize" the study of stress and stressors across the life course (Link and Phelan 1995) . Despite interest in the psychological impact of stress on individuals, very little research has been done that relates stress exposure to social origins and other life history factors (Thoits 1995) . Exposure to stressful life events, for example, has not always been found to link consistently with SES in the way a simple application of the SES gradient would predict (see Brown and Harris 1978 ; Turner et al . 1995) . One explanation for these findings is that the disadvantaged are more reactive or vulnerable to stress, once it occurs . But another explanation is that
249
Stress Contagion
measurement of stress exposure differs widely across studies, particularly in respect to stress contagion processes-between closely connected individuals, and across the same individuals over their course of life (see also Turner et al . 1995) . Better Measures of Stressor Exposure It is unfortunate that theoretical research emphasizing the importance of stressor exposure has not advanced to keep pace with biological advances in understanding stress processes (e .g ., McEwen 1999) . This mismatch of progress contributes to reductionism in the study of stress processes and even the social gradient in health . Studies of latent biological effects established early in childhood may soon predominate over the study of the social pathways that contribute to the manifestations of these latent effects in adulthood (cf . Power and Hertzman 1997) . Current studies of stress contagion, which wrestle with the interaction of the situation and the person, may provide a model for integrating the biological and the social . Sociologists could take advantage of more powerful designs and techniques for understanding contagion processes, even including biological measurement of stress reactions . Studies explicitly incorporating hypothesized biological pathways will enable sociologists to communicate more effectively with biomedical researchers (Fremont and Bird 1999) . The timing is right, because biomedical researchers share an interest in the sorts of chronic stress processes that now dominate the thinking of sociologists of stress (e .g ., McEwen and Stellar 1993) .
ACKNOWLEDGMENT The preparation of this paper was supported by NIA Program Project 2P50 AG1171106 (Project 3), the John D . and Catherine T . MacArthur Foundation Research Network on Successful Midlife Development, and the Alfred P . Sloan Foundation . The author is grateful to Allison Kavey for research assistance and to Phyllis Moen, Karl Pillemer, and David Almeida for their comments on this paper .
REFERENCES Adler, N., T. Boyce, M . A . Chesney, S . Cohen, S . Folkman, R . L. Kahn, and S . L . Syme . 1994 . "Socioeconomic Status and Health ." American Psychologist 49 : 15-24 . Almeida, D . M . 1998 . The Daily Interview for Stressful Experiences . Tucson, AZ: University of Arizona. Almeida, D . M., and R. C . Kessler . 1998 . "Everyday Stressors and Gender Differences in Psychological Distress." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 75 : 670-80. Almeida, D . M., E . Wethington, and A . Chandler . 1999 . "Daily Transmission of Tensions Between Marital Dyads and Parent-Child Dyads ." Journal of Marriage and the Family 61 : 49-61 .
250
ELAINE WETHINGTON
Almeida, D . M ., E. Wethington, and D. MacDonald . Forthcoming . "Daily Variation in Paternal Engagement and Negative Mood : Implications for Emotionally Supportive and Conflictual Interactions ." Journal of Marriage and Family. Aneshensel, C. S ., L . I . Pearlin, J . T . Mullan, S . H . Zarit, and C .1 J. Whitlatch . 1995 . Profiles in Caregiving: The Unexpected Career . New York: Academic . Aseltine, R., and R . C . Kessler. 1993 . "Marital Disruption and Depression in a Community Sample." Journal of Health and Social Behavior 34 : 237-51 . Belle, D . 1982. "The Stress of Caring : Women as Providers of Social Support ." In Handbook of Stress: Theoretical and Clinical Aspects, edited by L . Goldberger and S . Breznitz. New York : Free Press . Bernard, J. 1972 . The Future of Marriage . New York : World Publishing . Bolger, N ., A. DeLongis, R. C . Kessler, and E . Schilling . 1989b . "Effects of Daily Stress on Negative Mood." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 57 : 808-818 . Bolger, N ., A . DeLongis, R . C . Kessler, and E. Wethington . 1989a. "The Contagion of Stress Across Multiple Roles ." Journal of Marriage and the Family 51 : 175-183 . Bolger, N., A. DeLongis, R . C . Kessler, and E . Wethington . 1990. "The Microstructure of Daily Role-Related Stress in Married Couples ." Pp . 95-115 in Stress Between Work and Family, edited by J. Eckenrode and S . Gore . New York: Plenum . Bronfenbrenner, U . 1979 . The Ecology of Human Development . Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press . Bronfenbrenner, U . 1995 . "Ecological Systems Theory ." Annals of Child Development 6 : 187-249 . Brown, G . W., and T . 0. Harris. 1978. Social Origins of Depression: A Study ofPsychiatric Disorder in Women . New York: Free Press . Brown, G . W . and T . 0. Harris . 1982 . "Fall-off in the Reporting of Life Events ." Social Psychiatry 17 : 23-28 . Brown, G . W . 1989 . "Life Events and Measurement ." Pp . 3-45 in Life Events and Illness, edited by G . W. Brown and T . 0. Harris. New York : Guilford . Brown, G . W . 1992 . "Social Support : An Investigator-Based Approach ." Pp . 235-258 in The Meaning and Measurement of Social Support, edited by H. 0 . F . Veiel and U. Baumann . New York: Hemisphere . Brown, G . W ., A . Bifulco, and T. 0 . Harris. 1987 . "Life Events, Vulnerability, and the Onset of Depression : Some Refinements ." British Journal of Psychiatry 150 : 30-42 . Brown, G . W., T. 0 . Harris, and C . Hepworth . 1995 . "Loss, Humiliation, and Entrapment Among Women Developing Depression : A Patient and Non-Patient Comparison ." Psychological Medicine 25 : 7-21 . Chodorow, N . 1978 . The Reproduction of Mothering : Psychoanalysis and the Sociology of Gender. Berkeley, CA : University of California Press . Csikszentmihalyi, M ., and R . D . Larson . 1987 . "The Experience Sampling Method ." Journal ofNervous and Mental Disease 175 : 526-36 . Dohrenwend, B . S ., B . P. Dohrenwend, M . Dodson, and P . E . Shrout . 1984 . "Symptoms, Hassles, Social Supports, and Life Events : The Problem of Confounded Measures ." Journal of Abnormal Psychology 93 : 222-230 . Eckenrode, J. 1984. "The Impact of Chronic and Acute Stressors on Daily Reports of Mood ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 46 : 907-919 . Eckenrode, J., and N. Bolger . 1995. "Daily and Within-Day Event Measurement ." Pp . 80-101 in Measuring Stress: A Guide for Health and Social Sciences, edited by S. Cohen, R . C . Kessler, and L. U. Gordon . New York: Oxford University Press . --Eckenrode, J ., and S . Gore. 1990 . "Stress and Coping at the Boundary Between Work and Family ." Pp . 1-16 in Stress Between Work and Family, edited by J . Eckenrode and S . Gore . New York : Plenum .
Stress Contagion
251
Elder, G . H ., L . K . George, and M . J. Shanahan 1996 . "Psychosocial Stress over the Life Course ." Pp. 247-292 in Psychosocial Stress : Perspectives on Structure, Theory, Life Course, and Methods, edited by H . B . Kaplan. Orlando, FL: Academic Press . Elo, I . T., and S . H . Preston . 1996 . "Education Differentials in Mortality : United States, 1979-1985 ." Social Science and Medicine 42 : 47-57 . Folkman, S ., R. S . Lazarus, C . Dunkel-Schetter, A . DeLongis, and R . Gruen . 1986 . "Dynamics of a Stressful Encounter : Cognitive Appraisal, Coping, and Encounter Outcomes." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59 : 992-1003 . Fremont, A . M ., and C . E . Bird . 1999. "Integrating Sociological and Biological Models : An Editorial ." Journal of Health and Social Behavior 40 : 126-29 . Gerson, K . 1985 . Hard Choices. Berkeley : University of California Press . Gilligan, C . 1982 . In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development . Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press . Goode, W. 1960. "A Theory of Role Strain ." American Sociological Review 25 : 483-95 . Harris, T . 0, G . W . Brown, and A. T . Bifulco. 1990. "Loss of Parent in Childhood and Adult Psychiatric Disorder." Development and Psychopathology 2: 311-328 . Hammen, C . 1992 . "Life Events and Depression : The Plot Thickens ." American Journal of Community Psychology 20 : 179-193 . Herbert, T ., and S . Cohen. 1996 . "Measurement Issues in Research on Psychosocial Stress ." Pp. 295-332 in Psychosocial Stress: Perspectives on Structure, Theory, Life Course, and Methods, edited by H. B . Kaplan . New York : Academic . Hochschild, A . R . 1983 . The Managed Heart: Commercialization of Human Feeling . Berkeley, CA : University of California Press . Karasek, R ., and T . Theorell . 1990. Healthy Work : Stress, Productivity, and the Reconstruction of Working Life . New York : Basic . Keane, T . 1998 . "Psychological Effects of Military Combat ." Pp . 52-65 in Adversity, Stress, and Psychopathology, edited by B . P . Dohrenwend. New York : Oxford University Press . Kessler, R . C . 1997 . "The Effects of Stressful Life Events on Depression ." Annual Review of Psychology 48: 191-214 . Kessler, R . C . 1994 . "The National Comorbidity Survey of the United States ." International Review of Psychiatry 6 : 365-376 . Kessler, R . C ., J. Gillis-Light, W . J . Magee, K . S . Kendler, and L . J . Eaves . 1997 . "Childhood Adversity and Adult Psychopathology ." Pp. 29-49 in Stress and Adversity Across the Life Course : Trajectories and Turning Points, edited by I . H . Gotlib and B . Wheaton . New York : Cambridge University Press. Kessler, R. C ., and J . A. McRae . 1982 . "The Effects of Wives' Employment on the Mental Health of Married Men and Women." American Sociological Review 47 : 216-227 . Kessler, R. C., and J . D . McLeod . 1984 . "Sex Differences in Vulnerability to Undesirable Life Events." American Sociological Review 49 : 620-30 . Kessler, R. C ., J . D. McLeod, and E . Wethington . 1985 . "The Costs of Caring : A Perspective on the Relationship Between Sex and Psychological Distress ." Pp . 491-506 in Social Support : Theory, Research, and Applications, edited by I . Sarason and B . Sarason. Dordrecht, Netherlands : Martinus Nijhoff. Kessler, R . C ., and E. Wethington. 1991 . "The Reliability of Life Event Reports in a Community Survey ." Psychological Medicine 21 : 723-738 . Kuh, D ., C . Power, D . Blane, and M . Bartley . 1997 . "Social Pathways Between Childhood and Adult Health ." Pp . 169-198 in A Life Course Approach to Chronic Disease Epidemiology, edited by D . Kuh and Y . Ben-Shlomo. Oxford : Oxford University Press . Larson, R. D ., and D . M . Almeida . 1999 . "Emotional Transmission in the Daily Lives of Families : A New Paradigm for Studying Family Process." Journal of Marriage and the Family 61 : 5-20 .
252
ELAINE WETHINGTON
Larson, R . D., and S . Gilman . 1999 . "Transmission of Emotions in the Daily Interactions of Single-Mother Families ." Journal of Marriage and the Family 61 : 21-37 . Lazarus, R . S ., and S . M. Folkman . 1984 . Stress, Appraisal, and Coping . New York : Springer . Lepore, S . J . 1995 . "Measurement of Chronic Stressors ." Pp. 102-120 in Measuring Stress : A Guide for Health and Social Scientists, edited by S . Cohen, R . C . Kessler, and L. U . Underwood . New York: Oxford University Press . Link, B . G., and J . Phelan. 1995 . "Social Conditions As Fundamental Causes of Disease." Journal of Health and Social Behavior Extra Issue: 80-94 . Lynch, J. W ., G . A . Kaplan, and S . J . Shema . 1997. "Cumulative Impact of Sustained Economic Hardship on Physical, Cognitive, Psychological, and Social Functioning ." New England Journal of Medicine 337(26) : 1889-1895 . Marks, N . 1998 . "Does It Hurt to Care? Caregiving, Work-Family Conflict, and Midlife Well-Being ." Journal ofMarriage and the Family 60 : 951-966 . Marks, S . 1977 . "Multiple Roles and Role Strain : Some Notes on Human Energy, Time and Commitment." American Sociological Review 42 : 921-936 . Marmot, M . G., R . Fuhrer, S . L . Ettner, N . F. Marks, L. L . Bumpass, and C. D . Ryff. 1998. "Contribution of Psychosocial Factors to Socioeconomic Differences in Health ." Milbank Quarterly 76 : 403-448 . Mattlin, J ., E . Wethington, and R. C . Kessler. 1990. "Situational Determinants of Coping and Coping Effectiveness ." Journal of Health and Social Behavior 31 : 103-22 . McDonough, P ., G . Duncan, D . Williams, and J . S . House . 1997 . "Income Dynamics and Adult Mortality in the United States, 1972 through 1989 ." American Journal of Public Health 87 : 1476-1483 . McEwen, B . S . 1999. "Development of the Cerebral Cortex : XIII . Stress and Brain Development : II." Journal of the American Academy ofAdolescent Psychiatry 38 : 101-103 . McEwen, B . S ., and E . Stellar. 1993 . "Stress and the Individual ." Archives of Internal Medicine 153 : 2083-2101 . McLanahan, S . S ., and J. L . Glass . 1985 . "A Note on the Trend in Sex Differences in Psychological Distress." Journal of Health and Social Behavior 26 : 328-335 . Mickelson, K . D ., R. C . Kessler, and P . R . Shaver . 1997 . "Adult Attachment in a Nationally Representative Sample." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 73 : 1092-1106. Moen, P . E. 1992 . Women's Two Roles: A Contemporary Dilemma . New York : Auburn House . Peacock, E . H ., and P. T . P. Wong . 1990 . "The Stress Appraisal Measure (SAM) : A Multidimensional Approach to Cognitive Appraisal." Stress Medicine 6: 227-236 . Pearlin, L . I ., E . G . Menaghan, M . Lieberman, and J . T . Mullan . 1981 . "The Stress Process ." Journal ofHealth and Social Behavior 22 : 37-356 . Pearlin, L . I ., and C. Schooler . 1978 . "The Structure of Coping ." Journal of Health and Social Behavior 19: 2-21 . Power, C ., and C. Hertzman . 1997 . "Social and Biological Pathways Linking Early Life and Adult Disease ." British Medical Bulletin 53 : 210-221 . Repetti, R. L ., and J. Wood . 1997 . "Effects of Daily Stress at Work on Mothers' Interactions with Preschoolers." Journal of Family Psychology 11 : 90-108 . Ross, C ., J . Mirowsky, and J . Huber. 1983 . "Dividing Work, Sharing Work, and In-Between ." American Sociological Review 48 : 809-823. Ross, M . 1989 . "Relation of Implicit Theories to the Construction of Personal Histories ." Psychological Review 96: 341-357 . Ross, M ., and I. Newby-Clark. 1998 . "Construing the Past and the Future ." Social Cognition 16 : 133-150 . Rubin, D. C ., T. A. Rahal, and L . W. Poon . 1998 . "Things Remembered in Early Adulthood Are Remembered Best." Memory and Cognition 26 : 3-19 .
Stress Contagion
253
Siegrist, J . 1998 . "Adverse Health Effects of Effort-Reward Imbalance at Work ." Pp . 190-204 in Theories of Organizational Stress, edited by C . L. Cooper . New York: Oxford University Press . Simon, R . 1995 . "Gender, Multiple Roles, Role Meaning, and Mental Health ." Journal of Health and Social Behavior 36: 182-94 .
Staines, G . 1980 . "Spillover Versus Compensation : A Review of the Literature on the Relationship Between Work and Nonwork ." Human Relations 33 : 111-29. Stone, A . A ., R . C. Kessler, and J . A. Haythornthwaite. 1991 . "Measuring Daily Events and Experiences : Decisions for the Researcher ." Journal of Personality 59 : 575-607 . Thoits, P. 1995 . "Stress, Coping, and Social Support Processes : Where Are We? What Next?" Journal of Health and Social Behavior Extra Issue: 53-79 . Turner, R. J ., B . Wheaton, and D . A . Lloyd . 1995 . "The Epidemiology of Social Stress ." American Sociological Review'60: 104-24 .
Weiss, R . S . 1990 . Staying the Course : The Emotional and Social Lives of Men Who Do Well at Work. New York : Free Press . Wethington, E ., D . M. Almeida, G. W . Brown, E. Frank, and R . C. Kessler . Forthcoming. "The Assessment of Stressor Exposure ." In European Handbook of Mental Health Assessment, edited by A. Vingerhoets . Dordrecht, Netherlands : Martinus Nijhoff. Wethington, E ., G . W . Brown, and R. C. Kessler. 1995 . "Interview Measurement of Stressful Life Events ." Pp . 59-79 in Measuring Stress : A Guide for Health and Social Scientists, edited by S . Cohen, R. C . Kessler, and L. U . Gordon . New York: Oxford University Press . Wethington, E ., and R . C. Kessler . 1989 . "Employment, Parenting Responsibility, and Psychological Distress : A Longitudinal Study of Married Women ." Journal of Family Issues 10 : 527-546. Wethington, E ., and R. C . Kessler. 1993 . "Neglected Methodological Issues in Employment Stress ." Pp. 269-295 in Women, Work, and Coping : A Multidisciplinary Approach to Workplace Stress, edited by B . Long and S . Kahn. Montreal : McGill-Queens . Wethington, E., J. D . McLeod, and R . C . Kessler. 1987 . "The Importance of Life Events in Explaining the Gender Difference in Psychological Distress ." Pp . 144-56 in Gender and Stress, edited by G . Baruch and R . Barnett . New York: Free Press . Wheaton, B ., P. Rozell, and K. Hall. 1997 . "The Impact of Twenty Childhood and Adult Traumatic Stressors on the Risk of Psychiatric Disorder." Pp. 50-72 in Stress and Adversity Across the Life Course: Trajectories and Turning Points, edited by I . H . Gotlib and B . Wheaton . New York : Cambridge University Press. Williams, D . 1990 . "Socioeconomic Differentials in Health : A Review and Redirection ." Social Psychology Quarterly 53 : 81-99 .
INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE AND THE ENVIRONMENT DETERMINING THE FAIR USE OF MONO BASIN WATER
Karen A. Hegtvedt and Patrick J . Flinn
ABSTRACT Social policy often involves establishment of principles pertaining to the distribution of benefits and, as such, is certainly within the purview of distributive justice processes . The intent of this paper is to apply theoretical notions about the establishment of justice principles, the perception of injustice, and the means to resolve disputes over what constitutes a just distribution of environmental resources . Given the nature of these resources, the question of securing a just distribution across generations arises . To illustrate issues of justice and intergenerational justice, we present a case study of the water rights litigation between the City of Los Angeles and certain environmental interest groups over the city's diversion of water from the Mono Basin area of the Sierra Mountains in the state of California . Our analysis highlights a variety of group processes inherent in the environmental debate as well as stimulates future directions for both applied and basic research .
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 255-284 . Copyright © 2000 by JAI Press Inc . All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN: 0-7623-0651-3 255
2 56
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
INTRODUCTION Subtly or intensely, justice concerns may shape and color the tapestry of policy issues pertaining to the distribution of resources within society .' The policies themselves may reflect the visions of what their creators believe will ensure fair distributions and procedures . These visions of justice, however, stem not only from prescriptive ideals of what is just, but also from the values, goals, and interests of those weaving the policies . In fact, advocates of a particular policy may simply dye their interests in justice rhetoric . Moreover, to the extent that interests form threads of justice, and that interests vary by time and circumstance, the fairness of policy over generations may wear and fade, just like a tapestry . The general intent of this paper is to apply theoretical concerns about distributive justice to environmental policy . 2 The analysis presented here highlights theoretical questions regarding the establishment of a distribution policy as just, the emergence over time of the perception of injustice regarding the distribution resulting from the policy, and the resolution of competing justice claims in a manner that attempts to ensure justice at the time and for future generations . Our specific goals for the paper extend environmental justice analysis in new directions . First, in addressing the general theoretical questions, we summarize underlying group processes : the power dynamics of decision making, the legitimacy of the distributions resulting from the decisions, the perceptions of individuals affected by the decisions, the emergence of conflict between opposing parties, and ultimately, the negotiated (or litigated) resolution of that conflict . While it is beyond the scope of this paper to review each of these processes in detail, we abstract basic elements and cast them into a framework for analyzing the fairness of existing and emergent environmental policy . Our second goal involves explication of how these group processes affect not simply justice at one point in time but justice over time . Intergenerational justice refers to the fairness of procedures and resource distributions that affect two or more generations of people . The notion of "justice over time" is a matter of philosophical debate (Barry 1989 ; Laslett and Fishkin 1992) . That debate raises issues of practical significance in terms of the extent to which policy decisions of today embody justice with respect to future generations (or, retrospectively, how policy decisions of yesterday have affected justice for the current generation) . Although research on intergenerational justice has focused primarily on aging and elder care (Norris 1987), here we extend the analysis to issues of the environment . 3 The illustration of group processes and intergenerational justice issues with an extended environmental example is our third goal . The particular environmental case pertains to the diversion of water from the Mono Basin area of the Eastern Sierra Nevada of the state of California since the 1930s . This case involves water rights litigation between the City of Los Angeles and certain environmental interest groups regarding the city's rights to water in the Mono Basin . We conclude by suggesting avenues of both basic and applied research to enhance our understand-
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
257
ing of group processes and the fairness of environmental policy, especially over time .
JUST DISTRIBUTIONS AND PERCEIVED INJUSTICE Cohen and Greenberg (1982) define distributive justice as " . . .the application of a normative rule to the allocation of resources to recipients" (p . 1) . Justice exists when there is congruence between expectations for resources based on the normative rule and the actual distribution of resources . Generally a justice rule fosters effective social cooperation to promote individual well-being (Deutsch 1975), is consensually held to promote mutually agreeable exchanges or allocations (Reis 1986), and is impartial to the interests of the actors it serves (Barry 1989 ; Rawls 1971) . Thus, theoretically, a just distribution should ensure collective welfare . Despite this abstract ideal of justice, what people actually perceive to be fair often reflects their own material self-interest (Hegtvedt 1992b) . These empirical beliefs may undermine the key notions of impartiality, consensus, and collective welfare . Below we briefly examine three fundamental distributive justice issues . Our theoretical analysis of these issues provides the basic framework for understanding the distribution of environmental resources . First, we discuss how, in establishing justice, the rule that becomes normative depends upon the interests of those involved in the distribution, their interpersonal ties, and situational factors, including the legitimating beliefs of others . The second issue focuses on assessments of injustice resulting from the mismatch between an expected distribution and an actual one or from a questioning of the appropriateness or legitimacy of an existing distribution principle . Because of variation in the source of injustice as well as individual motivations, social comparisons, and other perceptions, differential evaluations of justice are likely to arise . Thus the third issue pertains to the means to resolve competing justice claims, which may be shaped by factors legitimating one claim over another. In our analysis we raise points relevant to assessing distributions over time . We conclude the section by applying these fundamental justice issues to the distribution of environmental resources .
Establishing Just Distributions Perspectives on the emergence of justice principles in general stem from sociological work on stratification and social psychological work on justice . The former (e .g ., Lenski 1966) typically suggests that power ultimately determines the distribution of rewards (resources) within a group or social system . Power-advantaged actors in society are more likely to accrue higher rewards and then justify resulting inequalities as fair . On the social psychological level, Emerson (1972) also draws attention to the importance of power position and network connections
258
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
in social exchange relationships . Such relationships are contexts in which justice norms emerge (Blau 1964 ; Homans 1974 ; Walster, Walster, and Berscheid 1978) . A major assumption of the exchange approach is that individuals attempt to maximize rewards from their relationships . In direct exchange relationships, negotiations over what actors give up and what they receive provides the basis for the development of proportionality as a justice rule . Proportionality indicates that outcomes are commensurate to contributions or statuses . Thus individuals who occupy power-advantaged positions are likely to expect greater rewards . Such expectations correspond with findings that people in impersonal relationships are likely to allocate abundant resources in a manner consistent with their self-interest (see Hegtvedt 1992b) . In contrast to justice rules emerging in direct exchanges or impersonal allocations, when exchange relations are "generalized," with no direct reciprocity between actors, proportionality may be de-emphasized. Generalized forms of exchange involve contributions of an actor to a group or to another actor without the expectation of immediate reciprocation from that particular partner but with the expectation of reciprocated resources from another actor or group when needed in the future (Ekeh 1974) . Such forms of exchange tend to enhance the level of trust and solidarity within the group, de-emphasizing individual differences as a basis for distribution . Thus, somewhat paradoxically, the stratification and social exchange literatures are consistent in their implication that justice principles emerge from self-interested behavior (Hegtvedt 1992b) . To the extent that "what is becomes what ought to be" (Homans 1974), originally self-interested rules become accepted as fair standards for resource distribution . Moreover, the aggregate distribution emerging from the repeated application of a distribution rule becomes "mutually entailed" and thus recognized as legitimate (Jasso 1983) . For example, to the extent that powerful actors develop distribution principles that benefit themselves, the inequality represented in the aggregate distribution of resources will also be seen as just . Unequal distributions may be seen as just by both power-advantaged and power-disadvantaged individuals for a number of reasons . First, the power-advantaged may simply justify as fair their proportions owing to their status and greater potential contributions . Second, as Della Fave (1980) argues, power disadvantaged actors may reevaluate themselves to come to believe that they are less deserving of greater outcomes and thus assess the inequality as fair . And third, as described in the legitimacy literature (Walker and Zelditch 1993 ; Zelditch and Walker 1984), insofar as individuals believe that others in authority (authorization) or their peers (endorsement) support the distribution, they are less likely to challenge the inequality . Thus by taking cues from others, individuals come to see a distribution as legitimate, and by implication, the rule that produced it as fair . 4 Changes over time, however, may erode the legitimacy of a distribution and increase perceptions of unfairness .
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
2 59
Assessments of Injustice
Discussions of perceived injustice typically pertain to the evaluation of onetime distributions . The most common type of injustice arises when individuals find that an actual distribution fails to meet their reward or resource expectations based on the application of the normative rule . This failure may be due to actual shortfalls or to how individuals perceive what they and others have contributed to and received from the allocation or exchange and the comparison that they invoke to test the rule (see Hegtvedt and Markovsky 1995) . Differences in the availability of information about resources and in interests may activate cognitive or motivational biases (see Fiske and Taylor 1991) that color fairness perceptions . Likewise, whether actors compare their shares of the distribution to what they have received in the past, to what others like themselves receive, or to what dissimilar others obtain may affect evaluations of justice . Thus even when a normative justice principle guides evaluations, people may differ in the conclusions they draw about the fairness of an actual distribution at one point in time . With the passage of time and concomitant changes in circumstances, the possibility arises that the existing justice principle is no longer appropriate or legitimate . Jasso (1983) suggests that people grow to view an existing distribution rule as inappropriate when there are : (1) changes in the availability of resources ; (2) alterations in the goals pursued ; (3) questions about the relevance of certain contributions as a basis for resources ; and (4) changes in the valuation of resources at issue . Although individuals may disagree on whether or not such conditions obtain and thus differ in their fairness evaluations of a given distribution, recognition of the implications of changing circumstances for populations is necessary to establish justice over time . Resolving Competing Justice Claims
A great deal of social psychological theory and research examines individual and, to some extent, collective reactions to injustice (see Hegtvedt and Markovsky 1995 ; Hegtvedt and Cook forthcoming) . Such research typically involves the mismatch between actual outcomes and those expected based on an accepted justice rule . The party or parties who feel unjustly treated attempt to redress the injustice in various ways (Adams 1965), none of which explicitly challenges existing ideas of fairness . In contrast, little work addresses situations in which an inappropriate distribution rule has been applied or in which, despite agreement on the justice principle, individuals come to different conclusions about whether justice exists . In such cases, actors hold competing justice claims . A direct means to resolve competing claims and to develop new, consensual notions of justice is negotiation between actors (Hegtvedt 1992a ; Hegtvedt and Cook 1987 ; Lamm 1986) . Alternatively, actors may involve a third party to hear their positions and settle their dispute (Thibaut and Walker 1975 ; Walster, Walster, and Berschied 1978) .
260
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK] . FLINN
Regardless of the means used to resolve competing justice claims, it is likely that involved parties are acting rationally, arguing for a distribution rule that represents the most efficient means to their goal . The goals that actors pursue may include self-interest, fairness, expedience, and so on (see Leventhal, Karuza, and Frye 1980) . To the extent that individuals are primarily interested in furthering their own (material) interests, cries of fairness may be only a means to legitimate those ends . In contrast, for actors pursuing a fairness goal, their cries may be an attempt to promote impartiality and collective welfare . It may be difficult, however, to discern the underlying motives of rational actors . Even the pursuit of fairness may be a means to enhance one's own welfare . If self-interested actors are concerned more about social rewards and costs than material ones, however, they may be more likely to advocate distributions beneficial to others (see Hegtvedt 1992a) . Research in small groups suggests a number of conditions that seem to increase an individual allocator's concern with social aspects of the distribution, leading to distributions beneficial to others : familiarity among group members (Austin 1980), attention to the distress of some group members (O'Malley and Becker 1984), individual's self-awareness in the allocator role (Kernis and Ries 1984), the open discussion of distribution rules within the group (Kahn, Nelson, Gaeddert, and Heam 1982), and the relative scarcity of rewards to be distributed (Hegtvedt 1987) . Similarly, in situations of generalized exchange, individuals cannot benefit directly and thus may favor allocations beneficial to others in the hope of establishing a norm that will benefit them in the future . Hegtvedt (1992a) argues that to the extent that disputing parties share a common goal of promoting collective welfare and agree upon the nature of that welfare, disagreements are likely to be resolved readily . In contrast, if one or both parties pursue materially self-interested goals, the dispute may be more difficult to resolve and involve more aggressive negotiation tactics . With concern over outcomes, arguments to third parties are likely to be presented in a manner favorable to the presenter (see Thibaut and Walker 1975) . And, appeals to justice may merely represent justifications for a particular preference and definition of collective welfare. These arguments regarding the resolution of competing justice claims focus primarily on disputing individuals, without reference to whether other people agree or disagree with one party or another . Indeed, the justice literature rarely examines the effects of what other people think on an individual's assessment of a distribution as just or unjust (see Hegtvedt and Johnson unpublished) . What others think, however, may legitimate particular claims (Walker and Zelditch 1993 ; Zelditch and Walker 1984) . And, notions of legitimacy-especially authorization-underlie rules codified in law . Thus when parties dispute the fairness of a distribution, the viability of their arguments depends not only on their internal logic but also on the extent to which the claims are supported by others-peers as well as authorities . Ultimately, the interests of disputing parties and the context of
lntergenerational Justice and the Environment
261
the dispute (i .e., beliefs of others, existing laws) complicate the resolution of competing claims in the distribution of resources, including environmental ones . justice Issues and the Distribution of Environmental Resources
The streamlined analysis of the fairness of a distribution of environmental resources below parallels the discussion of theoretical justice issues . We examine the establishment of a particular way of distributing environmental resources, the emergence of beliefs that the current policies are unfair, and the dynamics of disputes between advocates claiming the fairness of the status quo and proponents arguing for changes to ensure fairness . In doing so, it is necessary to recognize the historical specificity of meanings attached to the motives and perceptions underlying competing evaluations . The analysis demonstrates that the justness of any distribution of environmental resources is subject to change over time, and, as a consequence the need for developing a sense of intergenerational environmental justice . Throughout much of U .S . history, the dominant approach to the establishment of a particular way to distribute environmental resources focused on economic development . Individuals put to use environmental resources (e .g ., water, lumber, oil, land, minerals) to enhance their own and others' standards of living . Our country flourished with westward expansion and industrialization . In effect, marketplace concerns dominated decision making with regard to the use of natural resources . From the point of view of developers-wealthy and/or powerfully placed actors-the "community" thus benefitted from their endeavors (e .g ., in terms of job opportunities, availability of products and services) . Despite their own personal gains, they could justify as fair what they were doing, especially in comparison to other worse-off communities . The pattern that emerged for the use of environmental resources became the standard . Thus, as noted above, self-interested motivations may evolve into justice principles, which are mutually entailed in aggregate distribution standards . The high rate of use of environmental resources, however, has at least two negative consequences, which have resulted in assessments of injustice . First and most obviously, is the depletion of the resources themselves at a rate exceeding the rate of replacement . And, second, the cumulation of hazardous by-products and the displacement of disadvantaged groups in the name of progress . The latter consequence in particular captures what has become the typical interpretation of environmental justice (Perrolle 1993 ; Wenz 1988) . Insofar as environmental issues are treated as problems of justice in a stratified society, environmental injustice exists when problems of workplace risks, air pollution, hazardous wastes, global warming, and so on more adversely affect women, minorities, and the poor (e .g ., Bullard and Wright 1992 ; Hartley 1995 ; Stretskey and Hogan 1998 ; but see Petrikin 1995 for articles debating this viewpoint) . Heinegg (1979) argues that both the devastation of nature and the oppression of people stem from
262
KAREN A. HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
the denial of "otherness"-that is, the lack of concern for collective welfare . The rise in concerns for environmental justice corresponds with an enduring and successful environmental movement (Dunlap and Mertig 1992) . 5 This movement highlights three conditions that disrupt the mutual entailment represented in individual practices and overall distributions (Jasso 1983) : resource scarcity, alterations in the goals pursued, and changes in the valuation of resources . As noted, resource scarcity is inevitable, especially in the case of nonrenewable resources such as oil, natural gas, and minerals . Increased awareness of resource scarcity (Olsen, Lodwick, and Dunlap 1992) stimulates changes in worldviews, which in turn, affect goals and re-valuation of resources . Moreover, evidence suggests that environmentalism correlates with a concern for the justice of the larger community, responsibility, and equal sacrifice (see Clayton 1996) . In the last 30 years the shift from a technocratic worldview to an ecological one (Olsen, Lodwick, and Dunlap 1992) captures alterations in potential goals for the use of environmental resources and the re-valuation of those resources . The technocratic social paradigm emphasizes how humans are able to control natural resources to suit their own purposes and is consistent with the goal of economic development. In contrast, the ecological worldview stresses the balance between human societies and ecosystems despite the limits it puts on economic growth . This view corresponds to the goals of environmental justice . Implicit in these goal shifts, moreover, are new assessments of the value of certain resources . 6 The technocratic view suggests high valuation of technological advance and lower valuation of natural surroundings. The reverse characterizes the ecological worldview . Resource scarcity, coupled with goal changes, the re-valuation of resources, and support by others, have stimulated perceptions of injustice . Proponents of environmental conservation are likely to value continued biological diversity and the welfare of the larger community more than increased living standards (especially where standards are already high compared to those of other populations) . They may view as unjust attempts to develop land that threatens natural habitats, requires the restructuring of nature (e .g ., the diversion of water by various manmade means, the filling marsh lands), or affects various human populations unequally . The ecological worldview, moreover, alerts individuals to the impact of resource depletion on the survival of one's own group as well as future generations . Concern with the well-being of group members living and yet unborn may represent a form of generalized exchange, which decreases emphasis on an actor's own benefits at a particular point in time . Due to changing circumstances, two conflicting conceptions of justice with regard to the distribution of environmental resources exist . Although each is legitimated by peer endorsement, legitimation of the different perspectives by authorities is variable . At issue between advocates of resource distributions to promote economic development and proponents of changing patterns to conserve resources and protect the environment are the establishment of new just rules and institutions ensuring them . New rules may emerge from negotiations and compro-
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
263
mise between parties themselves or involving third parties (e .g ., government, courts), which lends greater legitimacy to a particular viewpoint . Given that resources are not limitless and that technology has not found substitutes for basic resources, the consequences of resolving current competing claims will impact future generations . Although what future generations may deem as just may be different from that promoted by any group now, failure to consider future generations when making decisions about scarce environmental resources may spell doom for those future populations . In the next section we review developments in the conceptualization of intergenerational justice, especially as it regards the distribution of environmental resources .
INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE AND ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES Although social scientists have typically constrained their analyses to individuals' beliefs about the fairness of a distribution at only one point in time, recent work in philosophy (Barry 1989 ; Laslett and Fishkin 1992) and the social sciences (Norris 1987 ; Cook and Donnelly 1996) has begun to examine the concept of justice over time . Insofar as distribution decisions-such as those regarding environmental resources-affect people across time, it seems appropriate intuitively to speak of intergenerational justice . The intuitive approach, however, belies a number of complexities in determining intergenerational justice . Below we review some of these complexities and examine strategies to circumvent them . We conclude with an analysis of how considerations of intergenerational justice inform an approach to environmental policy . Several factors complicate determining what constitutes intergenerational justice . First, historical time period may directly as well as indirectly, through the interests, perceptions, and the interpersonal relations of involved parties, affect conceptions of justice . Insofar as meanings of justice are historically mutable, an earlier generation cannot aspire to act justly toward a later distant generation whose members' understanding of justice may differ radically (Ball 1985) . Second, individual identities (especially over time) shape conceptions of benefits and harms that underlie the development of a justice principle (Fishkin 1992) . As a consequence, what is just for people at a certain time may not hold for future generations . Third, changes in population or birth cohort size may wreak havoc on the reasonable conclusions produced from the application of a justice principle for a fixed population over a short period of time (Laslett and Fishkin 1992) . The temporal asymmetry of population sizes prohibits calculation of future beneficiaries or per person sacrifices . And finally, if justice is defined as mutual advantage, a logical problem arises because future generations cannot help or harm the current generation (Barry 1989) .
2 64
KAREN A. HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
Intergenerational justice may be possible if " . . .[we] think not of a choice made by a particular generation at a single point in time but of a pattern of collaboration across many generations in a common scheme of justice," (Barry 1989, p . 201) . To the extent that individuals fulfill obligations to sustain just institutions, which benefit future people, intergenerational justice may emerge in the absence of direct mutual benefit . Similarly, as Laslett and Fishkin (1992) suggest, justice over time may exist in an obligation on all present people to conduct themselves in recognition of the rights of all future persons, regardless of geographical location and temporal position . In effect, these obligations represent what Laslett (1992) has called an "intergenerational contract," which specifies that the rights of the present generation, derived from previous generations, should be matched by the duties it performs toward future generations . These attempts at establishing intergenerational justice are mostly forward looking . By focusing on the maintenance of just institutions and general obligations to ensure the welfare of future people, complications in determining intergenerational justice dissipate . Presumably, just institutions will rise above individual identity-based definitions in looking out for the welfare of the larger community and have the necessary means to recognize the implications of predicted demographic changes . And, by being responsible to the larger community, such institutions are likely to involve more participants in the decision-making process, thereby enhancing legitimacy (see Tyler and Lind 1992) and increasing their capacity to take into account alterations in the meaning and value of resources depending upon socio-historical conditions . Philosophers who conceptualize justice over time raise questions about the environment. For example, Luper-Foy (1992) links the environment to intergenerational justice by specifying that justice entitles everyone in the world, including future generations, to an equitable share of benefits of the world's natural resources . Likewise, Laslett and Fishkin (1992) propose a hypothetical justice principle that every member of every generation must have equal access to the resources of the world, irrespective of birth generation . These prescriptions, however, imply that resources are infinite . Recognizing that resources are finite, Laslett and Fishkin emphasize the intergenerational contract to ensure that no generation is at liberty to ransack the environment . Daly (Daly and Cobb 1989) concretizes these philosophical prescriptions . To avoid the negative environmental consequences of optimizing in a free market economy, he proposes a model that emphasizes concern with collective welfare in the real world . The model requires the development of social institutions to regulate the use of the environment (e .g ., depletion of renewable resources, emissions levels) and to ensure a sustainable future for generations to come . The success of such social institutions is likely to depend on their legitimacy . The Daly and Cobb (1989) model for intergenerational environmental justice raises issues similar to the ones described for justice at a single point in time . The need for social institutions suggests that the model implicitly recognizes that peo-
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
2 65
pie may vary in their perceptions of justice . Questions underlying assessments of intergenerational justice correspond to those relevant to a one-time distribution . First, how does the distribution compare to that expected based on rules (laws) deemed just by relevant institutions? Second, regardless of such rules, to what extent does the distribution enhance collective welfare as represented currently and in the future? The first question involves a comparison between the actual distribution and a normative principle of justice, if one exists, and is consistent with Greenberg and Cohen's definition of distributive justice . The second question implies recognition of how codified rules, although legitimated, often reflect the interests of the powerful and thus do not necessarily epitomize the notion of collective welfare that is the essence of justice . Moreover, the second question raises concern with variation in what constitutes justice over time . With such variation competing claims regarding what ensures justice for future generations are likely to arise . How can social institutions, whose goals are long term, resolve such disputes? To examine how these justice questions play out in current environmental debates, we focus on a particular case : the export of water from the Mono Basin area of the state of California to local areas . In that case, the environmental values of the lake in its natural condition conflict with the water needs of the City of Los Angeles . Of both theoretical and practical interest are issues of : the motives and positions of parties involved in the establishment of the initial policy governing the water distribution ; factors leading to challenges to the initial policy, including the motives and positions of those voicing cries of injustice; and the role of the courts-as a social institution charged with determining just distributions-in resolving the dispute between parties arguing for what they believe is a fair distribution of water now and in the future .
THE DISTRIBUTION OF WATER FROM THE MONO BASIN : A CASE STUDY The case of Mono Lake involves the allocation of a finite resource-water . Legal doctrines applied 60 years ago established an allocation policy that allowed the City of Los Angeles, hundreds of miles south of the lake, to divert water from the streams feeding the lake . 8 Although then existing laws largely legitimated the policy, the fairness of its implementation has been challenged for as many years . Recently, the responsible institutions have set about reallocating the resource to address the unfairness . The reallocation resulted from efforts of grass-roots environmental organizations supporting lawsuits that used the institution of the courts to effect the desired change . Interestingly, the courts based their water reallocation decision on rules in existence at the time of the original allocation . They applied existing laws and principles and purported to harmonize them with poten-
2 66
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK) . FLINN
tially conflicting doctrines to bring about the reallocation. In effect, the courts rectified the earlier inappropriate application of distribution rules . In this section we first provide an overview of the Mono Lake ecosystem which is threatened by the half century of water diversions . We then trace the development of the Mono Lake case . The analysis begins with the original resource allocation and the definition of fairness offered by representatives of the City of Los Angeles based on their interpretation of water laws . The second part of our analysis examines the development of perceptions of injustice regarding the original allocation, which ultimately resulted in challenges in the courts . The institutional approach to resolving competing justice claims constitutes the third portion of our analysis . The discussion highlights the positions of actors to the conflict, the diverse evaluations of what various parties consider to be fair despite or in view of existing laws, and the role of the courts as a just institution bridging generations . The Mono Lake Ecosystem
Mono Lake sits 6,400 feet (approximately 1,950 meters) above sea level in the Sierra Nevada mountain range in California, about 200 miles (320 km) west of San Francisco. The historic lake level was approximately 6,420 feet above sea level . Mono Lake has no outlet ; it is fed by tributaries that drain the mountains which comprise the Mono Basin . As a consequence, the mineral salts eroded by the streams that feed Mono Lake have been deposited over thousands of years and, with evaporation, have made the lake saline (National Academy of Sciences 1987) . The natural salinity of the lake prevents fish from living in the lake but allows for a super-abundant growth of brine shrimp and alkali flies . These, in turn, create a unique and important source of food for migrating and nesting birds . Ninety-five percent of California's sea gull population (25% of the total species population) nests on islands in the lake . In addition, the chemical reaction caused by freshwater springs in the lake bed produce unusual, tower-shaped mineral pillars called tufa. Prior to the arrival of European settlers in the nineteenth century, Mono Lake was the home to indigenous people (Farquhar 1949) . These people relied on the brine shrimp and other local food sources for survival . One of the earliest European explorers, John Muir, wrote poignantly in 1875 about the rare beauty and grandeur of the lake framed by the mighty Sierra Mountains (see Wolfe 1979) . Capitalizing on that beauty, in the 1920s and 1930s a substantial resort community developed by Mono Lake and was a vacation destination from the growing cities of San Francisco and Los Angeles . Sources feeding the lake (Lee Vining Creek, Walker Creek, Parker Creek, and Rush Creek) supported large trout populations and were extensively fished by the public . The diversion of water from Mono Lake threatened its status as a scenic and unique ecological system . In 1993 the lake level was at 6,375 feet, significantly
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
267
below its historic level . The lack of fresh water from the tributaries increases the salinity of the lake, which, if unchecked, disrupts the local food chain beginning at its base of plankton, brine shrimp, and alkali flies (National Academy of Sciences 1987) . Diminishment of brine shrimp and alkali fly populations threatens the many species of birds that feed on them . In addition, lower lake levels create land bridges from the shore to the islands on which the birds nest, allowing predators access to the nesting sanctuaries . The lower lake level also adversely affects human populations and activities in several ways . First, the lake's recession diminishes its value as an economic resource, especially in terms of the local tourism industry . Second, the dry lake bed is difficult to traverse, thus decreasing human access to the lake . Third, exposure of greater portions of the lake bed increases the possibility that dried silt, containing high concentrations of alkali and other minerals that irritate mucous membranes and respiratory systems, will be airborne in winds . Dust particles blown by the wind across the saline crust of the lake bed generate immense dust storms that violate federal and state air pollution laws in a region with otherwise remarkably pure air (TRC Environmental 1993) . Finally, the lowering of the lake level has incised the channels of the streams feeding the lake, resulting in the draining of surrounding wet lands (Stine 1987) . As a consequence, continued water diversions caused a variety of environmental injuries and threatened even more . Thus Mono Lake represents a unique natural resource that has endured use by many generations . Unrestricted diversions of water, however, would ultimately destroy the Mono Lake ecosystem . Whether future generations will have the opportunity to enjoy the resource is a matter of legal debate resting upon the existence and interpretation of various principles governing water use and the protection of public resources in the past and in the present (for the future) . The Original Allocation of Water Rights : Diversion of Mono Basin Water as Fair The history of the distribution of water from the Mono Basin provides a basis for understanding how the diversion of water came to be considered fair . The emergence of the standard stems from actions based on goals of economic development, enacted by power-advantaged individuals . Moreover, to the extent that the standard corresponded to existing laws, it appears legitimate (i .e ., authorized) . Below we outline the emphasis on development, the steps necessary to provide water to facilitate development, and the implication of these guidelines for the actions of individuals in pursuit of their own interests . The creation of laws governing the allocation of water in the state of California corresponded to deliberate federal and state government policies with the explicit goal of encouraging the development of the West in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries . The U .S . government gave away public land to settlers who
268
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
were willing to develop it and exploit its resources . Likewise, the federal government granted mineral rights for little or no fee to those who would invest in the development of mineral resources . With regard to providing water to facilitate development, the state government in California granted free of charge exclusive rights to use water in the rivers and streams it owned, as long as the user was prepared to build the facilities necessary to put the water to "beneficial use ." Most consumptive uses for human activity fell within this broad definition . Once actors (individuals or groups) put the water to "beneficial use," rights to that water were "vested" and could not be taken by others . Moreover, the law allowed an appropriator to take water any distance from its source, provided that the facilities were constructed to do so. There was no absolute limit on the quantity of water the user could claim, even to the point of de-watering the stream or river entirely .9 Obtaining a water right in California is a straightforward, three-step process (Hutchins 1956) . First, one files an application, detailing the proposed project and specifying the amount of water to be used . The time of filing determines priority of applicants . The responsible state agency (currently the State Water Resources Control Board or the Water Board) reviews the application to assess whether the proposed use constitutes a "beneficial use," and whether there is any water in the stream not appropriated to prior claimants . The Water Board grants a permit to applicants meeting these requirements . The second step involves the construction of the diversion facilities detailed in the permit, as well as the actual diversion and use of the water . The completion of construction and the diversion of all possible water (up to the limit specified in the permit) allows the appropriator to take the third step, obtaining a license from the Water Board . The Water Board determines whether, in fact, the permittee has been able to put to beneficial use all of the water claimed in the permit . If so, the agency grants the license and the right to use the specified quantity is vested . If the permittee has not been able to use all of the water claimed in the permit, the license will reduce the amount granted to that actually put to use . This distribution policy and process provided an enormous incentive in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries to build irrigation facilities, dams, and aqueducts to put unappropriated water to use as soon as possible . Individual farmers pooled resources to form collective bodies to develop irrigation facilities . Towns and cities created municipal water agencies, with access to substantial amounts of capital to fund ambitious water development projects . The municipal water agency for the City of Los Angeles, the Department of Water and Power (DWP), undertook one of the most ambitious plans for the diversion of water in the state . In the early 1900s this small town in the southern California desert developed a plan to build a 300-mile aqueduct over the Tehachape Mountains, across the Mohave Desert, and north into the Sierra Nevada to export the snow melt from those mountains . Its first target was the Owens River, which it de-watered in the 1920s .
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
2 69
In the 1930s DWP filed an application to divert and export all of the water (potentially 100,000 acre-feet of water a year) flowing in the four principal streams feeding Mono Lake, to the north of the Owens River valley . The Water Board promptly granted a permit and DWP began construction of diversion dams and a tunnel through the volcanic mountain range which separated the Mono Basin from the Owens Valley . By 1940 construction of one barrel of the aqueduct was complete, and water left the Mono Basin destined for Los Angeles . The appropriation of water from the Mono Basin area conformed to existing laws-appropriate distribution principles for the time and place . In addition, the goal of the development of a city, with concomitant economic opportunities, appeared to serve collective interests, as well as the individual interests of the municipal power-holders . Thus it would not be unreasonable to conclude that the diversion of water was legitimated and perceived to be fair by those who would benefit from the economic development at that point in time . Emergence of Perceptions of Injustice Regarding Water Allocation
Despite the apparent legitimacy and, for some, fairness of the diversion of water from the Mono Basin to Los Angeles, other California citizens began to challenge the fairness of the water policies as early as 1928 . Challenges at that point in time stemmed from variation in information about resources and evaluation of those resources, which are colored by the individuals' own interests and motivations . Later challenges, as discussed more fully in the next section, also question the legitimacy of the allocation . Regardless of the source of challenge, DWP and its constituency in LA who benefit from the water diversion defended their position in the face of the concerns raised by parties who have interests in maintaining the natural environment surrounding the lake and its tributaries . In effect, each side invoked justice rhetoric that serves their own interest .' 0 Whether their justified self-interest constitutes justice per se depends on the definition of collective welfare . Initially, LA representatives emphasized the immense benefits to people in that area whereas Mono Lake advocates represent a narrower regional collective . With the shift toward an ecological worldview, the collective of concern to lake proponents includes the whole of the natural environment, which may also benefit people beyond region . Below we illustrate these points in our description of the events from the 1930s through 1970s . Starting in the nineteenth century, miners used hydraulic hoses to erode entire hillsides in the search for gold . Voters, largely in response to this wasteful practice, amended the state's constitution in 1928 to require that all water uses be "reasonable ." In 1933, in response to the destruction of fisheries by miners and others, legislators representing the mountain counties succeeded in enacting a law to require dam owners to allow sufficient water to pass through or over them "to keep in good condition any fish that may be planted or exist below the dam" (Cal . Fish & Game Code § 5937) . When DWP began its diversions in 1940, local resi-
270
KAREN A. HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
dents foresaw the effects of the project on the Mono Basin . The protests of these relatively powerless actors to the Water Board went unheeded . The Water Board claimed, "[it] is indeed unfortunate that the City's proposed development will result in decreasing the aesthetic advantages of Mono Basin but there is apparently nothing that this office can do to prevent it" (Water Board 1940) . Then in 1953, largely in response to DWP's activities in the Sierra Nevada, the state legislature enacted another statue that required all permits or licenses issued for water in the Mono or Owens area to contain a condition requiring compliance with section 5937 (Cal . Fish & Game Code § 5946) . These actions reflect emphasis on the value of different resources (e .g., fish, the natural environment) by local residents and means that those opposed to the water diversion employed to address what they perceived to be unjust . DWP, however, effectively thwarted these challenges to the fairness of the diversion and continued to de-water the Mono Basin tributaries . First, prior to the 1940 diversions, DWP offered to build a fish hatchery on the Owens River if the Department of Fish & Game would agree not to enforce section 5937 against DWP . The head of the department signed such an agreement despite the department's lack of legal authority to exempt anyone from the statute's requirements . Then in 1953 DWP argued that the newly enacted 5946 statue did not apply to its permits because they were issued prior to the effective date of the statue . An attorney for the Water Board documented agreement with DWP's claim for exemption . Thus the Water Board, which was obligated to enforce section 5946, never challenged DWP's activities . DWP's actions and the responses they received indicate the manipulation of perceptions of justice, especially when that perception serves in the interests of a powerful actor . Although the Water Board issued DWP's permits in the 1930s, DWP did not obtain licenses for Mono Basin water until 1974, owing in part to the rule of water appropriation that required DWP to put to beneficial use all of the water it intended to use prior to obtaining a license . The permits would allow DWP access to all of the flow of both the Owens and Mono Basin flows . At the time, however, DWP lacked the capacity to export the combined flow of this water to Los Angeles because their aqueduct across the Mohave Desert only had one barrel . The second barrel had been planned since the permits were granted, but the city had not grown sufficiently until the 1950s to justify the cost of construction . The second barrel was not finished until 1973, and DWP did not ask for its permits to be confirmed as licenses until 1974. DWP thus deliberately delayed the licensing process-in the meantime keeping others from appropriating the surplus wateruntil the cost of the second barrel could be justified . DWP's tactics and the water diversions they supported were within existing water rights laws . Whether their actions enhanced collective welfare, broadly defined, however, is questionable . Their interests focused narrowly on the development of the Los Angeles area, with little concern for the consequences for the Mono Basin area at any point in time-past, present, or future . Toleration of this
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
271
apparent disregard clearly eroded by the late 1970s with onset of a drought in California and the increased awareness of environmental issues . Drought conditions in the 1980s highlighted the scarcity of the resource . Water shortages affected population centers throughout the state (e .g ., San Francisco bay area, Sacramento), which raised questions about the disproportionate diversion of water to Southern California. These conditions, coupled with the shift toward an ecological worldview, undermined the fairness of the existing distribution principle, as Jasso (1983) would predict . Thus, although the diversion remained sanctioned by the state (i .e ., authorization), its legitimacy in the view of many (i .e ., endorsement) had eroded . Conflicting Justice Evaluations : Legal Challenges to DWP's Appropriation
Although differential perceptions of DWP's activities had long existed, the legitimacy of the opposing claims gained new life with the backing of strong environmental groups . The competing claims epitomized differences in values and the meaning of collective welfare . To resolve their differing claims of what would be fair and legitimate use of Mono Basin water, the environmental groups turned to the courts . They based their arguments on existing legal principles that consider benefits of a resource for all citizens . The parties relied on the courts as a just institution to enforce existing law and ensure justice for generations . Below we detail the events leading to the court's ruling . In doing so, we note difficulties even for a just institution to provide for intergenerational justice . In the late 1970s groups such as the National Audubon Society and the Mono Lake Committee (the latter of which formed specially to sponsor efforts to preserve the lake) coalesced to bring a lawsuit in 1979 challenging DWP's diversions in the California courts . These groups specifically couched their arguments for the reallocation of Mono Basin water in terms of intergenerational justice by relying upon the legal doctrine of "Public Trust." The Public Trust doctrine has its origins in both Roman law and English Common law . The Statutes of Justinian provided that "[b]y the law of nature these things are common to mankind-the air, running water, the sea and consequently the shores of the sea" (Institutes of Justinian 2 .1 .1 cited in National Audubon Society v . Superior Court, 33 Cal . 3d 419, 433 (1983)) . English Common Law developed the notion into the principle that the sovereign owns navigable waterways, holding them in trust for the benefit of all of the people (Stevens 1980) . When California became a state, it became trustee of the state's navigable waterways for the public benefit (City of Berkeley v. Superior Court, 26 Cal. 3d 515 (1980)) . As a trustee, the state is the nominal owner of the property and everything it does with the trust property must be in the best interests of all beneficiaries equally (Restatement of the Law 2d (Trusts) § 182) . When property such as a navigable waterway is viewed as a trust property, held for the benefit of all of the citizens, it operates to limit the ability of the trustee (the state) to grant exclusive
2 72
KAREN A. HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
ownership rights to some of the beneficiaries to the exclusion of others . In addition, an earlier Supreme Court ruling held that the Public Trust protected more than just the right to navigate, but included commerce, fishing, and even "the preservation of those lands in their natural state, so that they may serve as ecological units for scientific study, as open space, and as environments which provide food and habitat for birds and marine life, and which favorably affect the scenery and climate of the area" (Marks v . Whitney, 6 Cal . 3d 251, 359-60 (1971)) . The Public Trust doctrine allowed the environmental groups to argue that the state could not lawfully grant DWP exclusive rights to Mono Lake water because the state's own rights were limited by its trustee obligations . This argument in effect introduced an alternative definition of collective welfare and challenged the legitimacy of the interpretation of the water rights laws under which DWP was granted its permits . DWP contended in response that the Public Trust doctrine was "subsumed" in the water rights allocation process and thus could not affect its vested rights. The California Supreme Court recognized these two competing notions of what would constitute the fair distribution of Mono Basin water in its 1983 decision resolving some of the lawsuit's legal issues (National Audubon Society v . Superior Court, 33 Cal . 3d at 445 (1983)) . Noting that the Public Trust doctrine and the water appropriation system developed independently of each other and that embracing one at the cost of the other created an unbalanced structure, the Court rejected the argument that one doctrine was subsumed under the other and attempted to establish an accommodation making use of both sets of principles . The Court held : (1) that the state had a continuing duty to control the use of water in navigable waterways, and that this duty bars anyone from obtaining "a vested right to appropriate water in a manner harmful to the interests protected by the public trust;" (2) California's economic needs and the reliance of many on existing water allocations may allow harm to the Public Trust ; but (3) in considering water allocations and potential injury to the Public Trust, the state has an "affirmative duty" to take the public trust into account and to protect it whenever feasible . By applying the Public Trust rule-which existed at the time of the original allocation but was contrary to the interests of DWP-the Court permitted a reallocation of Mono Basin water . In its decision, the Court reconciled two existing but competing principles that may govern the allocation of water resources . The decision illustrated the difficulty of institutions to provide for a justice that encompasses all parties . Theoretically, in integrating Public Trust doctrine in the governance of water allocations, the Court broadened the definition of collective welfare to include a larger group of beneficiaries, and implied consideration for that group both now and in the future . Realistically, however, while purportedly not creating an entirely new legal basis for challenging water allocation decisions, the substantive limits the Public Trust doctrine imposes on water rights are not well defined .
Intergenerational Justice
and the Environment
273
In fact, although the Public Trust doctrine was applied to DWP's water rights in the 1983 National Audubon decision, the courts did not order water to be released into Mono Lake until 1985 . Its release, moreover, stemmed from a court injunction in later lawsuits filed under the Fish & Game Code (Jones & Stokes Associates 1993) . These lawsuits raised the question of DWP's exemptions from Fish & Game Code statues that had been in effect for decades . As described earlier, section 5937 of the code requires the owner of any dam to allow passage of sufficient water "to keep in good condition fish that may be planted or exist below the dam ;" and, Section 5946 prevents the issuance of any water permit or license (after September 9, 1953) unless the appropriator complies fully with Section 5937 . In two decisions, California Trout, Inc . v . State Water Resources Control Board, 207 Cal . App . 3d 585 (1989) and California Trout, Inc. v . Superior Court, 218 Cal . App . 3d 187 (1990), the California Court of Appeal required that DWP's water rights license be amended to contain the limitation for fish life required by Fish & Game Code § 5937 . In effect, the environmental groups' challenge to DWP's water diversions used old laws-most likely created to protect the interests of recreational fishermen more than a generation ago-to protect a natural resource for future generations . The Fish & Game Code statutes provided more definite, more clearly established, and simpler allocation rules than the more nebulous Public Trust doctrine . Although the latter more explicitly protects future generations, application of the former highlights another sense in which the Mono Lake case in intergenerational . That is, rules established for one purpose at one point in time may serve another purpose at a later point in time . Moreover, it is plainly easier to obtain a reallocation when the reallocation principle is simpler, easier to apply, and when the reallocation decision results from a prior, mistaken application of a previously existing rule rather than by the invention of a new allocation rule . In the case of Mono Lake, to comply with either the specific dictates of the Fish & Game Code or the less specific requirements of the Public Trust Doctrine, was necessary to allow the lake to rise far above the 6,372-foot level proposed by DWP (Jones & Stokes Associates 1993) . The claims of DWP-its conception of fairness in the distribution of Mono Basin water-lost ground in this case . As with the shift toward an ecological social worldview (Olsen, Lodwick, and Dunlap 1992), public opinion supported preserving Mono Lake : federal and state legislatures appropriated funds for DWP to develop alternative water supplies ; (former) Los Angeles mayor Tom Bradley, who appointed commissioners of DWP, called for resolving the Mono Lake controversy ; and opinion surveys on the Mono Lake issue show that the public is willing to pay substantially more than the cost of replacement water to protect Mono Lake (Jones & Stokes Associates 1993) . The ultimate reallocation of water from Los Angeles to Mono Lake occurred in September 1994, when the California State Water Resources Control Board issued a decision amending DWP's water rights licenses and requiring DWP to
274
KAREN A. HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
release enough water to bring the lake to an elevation of 6,392 feet (Water Board 1994) . As part of its hearing process, the Water Board held statewide public hearings in which any member of the public could comment on the reallocation issue . Of the hundreds of witnesses who appeared at the public sessions, only two spoke in favor of the DWP position : DWP itself and an engineer working for DWP . Even the administration of Republican Governor Pete Wilson-who appointed all the members of the Water Board-spoke in favor of the Mono Lake Committee position . Bereft of political allies, DWP finally capitulated and agreed not to appeal Water Board's decision (Hart 1996) . Although the final battle for Mono Lake was won in the field of politics, the court decisions made the victory possible in two ways . First, the courts legitimized environmentalist claims . The political battle could not have been waged, much less won, if the courts had not singled their strong support for the Mono Lake cause . Second, once DWP lost the political battle, its only other alternative was to return to the courts, where DWP could not expect a friendly reception . DWP's decision to forgo any appeal was based on its repeated failures in the courts, combined with the absence of public or political support for its position . All parties to the dispute and the public at large accepted the Water Board's decision to reallocate water in the Mono Lake . There was no subsequent legal challenge to the Water Board's decision, and it received wide praise across the political spectrum (Hart 1996) . This praise for the final decision suggests recognition of a broader definition of collective welfare-both now and in the futureunderlying just distributions of natural resources .
CONCLUSION : FAIR ENVIRONMENTAL POLICIES FOR THE FUTURE In this paper we have outlined group processes underlying the establishment of a just distribution, the awareness of injustice in a distribution, and responses to conflicting perceptions of justice. In applying these notions to the distribution of environmental resources, we have raised concerns with issues of justice as they affect multiple generations . To illustrate how these processes play out in the actual allocation of environmental goods, we summarized the chronology of events in the long-standing litigation regarding the allocation of water from the Mono Basin . Both the theoretical analysis and the empirical example suggest future avenues for research .
Establishing Justice and Responding to Injustice Although condensed, the theoretical background highlights necessary elements to consider in analyzing any policy debate regarding the distribution of resources . First, it is necessary to recognize that the structural power positions and related
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
275
interests of parties affect establishment and perceptions of what constitutes a fair distribution . These interests, moreover, influence the processing of information and the value of resources . To the extent that individuals have different interests, they are likely to have different perceptions of fairness . Throughout the history of the diversion of water from the Mono Basin, DWP represented only one vision of the just use of that water, a vision based on the goal of economic development in a distant city . The differences between DWP and its opponents may stem not from differences in a self-interested motivation, but in terms of the values inherent in the goals pursued and the definition of collective welfare, which is at the heart of a notion of justice that is beyond justified self-interest . Interestingly, the justice literature mentions though rarely explores empirically underlying motivations of actors involved in distributions or judgments of those distributions (see Hegtvedt and Markovsky 1995) . Thus investigation of underlying interests is an important direction for both basic research and applied analysis of environmental decision making . Second, as Jasso (1983) points out and the Mono Lake case illustrates, changes in structural conditions challenge the legitimacy of a particular distribution principle . The challenge derives from implications of resource scarcity for alterations in the goals pursued and the value of the resources, which in turn affect individuals' endorsement of a particular distribution . The dramatically decreased lake level, which represents a scarcity of water in the area, threatens the ecological system of the Mono Basin . The decreased level along with a general shift in the 1970s toward a more ecological worldview (Olsen, Lodwick, and Dunlap 1992) stimulated a successful challenge to DWP's policies, which appeared to be authorized owing to compliance with rules for obtaining licenses although not other rules (e .g ., the Public Trust doctrine and the Fish & Game Codes, sections 5937 and 5946). Thus the case highlights a long overlooked aspect of distributive injustice : its source in the application of inappropriate distribution principles . Eroding endorsement for a principle (i .e ., lack of legitimacy in the eyes of peers) portends a rule's inappropriateness . Although much research examines reactions to injustice based on the mis-application of a particular rule (e .g ., failure to produce equitable outcomes in a work group) (see Cook and Hegtvedt 1983 ; Hegtvedt and Cook forthcoming), far less focuses on situations when the wrong rule is applied . And, as Jasso (1983) would suggest, the wrong rule is more likely under changes in resource availability, goals, or valuation of resources . Systematic analysis of these underlying conditions and changes in perceptions of injustice is needed . A contrast between these two general types of injustice may also have implications for understanding reactions to injustice . Following in the Adams (1965) tradition, most research on reactions has focused on individual level reactions and the few studies examining collective reactions have pertained to the inappropriate application of a distribution rule . 1 1 The case study suggests that despite local citizens' cries of unfairness in the 1930s and onward, it was ultimately the coalition between these citizens and environmental groups that successfully led to changes
2 76
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
in the distribution rule . Collective responses may be a necessary condition to rectify injustice based on the application of an inappropriate rule, especially with regard to natural resources, which may in some respects be more like public than private goods . Research contrasting the type of injustice, the nature of the resource, and the success of possible responses could explore this issue . Moreover, any research considering injustice arising from the application of an inappropriate distribution principle invariably links the dynamics of justice processes to those of legitimacy (Walker and Zelditch 1993 ; Zelditch and Walker 1984) and pushes legitimacy research beyond the confines of formal organizations (see Hegtvedt and Johnson unpublished) . Resolving Competing Justice Claims
A major implication of changing conditions for perceptions of justice is the likelihood of conflict about what is just. As outlined in the initial theoretical section, little research addresses the means to resolve competing justice claims . What discussion there is (Hegtvedt 1992a ; Lamm 1986) relies upon negotiation as a means to resolve conflict between individuals whose perceptions differ . Because it is empirically difficult to discern whether allocation preferences reflect simply self-interests or a concern with justice per se, work in this area has been limited . Preliminary results from Hegtvedt, Brezina, and Funk (1995) show that individuals whose allocation preferences promote their self-interested material well-being are more likely to invoke justice rhetoric (i.e ., proclaiming the fairness of their own distribution and the unfairness of their partner's suggestion) than those whose preferences are more generous to others . In addition, use of justice claims is a means to shroud power issues . For example, although social movements may be propelled by power issues, movement advocates may use the language of justice and other values to make their points because of the illegitimacy of seeking outright to acquire power (see McAdam, McCarthy, and Zald 1988) . Both the justice and social movements research reiterate the importance of understanding underlying motivations and conceptions of what constitutes collective welfare . The Mono Lake dispute involved groups with different interests and occupying different positions of power . Although each side shied from invoking the language of power, both provided justifications for their positions . Extrapolating from Hegtvedt, Brezina, and Funk (1995), we would expect that DWP would be more likely to resort to use of justice rhetoric to defend its position rather than the environmental groups, whose position based on the Public Trust doctrine includes an extended notion of collective welfare . It would be interesting to conduct a content analysis of the arguments presented by opposing parties in environmental cases to compare to the experimental results . Such analysis would provide a more informed understanding of the persuasiveness of arguments, given respective positions and motivations of parties, underlying the resolution of competing justice claims .
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
2 77
The sparse work on the resolution of competing justice claims has yet to investigate the possibility of negotiations between corporate actors, such as groups that have formed coalitions or that represent other bodies, or the involvement of third parties . The latter draws attention to procedural justice work . A great deal of procedural justice research has examined preferences in dispute resolution cases (see Thibaut and Walker 1975) . Without going into detail here on this body of work, the research suggests that individuals typically prefer and judge as more fair opportunities to explain their cases to a third party . In effect, by taking environmental cases to the courts, parties are attempting to resolve their differences through arbitration . Each side presents its views and a judge (or jury) makes a final decision regarding the extent of the injustice and its remedy . Moreover, this preferred process of dispute resolution embodies a key principle of procedural justice : giving voice (Folger 1977) or ensuring the representation of all parties to the dispute in the decision making (see Leventhal, Karuza, and Frye 1980) . Capek (1993) stresses the right to democratic participation in community decision making as a key element in the environmental justice frame . The final Mono Lake hearing before the State Water Board encouraged such participation by affording the opportunity for individuals representing themselves or their groups to voice their opinions about the distribution of water from the Mono Basin . The analysis offered here, however, falls short of examining the critical relationship between procedural and distributive justice . Typically, if procedures are fair, individuals are more likely to accept the outcome as fair, even if those outcomes are low (see Lind and Tyler 1988) . With regard to the Mono Lake case, had DWP involved local residents and other interested parties in their initial plans and seriously considered their input, the ultimate fervor against DWP may have been attenuated . As it was, only with the onset of litigation were other voices heard . It is likely that opponents also viewed as unfair the procedures by which decisions were made (e .g ., the Department of Fish & Game's decision to exempt DWP from a statute without the legal authority to do so ; the Water Board's failure to respond to citizens' protests in the 1940s) . The extent to which procedural justice alone can stimulate opposition-regardless of outcome level-is an important direction for research, especially in environmental debates in which the actual outcome may not be known for years . Moreover, further research is necessary to examine the confluence of types of justice with regard to the distribution of environmental resources both at one point in time as well as over time (see Clayton 1996 for more theoretical analysis and Syme and Fenton 1993 for an empirical study) . Considering Intergenerational Justice
With changes in structural conditions and accompanying variations in perceptions of justice, the feasibility of intergenerational justice seems remote . Yet emphasis on procedural justice, which would dictate the involvement of representatives of interested parties whose values may include bio-diversity for future gen-
2 78
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
erations, may facilitate the development of intergenerational justice . In addition, environmentalists have often criticized decision makers on procedural grounds for not enforcing rules already on the books (Clayton 1996) . In the Mono Lake case the court avoided this criticism by relying upon existing legal doctrine . In appealing to the courts and in the court's reliance upon existing laws-especially ones that directly pertain to multiple generations or at least have implications spanning generations-the Mono Lake case epitomizes the solution to establishing intergenerational justice offered by philosophers (Laslett and Fishkin 1992) : the involvement of just institutions to ensure justice over time . This sort of solution, in fact, has moved beyond the confines of the writings of philosophers to greater visibility in environmental arguments and governmental organizations . For example, Patterson and Andrews (1995) describe one state's comparative risk project, Washington's 2010, which attempts to " . . .include a broader range of participants in identifying, assessing, and generating preferred management strategies for a wide range of environmental hazzards" (p . 85) . This project capitalizes on ensuring procedural justice in the hope that outcomes will also be judged as fair . Similarly, Collin, Beatley, and Harris (1995) stress the importance of merging environmental planning units with those working on issues of equity in housing and community development . In effect, these projects are attempts to establish just institutions specifically charged with a focus on the environment. Perhaps the most explicit attempt to do so came in 1994 with President Clinton's Executive Order (12898) that required all federal agencies to demonstrate that their policies did not unfairly inflict environmental harm on poor and minority communities . In addition, the order allowed for the development of an inter-agency task force for environmental justice policies . Whether these developments ensure intergenerational justice will be a matter for future evaluation research . One issue that such institutions will face is whether to establish new rules for distributing scarce resources or to invoke existing rules . In either case, the rules used to establish a sense of environmental justice may vary in terms of their complexity. In the Mono Lake case, the courts acknowledged the failure of previous generations to apply an appropriate justice principle, the Public Trust doctrine, to the allocation of water rights . By harmonizing the Public Trust doctrine with existing water rights laws, the courts recognized the unfairness of past allocation decisions as well as ensured protection of the resource for the enjoyment of future generations . In effect, the legal system had provided for future generations when it accepted the notion of the Public Trust . To the extent that legislatures must establish new laws (or the courts construct new legal theories) to protect environmental resources, they may threaten powerful parties who have benefitted from existing laws . As a consequence, they may face greater challenges . For example, the struggle between timber and wildlife interests in the Pacific Northwest portends substantially greater public controversy in its resolution than was the case in the Mono Lake dispute because legal principles of appropriate age and duration
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
279
do not appear available . It remains an empirical question, however, whether application of existing rules results in lower levels of animosity among parties than the development of new rules . And, more generally, research should examine the conditions under which institutions rely upon existing rules or develop new ones . If the course is toward the development of new rules to ensure fair distributions of environmental resources, the Mono Lake case suggests that simplicity and concreteness of rules may, under some conditions, be more effective than abstract, complex rules . Although the Public Trust doctrine captures important ideals to protect the environment intergenerationally, its dictates were more difficult to implement than those of the Fish & Game code, which also implies a long-term distribution of a resource . Whether it is more useful to establish abstract principles that can be interpreted subject to specific contextual concerns or to construe narrower allocation rules may depend upon the nature of the resource at issue, the breadth of the underlying goal, the desire for expediency, or, as is a main concern of this paper, the intended duration of the distribution . When resources are nonrenewable, but when their use has substantial and immediate economic benefit in the present, intergenerational conflict is joined . The Mono Lake case suggests that it is easier to resolve intergenerational conflicts by the application of generation-spanning allocation rules, rather than by the invention of new rules as changed circumstances may dictate . Rules created today that allow for flexible use tomorrow by necessity expand the definition of collective welfare that underlies a true sense of justice . As the review of philosophical discussions of intergenerational justice indicate, it is difficult to anticipate what future generations will consider beneficial and harmful . To the extent that principles and institutions exist to maintain resources for yet unborn populations, future people can assess the value of those resources for themselves . Indeed, like the color of a tapestry, the value of resources and the fairness of their distribution will change over time . It is the provision of this possibility that ensures intergenerational justice .
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Patrick J. Flinn was an attorney for some of the parties involved in the Mono Lake litigation ; the views presented here, however, are his own and not necessarily those of his firm or the parties he represented . We would like to thank reviewers of this manuscript for their helpful comments .
NOTES 1 . Although policies may reflect images of fairness in the distribution of resources, concerns with justice are neither necessary nor sufficient to the development of policy . Additional factorsinterest groups, politics, expedience, competing allocations, safety, and so on-contribute to shaping
280
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK) . FLINN
policy decisions as well . See Sabatier (1999) on theories of the policy process and various selections in Reuss (1993) for discussion of policy development regarding water resources specifically . 2. Complementing distributive justice, is procedural justice, or the fairness of the process of coming to a decision. Although this paper focuses primarily on distributive justice, issues of procedural justice are highly relevant to establishment and evaluation of environmental policy concerns (see Clayton 1996), and we touch upon such issues in our discussion . 3 . The notion of intergenerational justice may also apply to the domains of child welfare, education, and health care (see Cook and Donnelly 1996) . 4. The relationship between justice and legitimacy is complex . Legitimacy suggests a process through which patterns of behavior gain social support and are justified (see Ridgeway and Walker 1995) . As suggested by Weber (1968) legitimacy implies that actors believe social orders are desirable and the norms binding on members of the collectivity . Typically, as discussed further below, what is legal implies legitimacy . What is legitimate, however, may not be believed to be just by various parties . For example, tax laws are legitimate, but many may take issue with their fairness . And, what is just may not be legitimate . For example, many see the justness in the global fight for human rights yet in some countries that fight comes up against laws that allow suppression of individual freedoms . A thorough analysis of the justice/legitimacy relationship is beyond the scope of this paper (but see Hegtvedt and Johnson, unpublished, for a circumscribed analysis of this relationship) . Here we focus on people's evaluations of distributions as just, which may challenge existing legitimated distributions and forge new ones . 5 . The environmental movement has involved a number of large and small coalitions of activists, who draw attention to environmental interests . For example, African-American residents of the toxically contaminated Carver Terrace neighborhood of Texarkana, Texas mobilized to win a federal buyout and relocation after being declared a Superfund site in 1984 (Capek 1993) . Such mobilization-fueled by perceptions of environmental injustice-creates a corporate actor in environmental debates. Moreover, the larger environmental movement has been likened to a means not only to ensure environmental quality but also civil rights (Sarokin and Scholkin 1994) . The incentives, strategies, and coordination of such mobilization, however, are beyond the scope of this paper . We assume such processes result in advancing the goals of the environmental movement, which embody justice claims that compete with those of developers or other parties with an interest in using environmental resources . 6. In addition to the worldview approach, researchers have offered several schemes to capture different value orientations, for example, egoistic, altruistic, ecocentric (see Axelrod 1994 ; Merchant, 1992; Stern and Dietz 1994) . Presumably, these value orientations affect one's perceptions of what constitutes environmental justice (Clayton 1996) . 7 . Although intergenerational justice may also be backward looking, that is, focused on rectifying injustices of past generations, we confine our discussion to justice issues for future generations . 8 . Several books have outlined the history and politics of water distribution, for example, Gottlieb (1988), A Life of Its Own : The Politics of Power and Water and Walton (1992), Western Times and Water Wars. The latter chronicles events in the Owens Valley of California involving the use of water from the Owens River by the City of Los Angeles . Framed as a case study of social protest and politics, the book provides general background on events leading to the Mono Lake litigation and raises issues other than those presented here . 9 . The western water laws contrast with laws in the eastern United States, which typically restrict water use to riparian owners and limited the use of water to lands directly adjacent to the waterway . Thus a farmer with a stream could irrigate only the property adjacent to the water source . Moreover, eastern laws generally do not permit a farmer to interfere unreasonably with downstream riparian landowner. 10 . Such rhetoric constitutes justification for each party's position and is akin to the type of legitimations Berger and Luckmann (1966) describe. In contrast to legitimation in terms of authorization and endorsement, which provide collective (external) legitimation for a rule, act, and so on, justifications provide individuals with an internalized sense of legitimation for a position .
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
281
11 . Although individual-level reactions to injustice were the first heavily investigated area of research, little of the existing literature addresses choices among various individual-level reactions (see Hegtvedt and Cook forthcoming) . Here we extend the notion of choices to include the possibility of both individual and collective responses .
REFERENCES Adams, J . S . 1965 . "Inequity in Social Exchange ." Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 2 : 267-299 . Axelrod, L . 1994 . "Balancing Personal Needs with Environmental Preservation : Identifying the Values That Guide Decisions in Ecological Dilemmas ." Journal of Social Issues 50 : 85-104 . Austin, W. 1980. "Friendship and Fairness : Effects of Type of Relationship and Task Performance on Choice of Distribution Rules." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 4 : 402-408 . Ball, T . 1985 . "The Incoherence of Intergenerational Justice ." Inquiry 23 : 321-337 . Berger, P . L ., and T . Luckmann . 1966 . The Social Construction of Reality . Garden City, NY : Doubleday . Barry, B . 1989 . Theories of Justice (vol . 1). Berkeley : University of California Press . Bullard, R . D ., and B . H . Wright. 1992 . "The Quest for Environmental Equity : Mobilizing the AfricanAmerican Community for Social Change." Pp . 39-50 in American Environmentalism, edited by R . E . Dunlap and A . G . Mertig . Philadelphia : Taylor & Francis . Blau, P . 1964. "Justice in Social Exchange ." Sociological Inquiry 34 : 193-206 . Capek, S . M. 1993 . "The `Environmental Justice' Frame : A Conceptual Discussion and Application ." Social Problems 40 : 5-24 . Clayton, S. 1996. "What Is Fair in the Environmental Debate?" Pp . 195-211 in Current Societal Concerns about Justice, edited by L. Montada and M . J . Lerner . New York : Plenum Press . Cohen, R . L ., and J . Greenberg . 1982 . "The Justice Concept in Social Psychology ." Pp . 1-42 in Equity and Justice in Social Behavior, edited by J . Greenberg and R. L . Cohen . New York : Academic Press. Collin, R . W ., T . Beatley, and W . Harris . 1995 . "Environmental Racism : A Challenge to Community Development ." Journal of Black Studies 24 : 354-376 . Cook, K . S ., and S. Donnelly . 1996 . "Intergenerational Relations, Inequality, and Social Justice ." Pp .67-84 in Current Societal Concerns about Justice, edited by L . Montada and M . J . Lerner. New York: Plenum Press . Cook, K . S ., and K . A. Hegtvedt. 1983 . "Distributive Justice, Equity, and Equality ." Annual Review of Sociology 9 : 217-241 . Daly, H . E ., and J. B . Cobb, Jr . 1989 . For the Common Good : Redirecting the Economy toward Community, the Environment, and a Sustainable Future . Boston : Beacon Press . Della Fave, L . R . 1980 . "The Meek Shall Not Inherit the Earth : Self-Evaluation and the Legitimacy of Stratification ." American Sociological Review 45 : 995-971 . Deutsch, M . 1975 . "Equity, Equality, and Need : What Determines What Value Will Be Used as the Basis for Distributive Justice?" Journal of Social Issues 31 : 137-150. Dunlap, R . E., and A . G . Mertig. 1992 . "The Evolution of the U .S . Environmental Movement from 1970 to 1980 : Overview ." Pp. 1-10 in American Environmentalism, edited by R . E . Dunlap and A . G . Mertig . Philadelphia: Taylor & Francis . Ekeh, P. P . 1974 . Social Exchange Theory: The Two Traditions Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press. Emerson, R . M . 1972. "Exchange Theory, Part II : Exchange Relations and Networks ." Pp. 58-87 in Sociological Theories in Progress, volume 2, edited by J . Berger, M . Zelditch, and B . Anderson . Boston : Houghton Mifflin .
282
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
Farquhar, F . P . 1949 . Up and Down California in 1860-1864, The Journal of William H . Brewer. Berkeley : The University of California Press . Fishkin, J . S . 1992 . The Dialogue of Justice: Toward a Self-Reflective Society . New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Fiske, S . T ., and S . E . Taylor. 1991 . Social Cognition . New York: McGraw-Hill . Folger, R. 1977 . "Distributive and Procedural Justice : Combined Impact of 'Voice' and Improvement on Experienced Inequity ." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 35 : 108-119 . Gottlieb, R. 1988 . A Life of Its Own: The Politics of Power and Water. San Diego : Harcourt Brace Jovanovich . Hart, J . 1996 . Storm Over Mono : The Mono Lake Battle and the California Water Future. Berkeley : University of California Press . Hartley, T . W. 1995 . "Environmental Justice : An Environmental Civil Rights Value Acceptable to All World Views." Environmental Ethics 17 : 277-289 . Hegtvedt, K. A . 1987 . "When Rewards Are Scarce : Equal or Equitable Distributions?" Social Forces 66 : 183-207 . Hegtvedt, K. A . 1992a. "Bargaining for Justice : The Resolution of Competing Justice Claims ." Social Justice Research 5 : 155-172 . Hegtvedt, K . A. 1992b. "When Is a Distribution Rule Just?" Rationality and Society 4 : 308-331 . Hegtvedt, K . A ., T. Brezina, and S . Funk. 1995 . "When Cries of 'It's Not Fair' Are Not Fair : Factors Affecting the Negotiated Resolution of Justice Conflict ." Paper presented at the meetings of the American Sociological Association, Washington, DC . Hegtvedt, K. A ., and K . S . Cook . Forthcoming . "Distributive Justice : Recent Theoretical Developments and Applications ." In The Justice Reader, edited by J . Sanders and V . L. Hamilton. New York: Plenum Press . Hegtvedt, K. A ., and K. S . Cook. 1987 . "The Role of Justice in Conflict Situations ." Pp . 109-136 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol . 4, edited by E. Lawler. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press Inc . Hegtvedt, K . A., and C . Johnson. Unpublished. "Justice Beyond the Individual: A Future with Legitimation ." Department of Sociology, Emory University. Hegtvedt, K. A ., and B . Markovsky . 1995 . "Justice and Injustice ." Pp . 257-280 in Sociological Perspectives on Social Psychology, edited by K . S . Cook, G . Fine, and J. House . Boston : Allyn Bacon . Heinegg, P . 1979 . "Ecology and Social Justice : Ethical Dilemmas and Revolutionary Hopes." Environmental Ethics 1 : 321-327 . Homans, G . 1974. Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms. New York : Harcourt, Brace and World. Hutchins, W . 1956. The California Law of Water Rights . State of California. Jasso, G. 1983. "Fairness of Individual Rewards and Fairness of the Reward Distribution : Specifying the Inconsistency between Micro and Macro Principles of Justice ." Social Psychology Quarterly 46 : 185-199 . Jones & Stokes Associates . 1993 . Draft Environmental Impact Report for the Review of the Mono Basin Water Rights of the City of Los Angeles . Prepared for the California State Water Resources Control Board . Kahn, A ., R . E. Nelson, W . Gaeddert, and J . L . Hearn . 1982 . "The Justice Process : Deciding upon Equity or Equality ." Social Psychology Quarterly 45 : 3-8 . Kernis, M . H ., and H . T. Reis . 1984 . "Self-consciousness, Self-Awareness, and Justice in Reward Allocation ." Journal of Personality 52 : 58-70 . Lamm, H . 1986 . "Justice Considerations in Interpersonal Conflict ." Pp . 43-63 in Justice in Social Relations, edited by H . Bierhoff, R. Cohen, and J . Greenberg . New York: Plenum Press . Laslett, P. 1992 . "Is There a Generational Contract?" Pp . 24-48 in Justice between Age Groups and Generations, edited by P . Laslett and J. S . Fishkin . New Haven, CT : Yale University Press .
Intergenerational Justice and the Environment
283
Laslett, P ., and J . S . Fishkin . 1992 . "Introduction : Processional Justice ." Pp . 1-23 in Justice between Age Groups and Generations, edited by P . Laslett and J . S . Fishkin. New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Lenski, G . 1966 . Power and Privilege . New York: McGraw-Hill . Leventhal, G ., J . Karuza, Jr ., and W . R. Fry. 1980. "Beyond Fairness : A Theory of Allocation Preferences ." Pp . 167-218 in Justice and Social Interaction, edited by G . Mikula . New York: Springer-Verlag . Lind, E . A., and T. R . Tyler. 1988. The Social Psychology of Procedural Justice . New York : Plenum Press . Luper-Foy, S . 1992. "Justice and Natural Resources ." Environmental Values 1 : 47-64 . McAdam, D ., J . McCarthy, and M. Zald . 1988 . "Social Movements ." Pp . 695-737 in Handbook of Sociology, edited by N . Smelser . Newbury Park, CA : Sage . Merchant, C . 1992. Radical Ecology : The Search for a Livable World. New York: Routledge, Chapman, and Hall . National Academy of Sciences Mono Basin Ecosystem Study Committee . 1987 . The Mono Basin Ecosystem : Effects of Changing Lake Level . Washington, DC : National Academy Press . Norris, J . E. 1987 . "Justice and Intergenerational Relations : An Introduction ." Social Justice Research 1 : 393-404 . Olsen, M . E., D . G. Lodwick, and R . E . Dunlap. 1992. Viewing the World Ecologically . Boulder, CO : Westview Press . O'Malley, M . N ., and D . Becker . 1984 . "Removing Egocentric Bias : The Relevance of Distress Cues to Evaluation of Fairness ." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 10 : 235-242 . Patterson, C . J ., and R . N . L . Andrews. 1995 . "Procedural and Substantive Fairness in Risk Decisions : Comparative Risk Assessment Procedures ." Policy Studies Journal 23 : 85-95 . Perrolle, J . A . 1993 . "The Emerging Dialogue on Environmental Justice ." Social Problems 40 : 1-4 . Petrikin, J . S ., ed . 1995 . Environmental Justice. San Diego : Greenhaven Press . Rawls, J . 1971 . A Theory of Justice. Boston : Harvard University Press. Reis, H . T . 1986 . "Levels of Interest in the Study of Interpersonal Justice ." Pp . 186-2 10 in Justice in Social Relations, edited by H . Bierhoff, R . L. Cohen, and J . Greenberg . New York : Plenum Press . Restatement of the Law 2d (Trusts), American Law Institute (1957) . Reuss, M ., ed . 1993 . Water Resources Administration in the United States . East Lansing, MI : Michigan State University Press . Ridgeway, C., and H . A. Walker. 1995 . "Status Structures." Pp. 281-310 in Sociological Perspectives on Social Psychology, edited by K . S . Cook, G . Fine, and J . House . Boston : Allyn Bacon . Sabatier, P. A. 1999 . Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO : Westview Press . Sarokin, D . J., and J . Schulkin. 1994 . "Environmental Justice : Co-evolution of Environmental Concerns and Social Justice ." Environmentalist 14 : 121-129. Stern, P ., and T. Dietz . 1994 . "The Value Basis of Environmental Concerns ." Journal of Social Issues 50 : 65-84 . Stevens, J . 1980 . "The Public Trust: A Sovereign's Ancient Prerogative Becomes the People's Environmental Right ." University of California at Davis Law Review 14 : 195 . Stine, S . 1987 . Geomorphic and Geohydrographic Aspects of the Mono Lake Controversy . Report to the Community Organization and Research Institute, University of California, Santa Barbara . Stretskey, P ., and M . J . Hogan . 1998 . "Environmental Justice : An Analysis of Superfund Sites in Florida." Social Problems 45 : 268-287 . Syme, G . J ., and D . M . Fenton . 1993 . "Perceptions of Equity and Procedural Preferences for Water Allocation Decisions." Society and Natural Resources 6 : 347-360. Thibaut, J ., and L. Walker . 1975 . Procedural Justice: A Psychological Analysis . Hillsdale, NJ : Lawrence Erlbaum .
284
KAREN A . HEGTVEDT and PATRICK J . FLINN
Tyler, T. R., and E. A. Lind. 1992 . "A Relational Model of Authority in Groups." Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 1(25) : 115-191 . TRC Environmental Corporation . 1993 . Draft Mono Lake Air Quality Modeling Study . Prepared for the Great Basin Unified Air Pollution Control District, Bishop, California Walker, H . A ., and M. Zelditch, Jr. 1993 . "Power, Legitimacy, and the Stability of Authority: A Theoretical Research Program ." Pp. 364-381 in Theoretical Research Programs, edited by J . Berger and M. Zelditch, Jr . Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Walster, E., G . W . Walster, and E . Berscheid . 1978 . Equity : Theory and Research . Boston : Allyn and Bacon. Walton, J. 1992 . Western Times and Water Wars : State, Culture, and Rebellion in California . Berkeley: University of California Press . Water Board (California Division of Water Resources) . 1940 . Decisions 7053, 7055, 8042 & 8043 . Water Board (California State Water Resources Control Board). 1994 . Decision 1631 . Weber, M . 1968. Economy and Society, edited by G . Roth and C .Wittich. Berkeley : University of California Press . Wenz, P .S . 1988 . Environmental Justice. Albany, NY : State University of New York Press . Wolfe, L. M ., ed . 1979 . John of the Mountains : The Unpublished Journals of John Muir . Boston: Houghton Mifflin . Zelditch, M ., Jr ., and H . A. Walker . 1984 . "Legitimacy and the Stability of Authority ." Pp . 1-25 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol. 1, edited by E. Lawler. Greenwich, CT : JAI Press .
A THEORY OF EMBEDDED ENCOUNTERS
Jonathan H . Turner
ABSTRACT A conceptual framework for analyzing the relations among macro-, meso-, and micro-level forces is introduced . This framework is used to develop propositions (enumerated in Appendices A-J) explaining the dynamics of embedded encounters . Encounters are viewed as embedded within corporate and categoric units which, in turn, are lodged in institutional domains . Meso-level corporate and categoric units determine the number of individuals present, the nature of the distinctions among these individuals, the locations of individuals in structures, and the broader cultural scripts that circumscribe interaction of those in focused interaction. The encounter itself reveals its own dynamic properties revolving around demographic, status, symbolic, and transactional forces which, on the one side, reflect the structure and culture of corporate and categoric units and which, on the other side, reveal the potential to change meso- and macro-level structures and their associated cultural symbols .
Advances in Group Processes, Volume 17, pages 285-322 . Copyright 0 2000 by JAI Press Inc. All rights of reproduction in any form reserved . ISBN : 0-7623-0651-3 285
286
JONATHAN H . TURNER
Over the last 25 years theoretical sociology has debated the primacy of microversus macro-level forces in understanding the social world . Indeed, for a time in the 1970s and 1980s, sociological theory seemed somewhat consumed with conceptually bridging the perceived micro-macro "gap ." Thus far, these efforts to connect micro and macro levels of analysis have been more successful at the empirical than at the theoretical level of analysis . It is relatively easy to connect a macro variable-say, class membership as measured by an SES index-with a micro variable, such as people's attitudes or behaviors with respect to a particular topic . At a theoretical level, however, the problem revolves around identifying the generic or fundamental properties of macro and micro phenomena and, then, specifying conceptually in models and/or propositions how the dynamics of each property affect the operation of the others . In this paper I will make a preliminary effort to meet this theoretical challenge by arguing that social reality itself unfolds at three levels-micro, meso, and macro-and that the dynamics of forces at one level constrain the operative dynamics at other levels . I will argue further that the most theoretical payoff comes when our theories emphasize top-down processes-that is, macro to meso to micro . This emphasis stands in contrast to efforts by a number of prominent theorists to examine how macrostructures are ultimately constructed from face-to-face interaction processes . Even Talcott Parsons (1937, 1951) began with a micro analysis in building his grand conceptual edifice, and later efforts outside of functionalism have adopted the same strategy (e .g., Shibutani 1986 ; Collins 1981 ; Blumer 1962) . At some ultimate metaphysical level, it is certainly true that meso and macro structures are constructed from face-to-face interaction, but recognizing this fact is not the same as being able to theorize constructively about the connections among levels of reality . As I will stress, the problem of aggregation (of micro processes to make up a meso or macro structure) tends to leave micro to macro analyses metaphorical, without precise statements of how the meso and macro levels are constructed from micro encounters . In the end what tends to emerge are statements such as "society is constructed from symbolic interactions," "society is built from chains of interaction rituals," and the like . These statements are probably true but they do not explain the macro or meso, and in fact, I do not think that they adequately explain the embeddedness of the micro in meso and macro structures .
MICRO, MESO, AND MACRO LEVELS OF ANALYSIS To make the effort to connect theoretically population-level or societal-level dynamics with interpersonal processes, we must begin with analytical distinction among micro, meso, and macro . Many emphasize that this is an analytical rather than empirical separation of the social universe, since reality does not lay itself bare in this manner. Still, even as we admit that the distinction among micro,
287
A Theory of Embedded Encounters Forces
Structural Outcomes
Macro-level forces Social Institutions
Meso-level forces
Micro-level forces Figure 1 .
Corporate Units
Categoric Units
Encounters of Face-to-Face Interaction The Embeddedness of Macro- , Meso- , and Micro-level Social Forces
meso, and macro is analytical, I believe that there are metaphysical reasons for making this tri-part division . Human organization is not possible unless certain fundamental population-level problems of surviving in the environment are addressed, forcing the development of institutional systems at the macro level . But, institutions have to be built from something, and these are the structures of the meso level . And, meso-level structures constrain but are given life by individuals in face-to-face interactions comprising a micro level of reality . Without these three domains of reality becoming embedded in each other, larger-scale patterns of social organization would not be possible . The next issue is how to conceptualize the forces and structures at each level . In my view, the social universe is guided by universal forces which drive action, interaction, and organization ; and in so doing, they give social reality its pattern and structure . What I have in mind here is a notion very similar to Newton's use of the concept of gravity to explain the orbits of planets . Similarly, sociological theory should be about the fundamental forces that drive the properties of social reality at the micro, meso, and macro levels of analysis . Figure 1 delineates the structural outcomes of these fundamental forces . At the macro level (Turner 1995), the most generic patterns of the organization are institutional systems-for example, economy, polity, kinship, religion, law, medicine, education, and the like . At the meso level the two most generic forms of organization are corporate units and categoric units (Hawley 1986), with corporate units consisting of a division of labor among actors pursuing ends (e .g ., complex organizations,
288
JONATHAN H . TURNER
groups, communities) and with categoric units consisting of subpopulations of actors labeled as possessing certain characteristics (e .g ., social class, age cohorts, ethnic groups, gender) . At the micro level the most generic structure is the encounter which, following Goffman (1961, 1967, 1983) consists of either focused or unfocused interaction . As the arrows in the figure indicate, the forces
Macro-level forces Population forces Production forces Distribution forces
Institutional Systems Distributed in Space and Across Time
Power forces Reproduction forces
Meso-level forces Differentiation forces Corporate and Categoric Units Distributed in Space and Across Time Integration forces
Micro-level forces Demographic forces Status forces
Focused and Unfocused Encounters Distributed in Space and Across Time
Symbolic forces Transactional forces
Figure 2.
Levels of Social Reality
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
289
generating these structures are interconnected . Moving from macro to meso, institutional systems constrain the nature of corporate and categoric units, while the latter are the immediate structures from which institutional systems are constructed ; and going from meso to micro level of analysis, face-to-face interaction among individuals occurs in corporate and categoric units, whereas iterated interactions in encounters influence the nature of both corporate and categoric units . Thus, encounters reproduce or alter institutional structures by virtue of their embeddedness in corporate and categoric units ; conversely, institutional systems constrain face-to-face interaction in encounters via the corporate and categoric units of which they are comprised . Embeddedness is thus a key property of social reality, as Granovetter's (1985) famous article once reminded the discipline . Social action and interaction are always conducted within a larger sociocultural environment that constrains the
Table 1 .
Definitions of Generic Social Forces Macro-level Forces
Population :
Absolute number of individuals and the rate of growth in the size of a population . Power: Consolidation of power among its four fundamental bases--coercion, administration, symbols, material incentives-and the centralization of power on any or along all of the four bases . Production :
Distribution : Reproduction :
Technology, physical and human capital, property systems and entrepreneurship for the gathering of natural resources and their conversion into commodities as well as the necessary services for such gathering and conversion . Infrastructures to move people, resources, and information as well as exchange systems to distribute resources and information . Replication and replacement of members of a population . Meso-level Forces
Differentiation :
Integration :
Formation of different corporate structures in space and over time and formation of different categoric distinctions among members of a population . Boundary maintenance as well as internal and external ordering of relations within and between corporate and categoric units .
Micro-level Forces Demographic : Status :
Symbolic :
Transactional :
Number and categories of individuals co-present . Differentiation of power and authority, prestige and honor, and diffuse status characteristics among individuals co-present as well as the density of individuals co-present . Norms, values, and beliefs invoked or created among co-present individuals who normatize encounters with respect to rules of (a) communication, (b) framing, (c) rituals, (d) categories, and (e) feelings . Need states of individuals for (a) self-confirmation, (b) positive exchange payoffs, (c) predictability and trust, (d) intersubjectivity, and (e) group inclusion .
290
JONATHAN H . TURNER
dynamics of action and interaction . For my purposes in this analysis, I visualize encounters as episodes of face-to-face interaction that are, to varying degrees, constrained by the structure of corporate units or by the social distinctions imposed by categoric units, or both, because it is rather rare for individuals to interact outside the purview of either corporate or categoric units . Even when an interaction occurs outside of a corporate unit structure, categoric distinctions are almost always operative, defining the characteristics of the participants to the encounter . It is in this sense that an encounter is embedded in meso structures and the forces that drive the formation of such structures . In turn, corporate and categoric units are embedded in institutional systems that have been formed in response to the forces of the macro level ; and by extension, encounters are also embedded in these institutional systems since the blueprint rules of institutional systems constrain the structure of corporate and categoric units and, hence, the encounters embedded in these units . The theoretical task is now to be more specific and explain how the fact of embeddedness can help us develop generalizations about how macro and micro forces shape the flow of face-to-face interaction . In Figure 2, the left column denotes the forces generating the structures delineated in Figure 1, and Table 1 offers brief definitions of these forces . Those forces operating at the micro level will be emphasized, although their embeddedness in meso-and macro-level structures affects their operation . Obviously, these forces look rather familiar but they are nonetheless the generic forces that form institutional systems, corporate units, categoric units, and encounters . That is, these forces drive the formation and operation of different types of social structures . We are not used to visualizing these phenomena in quite this way, but once we think of these well-studied social processes as "driving forces," we shift slightly our vision of social reality . For example, differentiation and integration drive the formation level of corporate and categoric units ; and these are forces that interact with the macro-level forces to generate varying types of corporate and categoric units . Similarly, forces at the micro level drive the nature of interaction and, at the same time, interact with differentiation and integration forces operating at the meso level . At the micro level, macro forces determine the structures of societal systems but interact with differentiation and integration forces that form corporate and categoric units . This may initially seem like "old wine in new bottles," which is a fair assessment, but these new bottles give us a different refraction on reality . For the purposes of this paper, I cannot explain in great detail interconnections among these forces . But my general vision is this : institutional systems provide blueprints for the production of corporate and categoric units which, in turn, circumscribe the properties of encounters ; conversely, interaction in encounters reproduces or changes corporate and categoric units which reproduce or change institutional systems . Again, there is nothing that is radically new here ; the utility of this outline resides in what it allows us to do .
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
291
Thus, in trying to explain the dynamics of encounters, we must stay attuned to the independent effects of micro-level forces as they drive the encounter . At the same time, we must recognize that these micro-level forces interact with differentiation and integration forces as they form corporate categoric units which, in turn, reflect blueprints of institutional systems as they are driven by macro-level forces of population, production, power, distribution, and reproduction .
ENCOUNTERS As is well known, Goffman distinguished between focused and unfocused encounters . I will emphasize focused encounters where "people effectively agree to sustain for a time a single focus of cognitive and visual attention" (Goffman 1961), although my analyses can also explain unfocused encounters . In Goffman's analysis, focused encounters reveal eye-to-eye contact, mutual and preferential openness to verbal communication, heightened mutual relevance of acts, ecological huddling maximizing mutual perception and monitoring, emergent "we feelings," ritual and ceremonial punctuation of openings, closings, entrances and exits, and procedures for corrective compensation for deviant acts . Goffman (1983) was rather vague on the embeddedness of encounters, seeing them as lodged in a "gathering" where people are assembled in space with gatherings being further lodged within a more inclusive unit, the "social occasion," or larger undertaking sustained by fixed equipment, distinctive ethos and emotional structure, program and agenda, and preestablished sequencings of activities . Figures 1 and 2 are compatible with Goffman's position but add additional conceptual refinements . Most focused encounters occur within corporate units and under the influence of categoric distinctions, which, in turn, are part of a more encompassing institutional system . However, although I adopt many ideas from Goffman's analysis, my goal in this paper is twofold : (1) to reconceptualize the focused encounter, per se, and (2) to provide more detail on the embeddedness of focused encounters . The Embedding of Encounters in Corporate and Categoric Units
Before exploring in detail the forces driving a focused encounter, we should consider the properties of the meso-level structures in which encounters are generally embedded . These properties constrain the forces-demographic, status, symbolic, and transactional-which guide the flow of face-to-face interaction . Key Properties of Corporate Units I see five interrelated properties of corporate units as particularly important : (1) size of unit, (2) integrity of its external boundaries differentiating it from other
2 92
JONATHAN H . TURNER
corporate units and partitions into subunits within these boundaries, (3) formality of structure, (4) explicitness of the horizontal division of labor, and (5) explicitness of the vertical division of labor . Corporate units vary along all these dimensions, and they reveal diverse configurations among them . Yet, the first property-size-exerts the most important effects on the others . Large size will generally increase the visibility of external boundaries (e .g ., physical barriers) and internal partitions (e .g ., subgroups and cliques), formality of structure, horizontal and vertical divisions of labor . This correlation is not perfect, however, since a large business and a big city (both corporate units) will reveal very different profiles with respect to these properties . In contrast, small size is generally correlated with less pronounced boundaries and partitions, less formality, and less explicit divisions of labor (as is often the case with a group) . There are, of course, only rough correlations ; and so, we should concentrate on the properties themselves . Depending upon the configuration of properties, the structure of corporate units will vary, and so will the dynamics of encounters that are, to varying degrees, embedded in these structures . Key Properties of Categoric Units
Like corporate units, I see five key properties of categoric units : (1) homogeneity or heterogeneity of the categoric units to which individuals in an encounter belong (Blau 1994), (2) discreteness or clarity of the categories that distinguish individuals, (3) inequalities or rank-ordering of categoric distinctions, (4) correlation among, or superimposition of, membership in categoric units, and (5) correlation of categoric units with the structure of corporate units . These properties are less correlated than those of corporate units, and so, let me briefly enumerate each . An encounter with all members of the same category (e .g ., all white males) will have very different dynamics than one where heterogeneity prevails (e .g ., males and females); and in general, the greater the heterogeneity, the more individuals will have to work at sustaining the focus and boundaries of the encounter. The clarity of categories is also crucial ; categories that fade into each other pose different interpersonal challenges for participants in an encounter than those which are discrete (e .g ., male versus female or white versus black) . Categories are often rank-ordered, and the greater the rank differences among individuals in an encounter, the more strained is the interaction and the more individuals, especially low-ranking ones, will seek to limit interaction and, if possible, leave the encounter. Membership in categoric units is often correlated (e .g ., white, male, rich) ; and this kind of superimposition magnifies and accelerates the effects of homogeneity/heterogeneity and ranking . Finally, categoric units are, to widely varying degrees, structured by corporate units . When categories reflect positions in corporate units (e .g ., managerial executive, or blue-collar worker), the effects of corporate structures on individuals in an encounter is magnified . Conversely, categoric
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
293
distinctions among individuals in an encounter that are not tied to membership in corporate units will influence the flow of interaction primarily in terms of the other properties of categoric units-homogeneity/heterogeneity, clarity, rank ordering, and superimposition . These generalizations are only rough and approximate, because they are not tied to the forces operating at the micro level of analysis . An encounter is constrained by these properties of corporate and categoric units because the latter load the values for micro-level forces-that is, demographic, status, symbolic, and transactional-that drive the flow of face-to-face interaction . My goal is to develop more refined generalizations (summarized in the appendices), but to do so, it is necessary to examine micro social universe in more detail . The Flow of Interaction in Encounters
Demographic Forces The two most critical aspects in the demography of an encounter are (1) the number of individuals co-present and (2) their diversity (Collins 1975) . Large numbers of co-present individuals will reduce the values for many of the key variables defining an encounter : single visual and focus of attention, eye-to-eye ecological huddle, "we" feeling, and ritual punctuations (Noah 1998) . Moreover, as the number of individuals co-present increases, segmentation as well as differentiation of encounters are ever-more likely as individuals seek to maintain focus and boundaries by breaking off to form a smaller encounter . At the same time, multiple encounters in a space will often lead to migrations from encounter to encounter (the extreme case being a cocktail party), which reduces the stability of all encounters . The degree to which an encounter, or set of encounters, is embedded in the structure of corporate units is a crucial consideration . This structure can limit fluidity of encounters by providing a common focus for all participants (in line with the culture, structure, and goals of the corporate unit) ; and this structure can limit both segmentation and differentiation of encounters and migrations across encounters . Conversely, if a growing encounter is not tied to the structure of a corporate unit, then increases in the numbers co-present are more likely to cause segmentation/differentiation and migration which, in turn, reduce the stability and focus of encounters . In general, the larger, the more formal, clearly bounded and partitioned, and the more explicit the division of labor in a corporate unit, the more likely are encounters to sustain focus even as the size of encounters grows, and to limit migration to encounters related to the work goals of the corporate unit . The diversity of individuals present in the encounter alters the dynamics of the encounter dramatically . The diversity can follow from the division of labor in a corporate unit or it can be based on membership in broader categoric units, or
294
JONATHAN H . TURNER
both . In either case, diverse individuals must expend more interpersonal energy and effort, typically through ritual activities, to sustain the focus of attention and the feeling, and in general, the less homogeneous individuals in an encounter, the more the other forces in the encounter-status, symbolic, and transactional will organize the flow of interaction-and the more individuals will have to work at sustaining the encounter . The more categoric membership is tied to the division of labor in corporate units, however, the less pronounced these tendencies than is the case when categoric membership is disconnected from corporate units . Moreover, the more disconnected from corporate units and the more heterogeneous, and discrete, rank-ordered, and correlated are categoric distinctions among members in an encounter, the more activated are status, symbolic, and transactional forces, and the more individuals will need to expend effort in maintaining the focus of the encounter . In Appendix A I have stated somewhat more formally the hypotheses on demographic forces . Status Forces At the micro level, status forces revolve around (1) the distribution of positional power and/or authority, (2) the distribution of positional prestige and honor, (3) the density of connections among positions, and (4) the distribution of diffuse status characteristics (Webster and Foschi 1988) . 1 While there are no clear data that bear on the point, I would argue that there is a moderate inverse relationship between the salience of diffuse status characteristics, on the one side, and positional power/authority and prestige in corporate units, on the other side . The structure of authority and prestige in corporate units obviously does not eliminate the effects of diffuse status characteristics ; if such were the case, gender and ethnic discrimination in organizations would not exist . But I would hypothesize that the salience of diffuse status characteristics is reduced somewhat as the structure of a corporate unit becomes more formal and hierarchical . My reasoning in drawing this conclusion is that formality and hierarchy will order the assemblage of encounters and the flow of interaction within these encounters, leading participants in such encounters to use the allocation of authority and prestige by the structure of the corporate unit to guide the flow of interaction . Of course, the more an informal system emerges alongside the formal system, the less pronounced this effect, and the more likely are diffuse status characteristics to increase in salience in such encounters ; and moreover, the more likely are these effects in informal situations to spill over into encounters ordered by the formal structure of the corporate unit. Thus, in general, the more an encounter is embedded in a corporate structure and the more formal/hierarchical is the division of labor in this corporate unit, the more operative are differences in formally allocated power/authority and prestige/honor and the less salient are outside diffuse status characteristics . In contrast, the less an encounter is embedded in a corporate unit, the more relevant are categoric distinctions, and, as a consequence, the more salient are diffuse sta-
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
295
tus characteristics in determining the distribution of power and prestige . Moreover, if categoric distinctions are unambiguous or discrete (e .g ., male, female) rank-ordered (along some evaluative scale), and correlated with each other (such that rank on one categoric distinction predicts rank on another), the power of categoric units increases . This conclusion follows loosely from expectation states research on the combining of different status characteristics (e .g ., Wagner and Berger 1993, pp . 31-37 ; Berger, Wagner, and Zelditch 1989 ; Berger and Zelditch 1998, pp. 207-228) . My argument simply extends this finding by asserting that when this combining is facilitated by the clarity and ranking of categoric distinctions, combining does not need to "average" different characteristics (Berger and Fisek 1974) ; rather, when characteristics of actors in various categoric units are highly correlated, the combining process is additive and cumulative, increasing the effect of each characteristic and thereby making diffuse status characteristics all the more salient for interaction in an encounter . Density or the degree of connectedness among positions is always an important property of a social structure, and as a consequence, density influences status processes in encounters . High levels of density among the positions of individuals in an encounter will increase the salience of all status characteristics, both positional authority/prestige and diffuse status characteristics as well as prestige/authority generated in informal relations outside the formal power/authority and prestige structure of a corporate unit . Yet, when encounters are embedded in corporate units revealing a formal and hierarchical structure, the effects of density vary depending on the location of those in an encounter within the overall structure of the corporate unit . When actors come from diverse positions in the hierarchy, density will be low and, as a consequence, the formal positional authority and prestige systems will be more operative than diffuse status characteristics or informally generated prestige/authority . My reasoning is that when individuals do not interact consistently or informally (as is generally the case when their positions reveal low density), formal authority and prestige are, if only by default of alternative bases for assigning status, the more salient . This conclusion needs to be qualified by considerations of structural equivalence, or what Sailer has termed "regular equivalence" (My use of the term "structural equivalence" deviates from H . White et al . [1976] and conforms to Sailer's [ 1978] arguments on "regular equivalence .") When individuals hold similar positions in a corporate unit, they reveal similarities in orientations and behaviors, even when their positions are not connected . Thus, even under conditions of low density, individuals in structurally equivalent positions will be similar in orientation and behavior and, as a result, I would argue that they will increase the use of diffuse status characteristics in ordering the flow of the encounter . In a sense, their positional authority and prestige are neutralized by equivalence (even if they hold somewhat different titles), opening the door for the use of other status characteristics .
2 96
JONATHAN H . TURNER
A final consideration in examining the effects of density on encounters are situations of those who are located at similar positions within a corporate structure and who also have relatively high-density networks of ties . Such individuals will also tend to be similar ; and since there will be relatively modest differences in their positional authority and prestige, diffuse status characteristics and informally generated prestige and authority will become ever more salient in ordering interactions in encounters . For once formal authority and prestige recede as defining characteristics of individuals, the door is opened for other status considerations to take hold ; and such is especially likely to be the case when individuals have high-density ties and, hence, interact in encounters rather frequently . Turning to the embeddedness of encounters in categoric units, the less categoric distinctions in an encounter correspond to the formal positional authority and prestige in the corporate unit, the more diffuse status characteristics derived from membership in categoric units will be operative in an encounter . Moreover, once the capacity of the formal structure of the corporate unit to define status in an encounter is weakened, informally generated prestige and authority are increasingly likely to influence the flow of interaction in an encounter; and such informal allocations of prestige and authority will follow the predictions of status expectation and status generalization research (e .g ., Webster and Foschi 1988) and will be assigned on the basis of the evaluations of diffuse status characteristics (Wagner and Berger 1993, p . 28) . I would add a further hypothesis that, again, follows from expectations research on the combining of status characteristics . When categoric distinctions are discrete, unambiguous, rank-ordered, and correlated with each other, the more operative will be diffuse status characteristics, for the same reasons argued above . For when individuals do not need to average diverse, somewhat ambiguous, graduated, and uncorrelated status characteristics, categoric units have an additive and cumulative effect on status processes, thereby increasing their influence on the interactions in an encounter. When corporate units reveal horizontal differentiation of positions, the lack of hierarchy (and, generally, formality as well) will increase the salience of categoric distinctions in encounters . Without a hierarchy to impose positional authority and prestige, the more likely are diffuse status characteristics and informally generated prestige and authority become operative, in accordance with the dynamics examined above . A last dynamic on the embeddedness of encounters in categoric units is the fact that membership in a corporate unit often becomes a categoric distinction . For example, when a professor interacts with a business person, their respective memberships in corporate units become categoric distinctions that influence the flow of interaction . The more corporate unit affiliation becomes a categoric distinction in an encounter, the more operative are status processes examined in expectation states research . That is, the relative evaluation of corporate units in terms of prestige and power defines the rank of categoric distinctions that are derived by affil-
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
297
iation with a corporate unit, and the more likely will these distinctions operate like diffuse status characteristics in an encounter . In Appendix B these complex relationships between status forces, on the one hand, and their embeddedness in corporate and categoric units, on the other, are stated more formally . Symbolic Forces As Goffman (1967) emphasized in his adaptation of Durkheim's (1947 [1912]) sociology to encounters, culture exerts considerable influence on the flow of faceto-face interaction . Status and demographic forces circumscribe which systems of symbols are salient in an encounter;2 and so, the embeddedness of an encounter in social structures will activate in the minds of individuals cultural symbols relevant to the encounter . In examining symbolic forces in encounters, we are addressing the question of how culture influences the flow of face-to-face interaction . There have, of course, been many efforts to make this macro-to-micro connection . For example, Weber's (1958 [1904/05]) account of Protestantism and the rise of capitalism represents an early effort ; Durkheim's (1912) analysis of ritual as it reinforces commitments to the collective conscious is another. In mid-century, Parsons's (1951) discussion of how value orientations are translated into modes of action is yet another, as his portrayal of a cybernetic hierarchy of control (Parsons 1966) . Structuralist perspectives examining culture have also tried to connect the mechanisms by which the broader culture becomes part of individuals' actions and interactions (e .g ., Wuthnow 1987 ; Bourdieu 1984 ; Giddens 1984) . Some branches of symbolic interactionism (e .g ., Stryker 1980 ; Turner 1968) have also grappled with how culture shapes the symbols that will guide interaction . And, the expectation states program has similarly sought to demonstrate how broader value orientations are involved in legitimating the status order (Ridgeway and Berger 1986) . Thus, there is no lack of effort to engage the problem, and my efforts simply try to combine these various approaches into a more robust conceptualization . This effort begins with the recognition that there is a broader societal culture (often connected to the culture of other societies or systems of societies) . This culture can be conceptualized as a storehouse of symbol systems that can be drawn upon in order to construct social structures, and conversely, this storehouse is restocked and its contents altered by the construction and reconstruction of social structures . From this perspective, the most generic structural units-institutional domains, corporate units, and categoric units-carry systems of symbols, or culture . Yet, social structures selectively carry systems of culture, adopting, adapting, and changing culture . When individuals make symbols available to an encounter, they do so by becoming cognizant of the structural units within which an encounter is lodged and, then, by selecting what they perceive as the most relevant cultural contents from institutional domains, corporate units, and categoric units . At times, of course, individuals do not perceive the relevant structural units,
JONATHAN H . TURNER
298
Culture of Societal Systems Systems of value orientations Systems of technology Systems of texts 1 Culture of Ins1itutiond Systems Application and/or development of value orientations for specific institutional domains Translations of value orientations into ideologies and beliefs for specific institutional domains Utilization and development of technolog'res for specific institutional domains Adoption and development of texts for specific institutional domains Development of generalized norms for specific institutional domains
Culture of Corporate Units Application of institutional value orientations or development of new orientations
Culture of Categoric Units Definitions of social categories not directly associated with corporate units or institutional systems
Application of institutional beliefs and/or development of new ones
Definitions of social categories associated with corporate units
Application of institutional rule systems in specifying positional authority/prestige, connections among positions, and salience of varying status characteristics
Definitions of social categories associated with institutional domains Expectations for orientations and behaviors of members in various social categories
Application institutional technologies and/or development of new ones for achieving corporate unit goals
Evaluation of social categories in terms of value orientations
Application of institutional texts and/or development of new ones
Nortnatizing of Encounter
Figure 3 .
Dimensions of Culture
or find the constraints of such units bothersome, leading them to generate new cultural systems in an encounter . But creating new culture involves considerable interpersonal effort, often making the costs of doing so greater than the costs of following the constraints imposed by existing structures . "Normatizing" is the term I use to denote this process of selecting cultural contents from the structural
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
299
units within which an encounter is embedded, or creating new systems of symbols to guide the flow of interaction . As the arrows in the Figure 3 emphasize, the broader culture works its way down to the encounter via institutional systems, corporate units, and categoric units . As individuals form an encounter, they do so with the context of these structural units and the culture that they carry . This is not to say, however, that the flow of an encounter cannot create its own culture, or even counterculture, but it does say that most encounters begin with awareness, if only implicitly, of structural and cultural contexts and that the culture of this context is invoked and used . The culture of institutional systems and corporate units is most likely to be used when an encounter is lodged in a corporate unit that is embedded in an institutional system and when the structure of the corporate unit is formal and hierarchical with an explicit division of labor . Under these conditions, the status structure of the corporate unit is highly salient as is the culture associated with the distribution of positions . Even when a counterculture emerges within such units, it is reaction against the culture of the corporate unit and perhaps the broader institutional system in which the corporate unit is embedded-thus indicating that the culture of the institutional domain and corporate units is still salient . The culture of categoric units, also constrains the normatizing process . The more clear cut, discrete, rank-ordered (in terms of evaluative criteria) categoric units, the greater are their effects on an encounter ; and the more these categoric units are correlated with the structure of corporate units, the greater are the effects of categoric units . However, when encounters occur outside the corporate units or are only weakly embedded in such units, the culture of the categoric unit increases relative to corporate units or institutional systems, and as a result, the normatizing process will be driven by the categoric unit membership ; and the more clarity, discreteness, and differential evaluation of the social categories, the greater will be the power of categoric units . My reasoning here is simply that without the structure of corporate units to impose their culture, individuals will initially seek some other basis for finding culture ; by default, they will use definitions of social categories, at least initially . And as expectations research has documented, these kinds of categories can operate as diffuse status characteristics in ways that assign prestige and authority, especially if the encounter is formed to accomplish some defined task (Wagner and Berger 1993) . I would hypothesize, however, that the power of social categories decreases with less instrumental but frequently formed encounters ; and the more enduring are these non-instrumental encounters, the less salient will be membership in categoric units . The logic of this hypothesis follows from a number of classic studies on prejudice and discrimination documents whereby rates of interaction reduce prejudice which, I believe, is another way of saying that the salience of differentially evaluated social categories declines with frequent encounters among those in different categoric units . These relationships between cultural systems and embeddedness are summarized more formally in Appendix C .
3 00
JONATHAN H . TURNER
Thus, when an encounter occurs, much of the sorting of relevant cultural content has already been accomplished by simple incumbency in an institutional domain and the corporate and categoric units comprising this domain . For any new encounter, then, vast portions of individuals' inventories of norms have been pre-sorted, greatly reducing the range of symbolic content that must be evoked . Still, I have not specified in any detail just what I mean by normatizing, and so, let me now turn to a more detailed analyses . Sociologists often conceptualize norms as a noun, as a set of expectations associated with a position within a social structure . This emphasis is not entirely misplaced, since humans do carry vast inventories of norms in their brains but the process of selecting and applying norms is more active (Turner 1988, 1989, 1996, 1997) . It is a process of normatizing in which the cultural symbol system that will guide the flow of interaction in an encounter are selected, generally implicitly, and used to formulate expectations for self and others . At times, this process can involve the creation of new expectations, but more typically, the relevant cultural symbols can be found in individuals' stocks of knowledge, to use Alfred Schutz's (1967 [1932]) phrase, and adopted to new contingencies . I see normatizing as a master process at the micro level of reality because it includes developing expectations along at least five dimensions : 1.
2.
3.
4.
Rules of Communication . For embedded encounters, there are always rules of communication with respect to (a) the forms of talk, (b) the forms of nonverbal gesturing, (c) the forms of reciprocal talk and nonverbal gesturing, and (d) the forms of verbal and nonverbal communication in negotiating over resources . Framing . In all encounters individuals establish expectations for what is to be included and excluded (Goffman 1974 ; Turner 1988) . These rules of framing select (a) the appropriate frames for an encounter, (b) the appropriate way to key and rekey (i .e ., establish and change) frames, and (c) the appropriate procedures for laminating frames (i.e ., building up several layers of frames within frames) . Ritualizing. In all encounters individuals use rituals, or stereotyped sequences of talk and nonverbal gesturing to structure the flow of interaction (Goffman 1967), and as they do so, they establish expectations for (a) the appropriate repertoire of rituals to be used in an encounter, (b) the appropriate type gestural sequences to be employed, and (c) the appropriate gestures for opening, closing, forming, repairing, and framing the flow of interaction . Categorizing . In all encounters individuals invoke rules that define the nature of the situation, others, and self. Categorizing involves invoking expectations along several dimensions : (a) expectations for self and others in a situation, as defined by categoric units ; (b) expectations associated with basic types of situations (Goffman 1967 ; Collins 1975) as social,
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
301
work-practical, and ceremonial, and (c) expectations for level of intimacy with others as intimates, persons, or representatives of a category (Turner 1988) . 5 . Feeling . In all encounters individuals invoke "feeling" and "display" rules in an encounter (Hochschild 1979) . These rules reflect a broader "blueprint rules" of culture (Ridgeway 1982, 1994) as these dictate an "emotion culture" (Hochschild 1979) and, for various institutional domains, these are translated into "emotional ideologies ." Feeling and display rules indicate (a) the amount of appropriate emotion to be felt in a situation, (b) the direction, whether positive or negative, as well as the duration of the emotions
Culture of Societal Systems 1 Culture of Institutional Systems
Culture of Corporate Units
Culture of Categoric Units
The Culture of the Encounter The Dynamics of Normatizing
Categorizing
- Ritualizing Framing Crunication ~- Feelings
Figure 4 .
Normatizing an Encounter
. .a-
302
JONATHAN H . TURNER
to be experienced, and (c) the nature, intensity, and style of expressive behavior to be displayed . Figure 4 summarizes in broad contours my views on the dynamics of normatizing . Although each dimension of normatizing affects all others, some causal paths are more important than others . The sequence and arrows in Figure 4 delineate my sense for how normatizing operates . Individuals initially categorize situations, and much of this categorization is dictated by the embeddedness of encounters in the corporate and categoric units of various institutional systems . Once individuals have some sense for the categories of self and others, for the relative amounts of work-practical, social, or ceremonial content of the situation, and for the level of intimacy to be achieved, it becomes much easier to frame the encounter, to agree upon forms of verbal and nonverbal communication, and to decide upon the emotions to be experienced and expressed . If a situation is not readily amenable to categorization, however, then expectations for communication, rituals, and frames, and feelings will be somewhat ambiguous, forcing individuals to engage in verbal and nonverbal communication to establish frames and appropriate rituals . As frames are created, then it becomes ever more possible to categorize the situation, and as this occurs, other dimensions of normatizing all become more readily achieved . As the arrows indicate, communication, framing, and ritualizing form one cluster of causal paths. When expectations for forms of communication are established, framing and the ritual acts by which frames are keyed and rekeyed become much more readily established ; and as rituals generate clear-cut expectations for frames, expectations for forms of communication become unambiguous . Another path is among categorizing, framing, ritualizing, and feelings . When categories are understood, frames and the expectations for rituals used to key and rekey frames are more effective in establishing expectations for experiencing and expressing emotions . Intersecting this set of causal paths is the process of communication . When expectations for forms of talk and nonverbal gesturing are understood, expectations for frames, rituals, and feelings become more evident to individuals ; and reciprocally, as expectations for frames, rituals, and feelings are understood, expectations for forms of verbal and nonverbal gesturing are more clear-cut. These normatizing dynamics generate a culture for an encounter, but as is also communicated in Figure 4, this culture is often very much circumscribed by the culture of corporate and categoric units, as well as the institutional system in which these are embedded. When an encounter is embedded in corporate or categoric units, or both, the dynamics of normatizing are simplified . Individuals more readily categorize, and as they do so, expectations for forms of verbal and nonverbal communication and for framing are less ambiguous, enabling individuals to use rituals and to calibrate the appropriate feelings more easily . And as these feed off of each other, and back on each other, normatization is enhanced and the
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
303
encounter flows smoothly . At the same time, the culture and structure of corporate and categoric units in which the encounter is embedded are reinforced and reproduced. Appendix D summarizes some of the more important hypotheses on normatizing in embedded encounters are summarized. Transactional Dynamics
Interaction is always guided by the needs of individuals ; and while many of these are idiosyncratic to the individuals involved or the unique features of the interaction, there are, I believe (Turner 1987, 1988, 1994, 1999), more fundamental, generic, and pan-situational needs that always drive the flow of face-to-face interaction . I term these "transactional needs" because they are activated by (1) co-presence and (2) interaction in an encounter . At least five of these transactional needs are : (1) needs for self-confirmation, (2) needs for profitable exchange payoffs, (3) needs for predictability and trust, (4) needs for a sense of intersubjectivity, and (5) needs for group inclusion . Just how these need states manifest themselves is constrained by demographic, status, and symbolic forces, but there is also a reciprocal causal effect in that these need states (a) influence individuals' willingness to be co-present as well as their migrations to and from encounters, (b) shape the flow of status-organizing processes, and (c) mobilize individuals to normatize an encounter and, thereby, establish expectations for categories, communication, frames, rituals, and feelings that are crucial to the reproduction of structure and culture . Need states activate emotions, and as a consequence, they represent a critical force in connecting individuals to social structures . Encounters are viable when need states are met, because when needs are fulfilled, individuals experience positive emotions and are more likely to view self and others more favorably and, as a result, they are more likely to become committed to sustaining the flow of interaction and, by extension, the larger social structures in which an encounter is nested (Lawler 1992, 1997) . In contrast, when individuals experience negative emotions they are less likely to view self and others favorably, and as a consequence, they are less likely to become committed to sustaining the interaction . Negative emotions will, instead, push individuals to leave the encounter or, if they cannot leave, to breach feeling rules in ways that disrupt the flow of interaction and force communication, frames, and rituals into a constant repair mode-none of which promote viable encounters, nor the embeddedness of encounters . When need states cannot be met, then, the encounter will be strained, causing it to break up or causing individuals to re-normatize the encounter, often in ways that loosen its embeddedness in structural units and associated culture, or in ways that change the more inclusive structure and culture . If such disembedding of encounters is frequent and widespread across many different encounters, then micro-level forces begin to alter meso-level structures and, if the later are changed, macro-level institutional systems as well . These general principles about
304
JONATHAN H . TURNER
transactional needs and embeddedness are summarized more formally in Appendix E . To fully explicate the details of these relationships, however, we must examine each of the five transactional need in more detail . Self-confirmation . Individuals have a conception of themselves in all situations . These meanings about self carry expectations for persons along two fronts : (1) how they should behave, given the demographic and sociocultural constraints on the encounter and (2) how they should be treated by others in varying positions . When these expectations are met, self is confirmed ; and individuals feel positive emotions such as pleasure, happiness, and pride . When these expectations are exceeded, these positive emotions become more intense . Conversely, when self is not confirmed, more negative emotions will be aroused . The nature and intensity of both positive and negative emotions vary with attribution processes and cultural contexts (Turner 1999) . When individuals believe that their own competent behaviors have caused others to confirm their self, they will experience pride ; and conversely, when individuals sense that their own incompetence in an interaction is the source of their failure to experience confirming responses from others, they will experience shame . As Lewis (1971) and Scheff (1988, 1990) have emphasized in their related theories, individuals who experience shame consistently in one encounter or across sets of encounters will often have developed tendencies to bypass or repress this shame, and as a consequence, they will become depressed in these encounters and their modal level of emotional energy will decline . Yet, the repression is rarely complete, and such individuals will experience outbursts of anger as a release for repressed feelings of shame, but these outbursts only work to emphasize the incompetence of the individual . Moreover, these outbursts will not only exacerbate shame, they will generally activate guilt over having breached feeling rules at having forced communication and rituals into a repair mode . Guilt operates in similar ways to shame, except that the criterion of evaluation by the individual is not competence or incompetence but the ability to meet the moral expectations contained in the values, beliefs, and ideologies that apply to an encounter. The more normatized an encounter is, the more these moral expectations are understood . When individuals are able to abide by these expectations or to exceed them, they experience pride. Conversely, when they fail to meet these expectations they will experience guilt . And, like shame, repressed or bypassed guilt will cause depression and lowered emotional energy in an encounter or in all encounters if the experience of guilt has been chronic . Yet, like shame, sporadic emotional outbursts will come through the wall of repression, exceeding feeling rules and forcing interaction into a repair mode, and as a consequence, individuals will experience even more guilt for having disrupted the moral codes guiding an encounter. Individuals do not always make self attributions . There is almost always an external attribution process operating in encounters . When individuals perceive
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
305
that the qualities and behaviors of others are primarily responsible for the experience of self-confirmation, they will mobilize positive emotions (e .g ., liking, respect) toward these others . In contrast, when others (rather than self) are blamed for the failure to receive confirming responses, an individual will arouse anger toward these others . When this anger goes from low-intensity states (e .g ., annoyance) to higher-intensity states (e .g ., hate, rage), feeling rules will be breached, forcing the interaction into a repair mode . At times, individuals may experience guilt at having violated feeling rules, but more typically they sustain their perception that others are responsible for their failure to receive confirming responses . As a result, the interaction will burst apart, or if people cannot leave, the encounter will have to be re-normatized or remain in a chronic state of repair . Individuals also make external attributions to situations in which the encounter is embedded ; and when an encounter is embedded in corporate and categoric units, they will either increase or decrease their positive sentiments toward, and commitments to, these units . When individuals perceive that their receipt of confirming responses is due to the structure in which the encounter is lodged, they will experience positive emotions toward others who provided these confirming responses, but these positive emotions will be less intense than when the attribution is made to others alone . Instead, they will develop more intense positive sentiments to the situation (e .g ., gratitude, happiness, pleasure) and will be more likely to develop commitments to the corporate and categoric units in which the encounter is embedded . As such commitments emerge, the power of corporate and categoric units increases, and the normatization of the encounter will follow the cultural blueprints of these units . Thus, needs to confirm self are a critical dynamic in embedded encounters . The more self is confirmed, the more likely are normatizing processes to operate smoothly, and, by extension, the more likely are the structures in which an encounter is embedded to be reproduced . For when self is confirmed, forms of talk and discourse will seem proper ; frames will be accepted ; rituals will guide the interactional flow ; categories will be seen as appropriate ; and feeling rules will be followed . And reciprocally, when forms of talk, frames, rituals, categories, and feeling rules are accepted, individuals are more likely to understand how to behave in ways that elicit confirming responses for self . The more self is disconfirmed, however, the more likely is the encounter to be breached and de-normatized . For when self is not confirmed, talk shifts to forms expressing anger, feeling rules are more likely to be breached, frames are difficult to sustain, rituals disproportionately focus on repairs rather than structuring the flow of interaction, and categories are called into question . As de-normatization occurs, the less likely are the structures in which the encounter is embedded to be supported ; and the greater is the number of individuals across all encounters who fail to have self confirmed, the ever-more difficult is the reproduction of social structures . These dynamic relationships between needs for self-confirmation and embeddedness are summarized formally in Appendix F .
306
JONATHAN H . TURNER
Exchange payoffs . In all encounters individuals seek to realize rewards that exceed the costs in seeking these rewards . One of the most valuable rewards in an encounter is, of course, confirmation of self ; and so, individuals are particularly attuned to extrinsic and intrinsic reinforcers that confirm self . Just what these reinforcers are, or can be, is determined by the structures and associated culture in which an encounter is embedded . In general, the more clearly an encounter is normatized, the more realistic are expectations for the kinds and amounts of resources available and, as a consequence, the more likely are individuals to adjust their costs and investments in proportion to expected payoffs . When expectations for categorization are understood, individuals will define the nature of payoffs (as related to work-practical, social, or ceremonial rewards, and as tied to intrinsic or extrinsic reinforcers for varying degrees of intimacy) ; in turn, expectations for forms of talk will be readily comprehended ; frames are more likely to define relevant resources and expectations for payoffs ; rituals will pace the flow of negotiations and payoffs ; and feeling rules will constrain the nature, direction, and intensity of affect that can be used to reward or punish others or that can be received from others . When payoffs are perceived to correspond to expenditures of resources (e .g ., energy, time, investment of self), individual experience positive emotions (Homans 1961) ; and when payoffs do not meet these expectations or compensate individuals for their expenditures, they become angry ; 3 and the greater this sense of injustice, the more feeling rules will be abridged and the more the encounter will be breached and break apart, or alternatively, the more individuals will seek re-normatized the encounter . As anger exceeds the limits of feeling rules, talk shifts to more emotional forms, frames become difficult to maintain, rituals are increasingly devoted to repairs, and categories lose their hold to define the nature and involvement of parties to the encounter . If large numbers of individuals across many diverse encounters experience anger as a consequence of perceived injustices, the more breaches and/or re-normatizing the encounter will fail to reproduce the structures and associated culture in which these encounters are embedded, and, hence, the greater the probability of change in the more inclusive structure . The basic relationship between exchange payoffs and embeddedness is summarized formally in Appendix G .
Predictability and trust . In all encounters individuals have needs for predictability because when other cannot be relied upon to behave as expected, confirmation of self and, more generally, exchange payoffs become problematic . For when predictability is problematic, not only does a fundamental need state go unmet, thereby increasing the costs of the interaction, but also individuals must incur additional costs to self (e.g ., vulnerability to non-confirmation), costs in expenditures of effort (e .g., heightened monitoring of others' responses), and costs associated with increased risks (e .g ., investing resources with uncertain
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
3 07
returns) . As a result, the probability of rewards exceeding costs declines which, in turn, will cause anger and other disassociative responses . But, more than just greater certainty of exchange payoffs is involved . There is, I believe, a more general need for what Anthony Giddens (1984) termed "ontological security" in which individuals perceive the social universe as more secure when the actions of others can be anticipated in all relevant ways, not just in terms of exchange payoffs . Individuals are risk aversive because they find the anxiety associated with ontological insecurity highly unpleasant . Related to Giddens's notion of ontological security is Erik Erikson's (1950) concept of "trust" which I translate to mean that others can be relied upon to meet their obligations in an encounter. Thus, individuals not only seek predictability in the responses of others, they also have needs for a more general and diffuse sense that others can be trusted to meet all expectations relevant to an encounter . All encounters are steeped in expectations about what self and others are to do, and these become defined as obligations for what others should and must do . These expectations will be more readily understood (1) when the demography, distributional authority and prestige, and salience of diffuse status characters are clear and (2) when the encounter is normatized . These two conditions are more likely to be met when an encounter is embedded in corporate and categoric units within institutional domains . When others cannot be trusted to meet their obligations, however, anxiety and ontological insecurity will increase, while at the same time, anxiety will impose high costs and, as a consequence, decrease profitability in exchanges ; and as profitability declines below expectations or rules of justice, anger increases . Lack of trust strains an encounter, making it less viable and encouraging individuals to leave and/or to de-normatize the encounter . Without a diffuse sense of trust and predictability in the behaviors of others, categories are difficult to sustain, forms of talk and discourse become uncertain, frames lose their clarity, rituals prepare for breaches, and negative emotions like anxiety and anger place pressure on feeling rules . And so, the less individuals' actions can be predicted and trusted, the less viable is normatization of the encounter and, by extension, the less will the encounters reproduce the culture and structure of the more inclusive system in which the encounter is embedded . And the greater the number of encounters revealing this character, the more likely are broader structures and associated cultural systems to change . These relationships between predictability/trust and embeddedness are summarized formally in Appendix H . Intersubjectivity . Alfred Schutz (1967 [19321) was the first to recognize that individuals need to sense that they are perceiving and experiencing a situation in a similar way, or if differently, in a manner that is explainable . The famous breaching experiments of early ethnomethodology (e .g ., Garfinkel 1967) almost always resulted in either anxiety or anger because individuals' respective sense, even if this sense was only illusionary, that they are experiencing the situation in similar ways was destroyed . Without this sense of intersubjectivity, individuals
3 08
JONATHAN H . TURNER
experience anxiety or, if the sense of intersubjectivity is suddenly disrupted, they experience anger as well ; and as a consequence, normatizing an interaction becomes highly problematic . Categories are subject to re-negotiation ; communication becomes stalled in renegotiations over the proper form of talk ; frames are broken or remain unclear; rituals are devoted to repairs of breaches rather than the structuring of interaction ; and feeling rules are strained as anxiety and anger are aroused to the point of further breaches in the interaction (which, in turn, makes categories hard to sustain, talk strained, framing difficult, and rituals biased toward repairs) . Conversely, normatizing greatly facilitates achieving intersubjectivity ; when expectations for categories, forms of talk, frames, rituals, and feeling rules are understood, it is easier for individuals to sustain a sense that they experience the encounter in similar ways . Furthermore, status forces also operate to generate intersubjectivity, in several ways . First, the distribution of positional authority and prestige, as well as diffuse status characteristics, provide ways to make "understandable" perceived or potential differences in perceptions and experiences of the encounter (e .g ., as the result of incumbency in different positions) . Second, the culture associated with the structures in which the encounter is embedded provides further symbolic guidelines for how to perceive and experience the situation, regardless of positional and status differences . And so, if an encounter is deeply embedded in clear corporate or categoric structures, intersubjectivity is easier to achieve and even more so as the structure and culture of these units constrain normatization . Yet, when individuals consistently fail to achieve intersubjectivity, they will experience anxiety over, and often anger toward, those corporate and categoric units, and they may seek to change these units . These relationships between intersubjectivity and embeddedness are summarized in Appendix I . Group inclusion . Individuals need to feel involved in the ongoing flow of interaction in an encounter . This sense of inclusion need not represent emersion or engrossment in the encounter or imply high solidarity with others ; rather, individuals simply need to sense that others will respond to them and that they can initiate talk without fear of negative sanctions . To the extent that this sense of group inclusion does not exist, individuals experience anxiety and varying intensities of anger (depending upon such variables as the degree to which exclusion is deliberate and explicit4) . The sense of inclusion is more readily achieved when the demography, the distribution of positional authority and prestige, and the salience of diffuse status characteristics are unambiguous. Moreover, when normatization of categories, talk, frames, rituals, and feelings has occurred, the more individuals will know how to respond to others, and, conversely, the more certain are they about how others will respond to them . As a result, individuals will feel included in the ongoing flow of interaction, and they will develop positive sentiments toward others in the encounter and toward the more inclusive corporate and categoric units in which the encounter is embedded . 5 But, if categories of individuals
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
309
are excluded, and their numbers are large, then their disaffection from, or anger toward, those who have excluded them increase the level of conflict, while decreasing the viability of encounters and the ability of encounters to reproduce social structures and attendant culture . These relationships between group inclusion and embeddedness are summarized in Appendix J .
CONCLUSION The propositions in Appendices A-J constitute a theory of embedded encounters . Each appendix summarizes the dynamics of embeddedness for the four basic forces operating at the micro level-demographic, status, symbolic, and transactional forces . All of the propositions are testable and can, therefore, be considered as plausible hypotheses for future research . Obviously, the theory is not parsimonious, but it is possible to consolidate principles, although at this preliminary stage, I prefer to keep the theory robust . Rather than perform this consideration, I will close with the issue of how sociology should theorize across levels of reality, emphasizing the relative ease of macro-to-micro analysis when compared to micro-to-macro . My view is that when one engages micro-to-macro theorizing, generalizations become highly probabilistic and often vague . Using my vocabulary, these generalizations look something like this : the less viable encounters, the more problematic is reproduction of corporate and categoric units and, by extension, institutional domains . As a metaphoric statement, this generalization is true, but it lacks conceptual details . More than sloppy or biased theorizing is involved here, I believe . There are ontological reasons for the relative clarity of top-down as opposed to bottom-up conceptualizations . Because the macro and meso are, ultimately, composed of micro encounters, there are many more encounters to analyze if we wish to engage in bottom-up theorizing . In contrast, we can perform top-down analysis on just one encounter and generate far more explanatory power than if we analyzed one encounter to explain the dynamics of corporate or categoric units . Encounters are embedded in macro and micro structures and culture, whereas institutions, categories, and corporate units are not embedded in any one encounter . As a result, we must always engage in conceptual aggregation when trying to explain how the dynamics of meso structures are influenced by their constituent encounters . And since encounters are short term, we must not only aggregate many encounters to understand large-scale structures, we must aggregate iterations of encounters over time . The end result is that micro-to-meso or micro-to-macro generalizations will be highly probabilistic and, as a result, often appear vague . Thus, theorizing about the micro-macro "gap" is, I contend, far easier when one moves from macro to meso, and then, from meso to micro. For the reverse, we need to use conceptual tools, like simulation methodologies to help in analysis of iterated aggregations of micro encounters . Conceptual and simulation work along
31 0
JONATHAN H . TURNER
these lines have already proven to be useful in demonstrating that micro-level theoretical principles and assumptions can indeed generate explanations of more macro-level outcomes (e .g ., Mayhew 1984 ; Noah 1998 ; Markovsky 1988, 1997, Ridgeway 1991, 1998 ; Fararo 1989 ; Fararo and Skvoretz 1986) . And so, there is a distinct possibility that sociology can develop two-way models-that is, topdown and bottom-up-of social organization . The propositions offered in Appendices A-J will, I hope, contribute to this enterprise .
APPENDIX A Demography and Embeddedness
I . The larger the number of individuals in an encounter and/or the greater their diversity, the more problematic is the maintenance of a common focus of attention and common mood, and hence, the greater is the ritual energy devoted to sustaining the boundaries of, and the flow interaction in, the encounter . A . The larger is the number of individuals in an encounter, the greater the likelihood that 1 . the encounter will segment or differentiate into smaller encounters ; 2 . the participants in the encounter will migrate to new encounters . B . The more diverse are the participants in an encounter, the more salient will status, symbolic, and transactional forces in the encounter become and the more they will guide efforts to sustain the encounter . II . The more an encounter is embedded in a corporate unit, and the more categoric distinctions are correlated with the division of labor in this corporate unit, the less powerful are the processes described in I and I-A . A . The more an encounter is embedded in a corporate unit, and the larger, more formal, and partitioned is the division of labor in this corporate unit, the greater is the likelihood that 1 . the goals for the division of labor will sustain the focus of attention, especially when this division of labor assigns leadership positions ; 2 . the division of labor will limit migration and formation of new encounters . B . The more categoric units correspond to the division of labor in corporate units, the more pronounced are the effects in II-A(1), II-A(2), and the greater is the likelihood that 1 . the division of labor within the corporate unit will direct the operation of status, symbolic, and transactional forces ;
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
2.
311
the salience of outside status, symbolic, and transactional forces will decrease .
APPENDIX B Status and Embeddedness
I . The more the distribution of positional power/authority and prestige is determined by the structure of a corporate unit, and the more formal and hierarchical the structure of this unit, the less salient are diffuse status characteristics in most encounters ; and conversely, the less encounters are constrained by the formal structure of corporate units, and the more viable are informal systems of encounters within this structure, the more salient are diffuse status characteristics in all encounters . II . The more dense are the ties among positions in an encounter, the greater are the effects of all status characteristics, both positional power/authority and prestige as well as diffuse status characteristics . A . The more formal and hierarchical the structure of a corporate unit, the less dense are social ties across the entire organization, thereby increasing the likelihood that 1 . encounters among those at diverse positions within the corporate unit structure will rely upon formal authority and prestige to guide the flow of the encounter ; 2. encounters among those at similar or structurally equivalent positions will use both positional authority/prestige and diffuse status characteristics to guide the flow of the encounter, even when these positions are not directly connected ; 3 . encounters among those at the same level in a formal, hierarchical structure will reveal relatively high homophily among participants and density of ties and, hence, will use a higher ratio of diffuse status characteristics and informally generated prestige to guide the flow of the encounter . B . The larger a corporate unit, the more formal and hierarchical is the structure of this unit, and hence, the less dense are ties across all positions, thereby increasing the likelihood that all three processes delineated in 11-A will be operative . III . The less categoric distinctions in an encounter are structured by corporate units, the more operative are diffuse status characteristics and informally generated authority/prestige on the flow of encounters . A . The more discrete, unambiguous, rank-ordered, and correlated are categoric distinctions, the more operative are diffuse status characteristics on the flow of encounters .
31 2
JONATHAN H . TURNER
B.
C.
The more horizontal is the structure of a corporate unit, the less categoric distinctions are structured by the corporate unit, the more operative are diffuse status characteristics and informally generated positional authority/prestige on the flow of the encounter . The more membership in a corporate or type of corporate unit becomes, itself, a status characteristic in an encounter among those from different corporate units, the more the relative evaluation, prestige, and power of the corporate units will operate as a diffuse status characteristic on the flow of the encounter .
APPENDIX C Cultural Systems and Embeddedness
I . The more an encounter is located within an institutional domain and the corporate units comprising this domain, the greater is the likelihood that the culture of this domain and its corporate units will be used to normatize the encounter . A . The more formal, explicit, and hierarchical the division of labor of the corporate units in which an encounter is embedded, the greater will be the influence of the culture of this corporate unit on normatization . B . The more the division of labor of a corporate unit correlates with categoric unit memberships, the greater will be the influence of the culture of this corporate unit on normatization . II . The more an encounter is composed of members of categoric units, the greater is the likelihood the culture of these categoric units will be used to normatize the encounter . A . The more clear-cut, discrete, and rank-ordered are categoric distinctions, the greater their influence on normatization . B . The more correlated categoric distinctions, the greater their influence on normatization . C . The less correlated are categoric distinctions with the distinctions imposed by the division of labor of a corporate unit in which an encounter is located, the less influential are categoric distinctions on normatization . D . The more an encounter is composed of members of categoric units outside of the division of labor of corporate units, the greater is the influence of categoric distinctions on normatization: 1 . the more clear-cut, discrete, and rank-ordered are categoric distinctions, the more influential are these distinctions on normatization ;
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
2.
3.
313
the more instrumental the activities of members of different categoric units outside the division of labor of a corporate unit, the more influential are categoric distinctions on normatization ; the less instrumental, and the more prolonged interaction among members of diverse categoric units outside of corporate units, the less influential are categoric distinctions on normatization .
APPENDIX D Normatizing and Embeddedness
I . The more an encounter is embedded in corporate and categoric units within institutional domains, the more likely are individuals in the encounter to understand the expectations for communication, framing, ritualizing, categorizing, and feeling ; and conversely, the less embedded is an encounter, the less likely are individuals to understand, at least initially, the expectations for communication, framing, ritualizing, categorizing, and feeling, and as a consequence, the more interpersonal effort they will expend in creating the expectations necessary for a viable encounter . II . The more individuals in an encounter mutually understand expectations for categorizing self, others, and situation, the more likely are they to reach consensus on expectations for selection of appropriate frames, for keying and rekeying frames, and for laminating frames ; and reciprocally, the more they realize expectations for frames as well as keys and rekeys of frames, the more likely are they to sustain categorizations of self, others, and situation . III . The more individuals in an encounter understand expectations for categorizing self, others, and situation, the more likely are they to reach consensus on expectations for forms of verbal and nonverbal gesturing, for reciprocal gesturing, and for negotiation over resources ; and reciprocally, the more they realize expectations for forms of communication, the more likely are they to sustain categorizations of self, others, and situation . IV . The more individuals in an encounter understand expectations for appropriate frames and for forms of verbal and nonverbal gesturing, reciprocal gesturing, and negotiation over resources, the more likely are they to reach consensus on the appropriate rituals for opening, closing, forming, and repairing breaches in an interaction as well as for keying and rekeying frames ; and reciprocally, the more they reach consensus on rituals, the more viable are expectations for frames and, by extension, categorizations and forms of communication . V . The more individuals in an encounter understand expectations for forms of verbal and nonverbal gesturing, reciprocal gesturing, and negotiation over
314
JONATHAN H . TURNER
resources, the more likely are they to reach consensus on the appropriate frames and rituals ; and the more they reach consensus on frames and the rituals used to sustain them, the more clear-cut are expectations for communication . VI . The more individuals in an encounter understand expectations for forms of verbal and nonverbal gesturing and for rituals used in opening, closing, forming, repairing, keying, and rekeying of frames, the more likely are they to reach consensus on the appropriate feelings to be experienced and expressed . VII. The more individuals in an encounter understand expectations for the feelings to be experienced and expressed, the more likely are they to sustain consensus over forms of communication as well as the frames, rituals, and categories that are sustained by communication .
APPENDIX E Need States and Embeddedness
I . The more an encounter is embedded in corporate and categoric units within institutional domains, the more likely are individuals to normatize the encounter, and as a consequence, the more likely are needs for self-confirmation, profitable exchange payoffs, predictability and trust, and group inclusion to be met ; and reciprocally, the more these need states are met, the more likely are individuals to experience positive emotions and to become committed to sustaining normatization processes . II . The more an encounter is embedded in corporate and categoric units within institutional domains, and the more needs for self-confirmation, profitable exchange payoffs, predictability and trust, and group inclusion are met, the more likely are individuals to experience positive emotions toward, and commitments to, corporate and categoric units, and hence, the more firmly embedded will the encounter become ; and conversely, the less need states are met, the more likely are individuals to experience negative emotions toward, and commitments to, corporate and categoric units, and hence, the more likely is the encounter to break apart or be re-normatized in ways that reduce its level of embeddedness . III . The more persistently and widespread are problems with normatization across all encounters within corporate and categoric units, the more likely is either the breakup, inviability, or re-normatization to change the structure of categoric and corporate units ; and the more these units are changed, the more likely are the institutional domains in which corporate and categoric units are embedded to undergo transformation .
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
315
IV . The less an encounter is embedded in corporate and categoric units within institutional domains, or the more corporate and categoric units within institutional domains are changing, the more difficult is normatization and the less likely are some needs for self-confirmation, profitable exchange payoffs, predictability and trust, and group inclusion to be met ; and reciprocally, the less these need states are met, the more individuals will experience negative emotions and the more difficult will normatization become, and hence, the more stained and problematic will be efforts to sustain the flow of interaction in the encounter .
APPENDIX F Self-confirmation and Embeddedness 1 . The more expectations for self-confirmation are met or exceeded, the more positive are the emotions experienced by individuals and the more likely is an encounter to be normatized, and hence, the more viable is the encounter ; and conversely, the less expectations for self-confirmation are met, the more negative are the emotions experienced by individuals and the less likely is the encounter to be normatized, and hence, the less viable is the encounter . A . The more individuals perceive their own competence as causing confirming responses from others, the greater is their sense of pride ; and conversely, the more they see their own incompetence as causing disconfirming responses from others, the greater is their sense of shame, and the more persistent this experience of shame, the more likely are individuals to become chronically depressed, punctuated by outburst of anger that only heighten the sense of incompetence . B . The more individuals perceive their ability to meet expectations of cultural values, beliefs, and norms as causing confirming responses from others, the greater is their sense of pride ; and conversely, the more they see the failure to meet expectations as their own fault, the greater is their sense of guilt, and the more persistence the sense of guilt, the more likely are individuals to become chronically depressed punctuated by outbursts of anger that only heighten their sense of having violated expectations . C . The more individuals perceive that others are the cause of confirming responses, the more positive their emotions toward these others ; and conversely, the more individuals blame others for the lack of confirming responses, the greater is their sense of anger toward these others and the more likely are feeling rules to be violated .
316
JONATHAN H . TURNER
D . The more individuals perceive conditions in the corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded as causing confirming responses from others, the more likely are they to experience low-intensity positive emotions toward others in this setting and the more positive will be their sentiments about, and commitments to, corporate and categoric units in which the encounter is embedded ; and conversely, the more conditions in the broader setting are perceived as the cause of disconfirming responses, the less intense is the anger toward others and the more negative will their sentiments about, and commitments to, corporate and categoric units in which the encounter is embedded . E . The more individuals perceive conditions in the corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded as causing the confirming responses of others, the more positive their emotions toward, and commitments to, these corporate and categoric units, and hence, the more firmly embedded is the encounter .
APPENDIX G Exchange Payoffs and Embeddedness
I . The more individuals in an encounter can accurately perceive the available resources and the costs in securing these resources, the more likely are they to adjust their expectations and behaviors in order to receive an excess of rewards to costs, and the more exchange payoffs exceed costs or expectations for payoffs, the more positive are the emotions experienced by individuals, and hence, the more likely are individuals to remain committed to the encounter ; and conversely, the more exchange payoffs do not exceed actual costs or expectations for payoffs, the more individuals experience anger, and hence, the less likely are individuals to remain committed to the encounter. A . The more clear-cut are the demography, the distribution of positional authority and prestige, and the salience of diffuse status characteristics in an encounter, the more likely are individuals to accurately perceive the available resources and the costs in securing these resources, and the more likely are their expectations for payoffs to correspond to likely exchange outcomes. B . The more an encounter is normatized, the more likely are individuals to accurately perceive the available resources and the costs in securing these resources, and the more likely are their expectations for payoffs to correspond to likely exchange outcomes .
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
31 7
C.
The more an encounter is normatized, the more likely are rules of justice to be operative, and the more salient rules of justice, the more likely are exchange payoffs to be proportional to the costs and investments in securing these payoffs . II . The more individuals in an encounter receive expected payoffs or payoffs in accordance with rules of justice, the greater are their positive emotions toward those corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded ; and conversely, the more individuals do not receive expected payoffs or payoffs in accordance with rules of justice, the greater is their anger toward, and the less are their commitments to, those corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded . III . The greater the number of individuals across all encounters within categoric and corporate units who fail to receive expected payoffs in accordance with rules of justice, and the more persistent this failure, the more likely are individuals to seek to change the structure and culture of the corporate and categoric units in which encounters are embedded .
APPENDIX H Predictability/Trust and Embeddedness I . The more individuals in an encounter can perceive that the behaviors of others are predictable and that others can be trusted to behave as expected, the more positive are the emotions experienced by individuals, and hence, the more likely are individuals to remain committed to the encounter ; and conversely, the more individuals fail to perceive that the behaviors of others are predictable and that others can be trusted to behave as expected, the greater is their anxiety, and, if exchange payoffs and self-confirmation are also diminished by the lack of predictability and trust, the greater is their level of anger as well . A . The more clear-cut the demography, the distribution of positional authority and prestige, and the salience of diffuse status characteristics in an encounter, the more predictable are the behaviors of individuals, and the more likely are individuals to be trusted to behave as expected . B . The more an encounter is normatized, the more likely are the behaviors of others to be predictable, and the more likely are individuals to be trusted to behave as expected . II . The more predictable the behaviors of others and the more they are trusted to behave as expected across all encounters, the more positive are their emotions toward, and the greater are the commitments to, the corporate and categoric units in which the encounter is embedded ; and conversely, the less predictable and the less trustworthy the responses of others across all
31 8
JONATHAN H . TURNER
encounters, the more negative are the emotions toward, and the less are the commitments to, the corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded. III . The greater is the number of individuals across all encounters who experience unpredictability and question the trustworthiness of others, and the more persistent this experience, the more likely are individuals to change the structure and culture of the corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded .
APPENDIX I Intersubjectivity and Embeddedness
I . The more individuals in an encounter perceive that others are experiencing the situation in similar ways or that differences in experiences are accountable (intersubjectivity), the more positive the emotions aroused in individuals, and hence, the more likely are they to remain committed to the encounter; and conversely, the less individuals experience intersubjectivity, the greater is their anxiety and, if the loss of intersubjectivity is unexpected or sudden, the greater is anger as well . A . The more clear-cut the demography, the distribution of positional authority and prestige, and the salience of diffuse status characteristics in an encounter, the more likely are individuals to experience intersubjectivity . B . The more an encounter is normatized, the more likely are individuals to experience intersubjectivity . II . The more individuals experience intersubjectivity across all encounters, the more positive are their emotions toward, and the greater are their commitments to, the corporate and categoric units in which the encounter is embedded ; and conversely, the less intersubjectivity is experienced, the more persistent this failure to achieve intersubjectivity, the greater is the anxiety and/or anger aroused in individuals, and the more negative are their emotions toward, and their commitments to, the corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded . III . The greater is the number of individuals across all encounters failing to achieve intersubjectivity, and the more persistent this experience, the more likely are individuals to change the structure and culture of corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded .
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
319
APPENDIX ) Group Inclusion and Embeddedness I. The more individuals in an encounter experience a sense of being involved in the ongoing flow of interaction (group inclusion), the more positive are their sentiments toward others in the encounter, the more likely are they to remain committed to the encounter; conversely, the less individuals experience a sense of group inclusion, the greater is their anxiety and, if their exclusion has been deliberate, the greater is their anger as well . A . The more clear-cut the demography, the distribution of positional authority and prestige, and the salience of diffuse status characteristics, the more likely are individuals to experience a sense of group inclusion . B . The more an encounter is normatized, the more likely are individuals to experience a sense of group inclusion . II . The more individuals experience a sense of group inclusion across all encounters, the more positive are their emotions toward, and the greater their commitments to, the corporate and categoric units in which the encounter is embedded ; and conversely, the less a sense of group inclusion has been achieved, and the more persistent this failure to sense group inclusion, the greater is the anxiety/anger aroused in individuals, and the more negative are their emotions toward, and their commitments to, the corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded . III . The greater is the number of individuals across all encounters failing to achieve a sense of group inclusion, and the more persistent this experience, the more likely are individuals to change the structure and culture of the corporate and categoric units in which an encounter is embedded .
NOTES 1 . This section delves into a large literature on status generalization and expectation states . The generalizations below are, I believe, consistent with findings in this literature, but my focus is sufficiently at variance with most studies in this area that I cannot be sure . A recent series of articles appears, to me at least, to be consistent with my generalizations (see Ridgeway et al . 1998 ; Webster and Hysom 1998; Berger et al . 1998 ; see also Wagner and Turner 1998) . 2 . The terms "circumscribe," "constrain," and "select" are vague, but they capture the essence of what occurs . Individuals' range of options are indeed constrained, and within this range they do select what they see as the most appropriate rules of communication, framing, ritualizing, categorizing, and feeling . Only when institutional norms are vague or when an encounter reveals problematic properties does this "selection" become highly conscious . Most of the time it is implicit and unconscious .
320
JONATHAN H . TURNER
3 . Attribution process may also be important in just how angry an individual becomes and whether this anger is directly at self, others, or the situation . 4 . Again, attribution processes may operate here, depending on whether self or others are blamed for non-inclusion . 5 . In this space, individuals may well be involved in unfocused encounters . Thus, one of the big differences between focused and unfocused encounters is that individuals do not need to feel included in the latter; indeed, the whole structure of unfocused interaction is to avoid group inclusion.
REFERENCES Berger, J ., and M. H. Fisek . 1974 . "A Generalization of the Theory of Status Characteristics and Expectation States ." Pp . 163-205 in Expectation States Theory, edited by J . Berger, L . Conner, and M . H. Fisek. Cambridge: Winthrop. Berger, J., C . L. Ridgeway, M . Hamit Fisek, and R . Z . Norman . 1998 . "The Legitimation and Delegitimation of Power and Prestige Orders ." American Sociological Review 63 : 379-405. Berger, J., D . G . Wagner, and M. Zelditch, Jr. 1989. "Theory Growth, Social Processes and Metatheory ." Pp . 19-42 in Theory Building in Sociology, edited by J. H . Turner. Newbury Park, CA : Sage. Berger, J ., and M . Zelditch, Jr . 1998. Status, Power and Legitimacy : Strategies and Theories. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers . Blau, P. M . 1964. Exchange and Power in Social Life . New York : Wiley . Blau, P . M. 1994. Structural Context of Opportunities . Chicago : University of Chicago Press . Blumer, H. 1962 . "Society as Symbolic Interaction ." Pp . 179-92 in Human Behavior and Social Process, edited by A. Rose . Boston : Houghton Mifflin . Bourdieu, P . 1984 . Distinction: A Social Critique of Judgement . Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press. Collins, R. 1975 . Conflict Sociology : Toward An Explanatory Science . New York: Academic Press . Collins, R . 1981 . "On the Micro-Foundation of Macro-Sociology." American Journal of Sociology 86 : 984-1014 . Durkheim, E . 1947 [19121 . The Elementary Forms of Religious Life . New York: Free Press. Erikson, E . 1950 . Childhood and Society . New York : Norton. Fararo, T . 1989 . The Meaning of General Theoretical Sociology. New York : Cambridge University Press . Fararo, T., and J. Skvoretz . 1986. "E-State Structuralism : A Theoretical Method ." American Sociological Review 51 : 591-602 . Garfinkel, H . 1967 . Studies in Ethnomethodology . Englewood Cliffs, NJ : Prentice-Hall . Giddens, A. 1984 . The Constitution of Society. Cambridge, UK : Polity Press . Goffman, E . 1961 . Encounters: Two Studies in the Sociology of Interaction . Indianapolis : Bobbs-Merrill. Goffman, E . 1967 . Interaction Ritual. Garden City, NY : Doubleday. Goffman, E . 1974 . Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience . New York : Harper and Row . Goffman, E . 1983 . "The Interaction Order ." American Sociological Review 48 : 1-17 . Granovetter, M . 1985 . "Economic Action and Social Structure : The Problem of Embeddedness ." American Journal of Sociology 91 : 481-510. Hawley, A . 1986 . Human Ecology : A Theoretical Essay . Chicago : University of Chicago Press . Hochschild, A. 1979 . "Emotion Work, Feeling Rules, and Social Structure ." American Journal of Sociology 85 : 551-75 . Homans, G . C . 1961 . Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms. New York : Harcourt Brace Jovanovich .
A Theory of Embedded Encounters
321
Lawler, E . J . 1992 . "Affective Attachments to Nested Groups : A Choice-Process Theory ." American Sociological Review 57 : 327-39 . Lawler, E . J . 1997 . "Affective Attachments to Nested Groups : The Role of Rational Choice Processes ." Pp . 387-403 in Status Generalization: New Theory and Research . Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Lewis, H . B . 1971 . Shame and Guilt in Neurosis . New York: International Universities Press . Markovsky, B . 1988 . "From Expectation States to Macro Processes ." Pp. 351-65 in Status Generalization: New Theory and Research . Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Markovsky, B . 1997. "Building and Testing Multilevel Theories ." Pp. 13-28 in Status, Network and Structure, edited by J . Szmatka, J. Skvoretz, and J . Berger. Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Mayhew, B . 1984 . "Baseline Models of Sociological Phenomena ." Journal of Mathematical Sociology 9 : 259-81 . Noah, M . 1998 . "Beyond Individual Differences : Social Differentiation from First Principles ." American Sociological Review 63 : 309-30 . Parsons, T . 1937 . The Structure of Social Action . New York : McGraw-Hill . Parsons, T . 1951 . The Social System . New York : The Free Press . Parsons, T. 1966 . Societies: Evolutionary and Comparative Perspectives . Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall . Ridgeway, C . L . 1982. "Status in Groups : The Importance of Emotion ." American Sociological Review 47 : 76-88 . Ridgeway, C . L. 1991 . "The Social Construction of Status Value : Gender and Other Nominal Characteristics ." Social Forces 70 : 367-86 . Ridgeway, C . L . 1994 . "Affect ." Pp . 205-20 in Group Processes: Sociological Analysis, edited by M . Foschi and E . Lawler . Chicago, IL : Nelson-Hall. Ridgeway, C . L . 1998 . "Where Do Status Beliefs Come From?" Pp . 137-58 in Status, Network and Structure, edited by J . Szmatka, J . Skvoretz, and J. Berger. Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Ridgeway, C ., and J. Berger. 1986 . "Expectations, Legitimation, and Dominance Behavior in Task Groups." American Sociological Review 51 : 603-17 . Ridgeway, C ., E . H . Boyle, K . J . Kuipers, and D . T. Robinson . 1998 . "How Do Status Differences Develop? The Role of Resources and Interactional Experiences ." American Sociological Review 63 : 331-50 . Sailer, L. D . 1978 . "Structural Equivalence ." Social Networks 1 : 73-90 . Scheff, T . 1988 . "Shame and Conformity : The Deference-Emotion System ." American Sociological Review 53 : 395-406 . Scheff, T . 1990 . "Socialization of Emotion: Pride and Shame as Causal Agents ." Pp . 281-304 in Research Agendas in the Sociology of Emotions . Albany, NY : SUNY Press . Schutz, A . 1967 [1932] . The Phenomenology of the Social World . Evanston, IL : Northwestern University Press . Shibutani, T . 1986. Social Processes : An Introduction to Sociology . Berkeley : University of California Press. Stryker, S . 1980 . Symbolic Interactionism : A Structural Version . Menlo Park, CA : Benjamin-Cummings . Turner, J . H . 1987. "Toward a Sociological Theory of Motivation ." American Sociological Review 52: 15-27 . Turner, J . H. 1988 . A Theory of Social Interaction . Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Turner, J . H . 1989 . "A Theory of Microdynamics ." Pp . 1-26 in Advances in Group Processes, Vol . 6, edited by E . Lawler. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press . Turner, J . H . 1994. "A General Theory of Motivation and Emotion in Human Interaction ." Osterreichische Zeitschrift fur Soziologie 8 : 20-35 .
322
JONATHAN H . TURNER
Turner, J . H. 1995 . Macrodynamics: Toward a Theory on the Organization of Human Populations . New Brunswick, NJ : Rutgers University Press . Turner, J . H . 1996 . "Cognition, Emotion and Interaction in the Big-brained Primate ." Pp. 295-315 in Social Processes and Human Relations, edited by K. M . Kwan. Greenwich, CT : JAI Press . Turner, J . H. 1997 . "The Nature of Dynamics of `The Social' among Humans ." Pp. 105-32 in The Mark of the Social, edited by J . D . Greenwood . New York : Rowman and Littlefield. Turner, J . H . 1999 . "Toward a General Sociological Theory of Emotions ." Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 29 : 133-62. Turner, R. 1968 . "Social Roles : Sociological Aspects." In International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. New York: Macmillan . Wagner, D . G., and J . Berger . 1993 . "Status Characteristics Theory : The Growth of a Program ." Pp . 23-63 in Theoretical Research Programs : Studies in the Growth of Theory, edited by J . Berger and M. Zelditch, Jr. Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press. Wagner, D., and J . H . Turner. 1998 . "Expectation States Theories ." Pp. 452-65 in The Structure of Sociological Theory, edited by J . H. Turner. Belmont, CA : Wadsworth . Weber, M. 1958 [1904/05] . The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism . New York : Scribners. Webster, M . A., Jr ., and M . Foschi, eds. 1988 . Status Generalization : New Theory and Research . Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press . Webster, M ., and S . J. Hysom . 1998 . "Creating Status Characteristics." American Sociological Review 63 : 351-78 . White, H ., S . A . Boorman, and R. L . Breiger. 1976 . "Social Structure from Multiple Networks : I . Block Models of Roles and Positions ." American Journal of Sociology 81 : 730-80. Wuthnow, R . 1987 . Meaning and Moral Order: Explorations in Cultural Analysis . Berkeley : University of California Press .